author | Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de> |
Tue, 23 Mar 2010 13:07:02 +0100 | |
changeset 1613 | 98b53cd05deb |
parent 1612 | c8c9b3b7189a |
child 1617 | 99cee15cb5ff |
permissions | -rw-r--r-- |
754
b85875d65b10
added a paper for possible notes
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
diff
changeset
|
1 |
(*<*) |
b85875d65b10
added a paper for possible notes
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
diff
changeset
|
2 |
theory Paper |
1506
7c607df46a0a
slightly more in the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1493
diff
changeset
|
3 |
imports "../Nominal/Test" "LaTeXsugar" |
754
b85875d65b10
added a paper for possible notes
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
diff
changeset
|
4 |
begin |
1493
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
5 |
|
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
6 |
notation (latex output) |
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
7 |
swap ("'(_ _')" [1000, 1000] 1000) and |
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
8 |
fresh ("_ # _" [51, 51] 50) and |
1506
7c607df46a0a
slightly more in the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1493
diff
changeset
|
9 |
fresh_star ("_ #* _" [51, 51] 50) and |
1493
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
10 |
supp ("supp _" [78] 73) and |
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
11 |
uminus ("-_" [78] 73) and |
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
12 |
If ("if _ then _ else _" 10) |
754
b85875d65b10
added a paper for possible notes
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
diff
changeset
|
13 |
(*>*) |
b85875d65b10
added a paper for possible notes
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
diff
changeset
|
14 |
|
b85875d65b10
added a paper for possible notes
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
diff
changeset
|
15 |
section {* Introduction *} |
b85875d65b10
added a paper for possible notes
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
diff
changeset
|
16 |
|
b85875d65b10
added a paper for possible notes
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
diff
changeset
|
17 |
text {* |
1524 | 18 |
So far, Nominal Isabelle provides a mechanism for constructing |
1607 | 19 |
alpha-equated terms, for example |
1485
c004e7448dca
temporarily disabled tests in Nominal/ROOT
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1484
diff
changeset
|
20 |
|
1520
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
21 |
\begin{center} |
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
22 |
$t ::= x \mid t\;t \mid \lambda x. t$ |
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
23 |
\end{center} |
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
24 |
|
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
25 |
\noindent |
1550 | 26 |
where free and bound variables have names. For such terms Nominal Isabelle |
1607 | 27 |
derives automatically a reasoning infrastructure that has been used |
1550 | 28 |
successfully in formalisations of an equivalence checking algorithm for LF |
29 |
\cite{UrbanCheneyBerghofer08}, Typed |
|
1520
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
30 |
Scheme~\cite{TobinHochstadtFelleisen08}, several calculi for concurrency |
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
31 |
\cite{BengtsonParrow07,BengtsonParow09} and a strong normalisation result |
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
32 |
for cut-elimination in classical logic \cite{UrbanZhu08}. It has also been |
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
33 |
used by Pollack for formalisations in the locally-nameless approach to |
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
34 |
binding \cite{SatoPollack10}. |
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
35 |
|
1535
a37c65fe10de
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1528
diff
changeset
|
36 |
However, Nominal Isabelle has fared less well in a formalisation of |
1524 | 37 |
the algorithm W \cite{UrbanNipkow09}, where types and type-schemes |
38 |
are of the form |
|
1570 | 39 |
% |
40 |
\begin{equation}\label{tysch} |
|
41 |
\begin{array}{l} |
|
42 |
T ::= x \mid T \rightarrow T \hspace{5mm} S ::= \forall \{x_1,\ldots, x_n\}. T |
|
43 |
\end{array} |
|
44 |
\end{equation} |
|
1520
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
45 |
|
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
46 |
\noindent |
1566 | 47 |
and the quantification $\forall$ binds a finite (possibly empty) set of |
1550 | 48 |
type-variables. While it is possible to implement this kind of more general |
49 |
binders by iterating single binders, this leads to a rather clumsy |
|
50 |
formalisation of W. The need of iterating single binders is also one reason |
|
51 |
why Nominal Isabelle and similar theorem provers that only provide |
|
52 |
mechanisms for binding single variables have not fared extremely well with the |
|
53 |
more advanced tasks in the POPLmark challenge \cite{challenge05}, because |
|
54 |
also there one would like to bind multiple variables at once. |
|
1520
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
55 |
|
1577 | 56 |
Binding multiple variables has interesting properties that cannot be captured |
1587 | 57 |
easily by iterating single binders. For example in case of type-schemes we do not |
58 |
want to make a distinction about the order of the bound variables. Therefore |
|
1550 | 59 |
we would like to regard the following two type-schemes as alpha-equivalent |
1572 | 60 |
% |
61 |
\begin{equation}\label{ex1} |
|
62 |
\forall \{x, y\}. x \rightarrow y \;\approx_\alpha\; \forall \{y, x\}. y \rightarrow x |
|
63 |
\end{equation} |
|
1520
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
64 |
|
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
65 |
\noindent |
1587 | 66 |
but assuming that $x$, $y$ and $z$ are distinct variables, |
67 |
the following two should \emph{not} be alpha-equivalent |
|
1572 | 68 |
% |
69 |
\begin{equation}\label{ex2} |
|
70 |
\forall \{x, y\}. x \rightarrow y \;\not\approx_\alpha\; \forall \{z\}. z \rightarrow z |
|
71 |
\end{equation} |
|
1520
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
72 |
|
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
73 |
\noindent |
1587 | 74 |
Moreover, we like to regard type-schemes as |
1524 | 75 |
alpha-equivalent, if they differ only on \emph{vacuous} binders, such as |
1572 | 76 |
% |
77 |
\begin{equation}\label{ex3} |
|
78 |
\forall \{x\}. x \rightarrow y \;\approx_\alpha\; \forall \{x, z\}. x \rightarrow y |
|
79 |
\end{equation} |
|
1485
c004e7448dca
temporarily disabled tests in Nominal/ROOT
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1484
diff
changeset
|
80 |
|
1520
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
81 |
\noindent |
1535
a37c65fe10de
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1528
diff
changeset
|
82 |
where $z$ does not occur freely in the type. |
1545 | 83 |
In this paper we will give a general binding mechanism and associated |
1524 | 84 |
notion of alpha-equivalence that can be used to faithfully represent |
1545 | 85 |
this kind of binding in Nominal Isabelle. The difficulty of finding the right notion |
1607 | 86 |
for alpha-equivalence can be appreciated in this case by considering that the |
1524 | 87 |
definition given by Leroy in \cite{Leroy92} is incorrect (it omits a side-condition). |
88 |
||
1520
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
89 |
However, the notion of alpha-equivalence that is preserved by vacuous binders is not |
1566 | 90 |
always wanted. For example in terms like |
1587 | 91 |
% |
1535
a37c65fe10de
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1528
diff
changeset
|
92 |
\begin{equation}\label{one} |
1550 | 93 |
\LET x = 3 \AND y = 2 \IN x\,-\,y \END |
1535
a37c65fe10de
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1528
diff
changeset
|
94 |
\end{equation} |
1520
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
95 |
|
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
96 |
\noindent |
1524 | 97 |
we might not care in which order the assignments $x = 3$ and $y = 2$ are |
1535
a37c65fe10de
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1528
diff
changeset
|
98 |
given, but it would be unusual to regard \eqref{one} as alpha-equivalent |
1524 | 99 |
with |
1587 | 100 |
% |
1520
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
101 |
\begin{center} |
1550 | 102 |
$\LET x = 3 \AND y = 2 \AND z = loop \IN x\,-\,y \END$ |
1520
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
103 |
\end{center} |
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
104 |
|
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
105 |
\noindent |
1550 | 106 |
Therefore we will also provide a separate binding mechanism for cases in |
107 |
which the order of binders does not matter, but the ``cardinality'' of the |
|
1535
a37c65fe10de
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1528
diff
changeset
|
108 |
binders has to agree. |
1520
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
109 |
|
1550 | 110 |
However, we found that this is still not sufficient for dealing with |
111 |
language constructs frequently occurring in programming language |
|
112 |
research. For example in $\mathtt{let}$s containing patterns |
|
1587 | 113 |
% |
1535
a37c65fe10de
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1528
diff
changeset
|
114 |
\begin{equation}\label{two} |
1550 | 115 |
\LET (x, y) = (3, 2) \IN x\,-\,y \END |
1535
a37c65fe10de
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1528
diff
changeset
|
116 |
\end{equation} |
1520
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
117 |
|
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
118 |
\noindent |
1535
a37c65fe10de
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1528
diff
changeset
|
119 |
we want to bind all variables from the pattern inside the body of the |
a37c65fe10de
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1528
diff
changeset
|
120 |
$\mathtt{let}$, but we also care about the order of these variables, since |
1566 | 121 |
we do not want to regard \eqref{two} as alpha-equivalent with |
1587 | 122 |
% |
1520
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
123 |
\begin{center} |
1550 | 124 |
$\LET (y, x) = (3, 2) \IN x\,- y\,\END$ |
1520
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
125 |
\end{center} |
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
126 |
|
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
127 |
\noindent |
1545 | 128 |
As a result, we provide three general binding mechanisms each of which binds multiple |
1566 | 129 |
variables at once, and let the user chose which one is intended when formalising a |
1524 | 130 |
programming language calculus. |
1485
c004e7448dca
temporarily disabled tests in Nominal/ROOT
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1484
diff
changeset
|
131 |
|
1545 | 132 |
By providing these general binding mechanisms, however, we have to work around |
1524 | 133 |
a problem that has been pointed out by Pottier in \cite{Pottier06}: in |
134 |
$\mathtt{let}$-constructs of the form |
|
1587 | 135 |
% |
1520
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
136 |
\begin{center} |
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
137 |
$\LET x_1 = t_1 \AND \ldots \AND x_n = t_n \IN s \END$ |
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
138 |
\end{center} |
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
139 |
|
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
140 |
\noindent |
1524 | 141 |
which bind all the $x_i$ in $s$, we might not care about the order in |
1520
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
142 |
which the $x_i = t_i$ are given, but we do care about the information that there are |
1524 | 143 |
as many $x_i$ as there are $t_i$. We lose this information if we represent the |
1550 | 144 |
$\mathtt{let}$-constructor by something like |
1587 | 145 |
% |
1523
eb95360d6ac6
another little bit for the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1520
diff
changeset
|
146 |
\begin{center} |
1524 | 147 |
$\LET [x_1,\ldots,x_n].s\;\; [t_1,\ldots,t_n]$ |
1523
eb95360d6ac6
another little bit for the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1520
diff
changeset
|
148 |
\end{center} |
1520
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
149 |
|
1523
eb95360d6ac6
another little bit for the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1520
diff
changeset
|
150 |
\noindent |
1566 | 151 |
where the notation $[\_\!\_].\_\!\_$ indicates that the $x_i$ become bound |
152 |
in $s$. In this representation the term \mbox{$\LET [x].s\;\;[t_1,t_2]$} |
|
153 |
would be a perfectly legal instance. To exclude such terms an additional |
|
154 |
predicate about well-formed terms is needed in order to ensure that the two |
|
155 |
lists are of equal length. This can result into very messy reasoning (see |
|
1577 | 156 |
for example~\cite{BengtsonParow09}). To avoid this, we will allow type specifications |
1566 | 157 |
for $\mathtt{let}$s as follows |
1587 | 158 |
% |
1528
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
159 |
\begin{center} |
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
160 |
\begin{tabular}{r@ {\hspace{2mm}}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l} |
1570 | 161 |
$trm$ & $::=$ & \ldots\\ |
1545 | 162 |
& $\mid$ & $\mathtt{let}\;a\!::\!assn\;\;s\!::\!trm\quad\mathtt{bind}\;bn\,(a) \IN s$\\[1mm] |
1570 | 163 |
$assn$ & $::=$ & $\mathtt{anil}$\\ |
1528
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
164 |
& $\mid$ & $\mathtt{acons}\;\;name\;\;trm\;\;assn$ |
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
165 |
\end{tabular} |
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
166 |
\end{center} |
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
167 |
|
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
168 |
\noindent |
1577 | 169 |
where $assn$ is an auxiliary type representing a list of assignments |
1545 | 170 |
and $bn$ an auxiliary function identifying the variables to be bound by |
1566 | 171 |
the $\mathtt{let}$. This function is defined by recursion over $assn$ as follows |
1528
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
172 |
|
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
173 |
\begin{center} |
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
174 |
$bn\,(\mathtt{anil}) = \varnothing \qquad bn\,(\mathtt{acons}\;x\;t\;as) = \{x\} \cup bn\,(as)$ |
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
175 |
\end{center} |
1523
eb95360d6ac6
another little bit for the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1520
diff
changeset
|
176 |
|
1528
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
177 |
\noindent |
1550 | 178 |
The scope of the binding is indicated by labels given to the types, for |
179 |
example \mbox{$s\!::\!trm$}, and a binding clause, in this case |
|
1577 | 180 |
$\mathtt{bind}\;bn\,(a) \IN s$, that states to bind in $s$ all the names the |
1607 | 181 |
function call $bn\,(a)$ returns. This style of specifying terms and bindings is |
1577 | 182 |
heavily inspired by the syntax of the Ott-tool \cite{ott-jfp}. |
1528
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
183 |
|
1545 | 184 |
However, we will not be able to deal with all specifications that are |
1570 | 185 |
allowed by Ott. One reason is that Ott allows ``empty'' specifications |
186 |
like |
|
187 |
||
188 |
\begin{center} |
|
189 |
$t ::= t\;t \mid \lambda x. t$ |
|
190 |
\end{center} |
|
191 |
||
192 |
\noindent |
|
1577 | 193 |
where no clause for variables is given. Such specifications make some sense in |
1607 | 194 |
the context of Coq's type theory (which Ott supports), but not at all in a HOL-based |
195 |
environment where every datatype must have a non-empty set-theoretic model. |
|
1570 | 196 |
|
197 |
Another reason is that we establish the reasoning infrastructure |
|
198 |
for alpha-\emph{equated} terms. In contrast, Ott produces a reasoning |
|
199 |
infrastructure in Isabelle/HOL for |
|
1545 | 200 |
\emph{non}-alpha-equated, or ``raw'', terms. While our alpha-equated terms |
1556 | 201 |
and the raw terms produced by Ott use names for bound variables, |
1545 | 202 |
there is a key difference: working with alpha-equated terms means that the |
203 |
two type-schemes with $x$, $y$ and $z$ being distinct |
|
1528
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
204 |
|
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
205 |
\begin{center} |
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
206 |
$\forall \{x\}. x \rightarrow y \;=\; \forall \{x, z\}. x \rightarrow y$ |
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
207 |
\end{center} |
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
208 |
|
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
209 |
\noindent |
1550 | 210 |
are not just alpha-equal, but actually equal. As a |
211 |
result, we can only support specifications that make sense on the level of |
|
212 |
alpha-equated terms (offending specifications, which for example bind a variable |
|
1556 | 213 |
according to a variable bound somewhere else, are not excluded by Ott, but we |
214 |
have to). Our |
|
1550 | 215 |
insistence on reasoning with alpha-equated terms comes from the wealth of |
216 |
experience we gained with the older version of Nominal Isabelle: for |
|
217 |
non-trivial properties, reasoning about alpha-equated terms is much easier |
|
1556 | 218 |
than reasoning with raw terms. The fundamental reason for this is that the |
1550 | 219 |
HOL-logic underlying Nominal Isabelle allows us to replace |
220 |
``equals-by-equals''. In contrast replacing ``alpha-equals-by-alpha-equals'' |
|
221 |
in a representation based on raw terms requires a lot of extra reasoning work. |
|
1535
a37c65fe10de
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1528
diff
changeset
|
222 |
|
a37c65fe10de
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1528
diff
changeset
|
223 |
Although in informal settings a reasoning infrastructure for alpha-equated |
1607 | 224 |
terms is nearly always taken for granted, establishing |
1550 | 225 |
it automatically in the Isabelle/HOL theorem prover is a rather non-trivial task. |
1535
a37c65fe10de
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1528
diff
changeset
|
226 |
For every specification we will need to construct a type containing as |
1556 | 227 |
elements the alpha-equated terms. To do so, we use |
1535
a37c65fe10de
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1528
diff
changeset
|
228 |
the standard HOL-technique of defining a new type by |
1556 | 229 |
identifying a non-empty subset of an existing type. The construction we |
1607 | 230 |
perform in HOL can be illustrated by the following picture: |
1545 | 231 |
|
1528
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
232 |
\begin{center} |
1552 | 233 |
\begin{tikzpicture} |
234 |
%\draw[step=2mm] (-4,-1) grid (4,1); |
|
235 |
||
236 |
\draw[very thick] (0.7,0.4) circle (4.25mm); |
|
237 |
\draw[rounded corners=1mm, very thick] ( 0.0,-0.8) rectangle ( 1.8, 0.9); |
|
238 |
\draw[rounded corners=1mm, very thick] (-1.95,0.85) rectangle (-2.85,-0.05); |
|
239 |
||
240 |
\draw (-2.0, 0.845) -- (0.7,0.845); |
|
241 |
\draw (-2.0,-0.045) -- (0.7,-0.045); |
|
242 |
||
243 |
\draw ( 0.7, 0.4) node {\begin{tabular}{@ {}c@ {}}$\alpha$-\\[-1mm]clas.\end{tabular}}; |
|
244 |
\draw (-2.4, 0.4) node {\begin{tabular}{@ {}c@ {}}$\alpha$-eq.\\[-1mm]terms\end{tabular}}; |
|
245 |
\draw (1.8, 0.48) node[right=-0.1mm] |
|
246 |
{\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}}existing\\[-1mm] type\\ (sets of raw terms)\end{tabular}}; |
|
247 |
\draw (0.9, -0.35) node {\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}}non-empty\\[-1mm]subset\end{tabular}}; |
|
248 |
\draw (-3.25, 0.55) node {\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}}new\\[-1mm]type\end{tabular}}; |
|
249 |
||
250 |
\draw[<->, very thick] (-1.8, 0.3) -- (-0.1,0.3); |
|
251 |
\draw (-0.95, 0.3) node[above=0mm] {isomorphism}; |
|
252 |
||
253 |
\end{tikzpicture} |
|
1528
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
254 |
\end{center} |
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
255 |
|
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
256 |
\noindent |
1577 | 257 |
We take as the starting point a definition of raw terms (defined as a |
1556 | 258 |
datatype in Isabelle/HOL); identify then the |
1607 | 259 |
alpha-equivalence classes in the type of sets of raw terms according to our |
1556 | 260 |
alpha-equivalence relation and finally define the new type as these |
261 |
alpha-equivalence classes (non-emptiness is satisfied whenever the raw terms are |
|
1607 | 262 |
definable as datatype in Isabelle/HOL and the fact that our relation for |
263 |
alpha-equivalence is indeed an equivalence relation). |
|
1556 | 264 |
|
1607 | 265 |
The fact that we obtain an isomorphism between the new type and the non-empty |
1556 | 266 |
subset shows that the new type is a faithful representation of alpha-equated terms. |
1577 | 267 |
That is not the case for example in the representation of terms using the locally |
1607 | 268 |
nameless representation of binders \cite{McKinnaPollack99}: in this representation |
269 |
there are ``junk'' terms that need to |
|
1556 | 270 |
be excluded by reasoning about a well-formedness predicate. |
271 |
||
1577 | 272 |
The problem with introducing a new type in Isabelle/HOL is that in order to be useful, |
1572 | 273 |
a reasoning infrastructure needs to be ``lifted'' from the underlying subset to |
1607 | 274 |
the new type. This is usually a tricky and arduous task. To ease it, |
1577 | 275 |
we re-implemented in Isabelle/HOL the quotient package described by Homeier |
276 |
\cite{Homeier05}. This package |
|
277 |
allows us to lift definitions and theorems involving raw terms |
|
1607 | 278 |
to definitions and theorems involving alpha-equated, terms. For example |
1577 | 279 |
if we define the free-variable function over lambda terms |
280 |
||
281 |
\begin{center} |
|
282 |
$\fv(x) = \{x\}$\hspace{10mm} |
|
283 |
$\fv(t_1\;t_2) = \fv(t_1) \cup \fv(t_2)$\\[1mm] |
|
284 |
$\fv(\lambda x.t) = \fv(t) - \{x\}$ |
|
285 |
\end{center} |
|
286 |
||
287 |
\noindent |
|
288 |
then with not too great effort we obtain a function $\fv_\alpha$ |
|
289 |
operating on quotients, or alpha-equivalence classes of terms, as follows |
|
290 |
||
291 |
\begin{center} |
|
292 |
$\fv_\alpha(x) = \{x\}$\hspace{10mm} |
|
293 |
$\fv_\alpha(t_1\;t_2) = \fv_\alpha(t_1) \cup \fv_\alpha(t_2)$\\[1mm] |
|
294 |
$\fv_\alpha(\lambda x.t) = \fv_\alpha(t) - \{x\}$ |
|
295 |
\end{center} |
|
296 |
||
297 |
\noindent |
|
298 |
(Note that this means also the term-constructors for variables, applications |
|
299 |
and lambda are lifted to the quotient level.) This construction, of course, |
|
1607 | 300 |
only works if alpha-equivalence is an equivalence relation, and the |
301 |
definitions and theorems are respectful w.r.t.~alpha-equivalence. Hence we |
|
302 |
will not be able to lift a bound-variable function to alpha-equated terms |
|
303 |
(since it does not respect alpha-equivalence). To sum up, every lifting of |
|
304 |
theorems to the quotient level needs proofs of some respectfulness |
|
305 |
properties. In the paper we show that we are able to automate these |
|
306 |
proofs and therefore can establish a reasoning infrastructure for |
|
307 |
alpha-equated terms.\medskip |
|
1577 | 308 |
|
1506
7c607df46a0a
slightly more in the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1493
diff
changeset
|
309 |
|
1528
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
310 |
\noindent |
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
311 |
{\bf Contributions:} We provide new definitions for when terms |
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
312 |
involving multiple binders are alpha-equivalent. These definitions are |
1607 | 313 |
inspired by earlier work of Pitts \cite{Pitts04}. By means of automatic |
1528
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
314 |
proofs, we establish a reasoning infrastructure for alpha-equated |
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
315 |
terms, including properties about support, freshness and equality |
1607 | 316 |
conditions for alpha-equated terms. We are also able to derive, at the moment |
317 |
only manually, strong induction principles that |
|
318 |
have the variable convention already built in. |
|
1485
c004e7448dca
temporarily disabled tests in Nominal/ROOT
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1484
diff
changeset
|
319 |
*} |
c004e7448dca
temporarily disabled tests in Nominal/ROOT
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1484
diff
changeset
|
320 |
|
1493
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
321 |
section {* A Short Review of the Nominal Logic Work *} |
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
322 |
|
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
323 |
text {* |
1556 | 324 |
At its core, Nominal Isabelle is an adaption of the nominal logic work by |
325 |
Pitts \cite{Pitts03}. This adaptation for Isabelle/HOL is described in |
|
1517
62d6f7acc110
corrected the strong induction principle in the lambda-calculus case; gave a second (oartial) version that is more elegant
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1506
diff
changeset
|
326 |
\cite{HuffmanUrban10}, which we review here briefly to aid the description |
1556 | 327 |
of what follows. Two central notions in the nominal logic work are sorted |
1570 | 328 |
atoms and sort-respecting permutations of atoms. The sorts can be used to |
329 |
represent different kinds of variables, such as term- and type-variables in |
|
330 |
Core-Haskell, and it is assumed that there is an infinite supply of atoms |
|
331 |
for each sort. However, in order to simplify the description, we shall |
|
332 |
assume in what follows that there is only a single sort of atoms. |
|
1556 | 333 |
|
1493
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
334 |
|
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
335 |
Permutations are bijective functions from atoms to atoms that are |
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
336 |
the identity everywhere except on a finite number of atoms. There is a |
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
337 |
two-place permutation operation written |
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
338 |
|
1506
7c607df46a0a
slightly more in the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1493
diff
changeset
|
339 |
@{text[display,indent=5] "_ \<bullet> _ :: (\<alpha> \<times> \<alpha>) list \<Rightarrow> \<beta> \<Rightarrow> \<beta>"} |
1493
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
340 |
|
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
341 |
\noindent |
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
342 |
with a generic type in which @{text "\<alpha>"} stands for the type of atoms |
1570 | 343 |
and @{text "\<beta>"} for the type of the object on which the permutation |
1493
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
344 |
acts. In Nominal Isabelle the identity permutation is written as @{term "0::perm"}, |
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
345 |
the composition of two permutations @{term p} and @{term q} as \mbox{@{term "p + q"}} |
1570 | 346 |
and the inverse permutation of @{term p} as @{text "- p"}. The permutation |
1493
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
347 |
operation is defined for products, lists, sets, functions, booleans etc |
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
348 |
(see \cite{HuffmanUrban10}). |
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
349 |
|
1570 | 350 |
The most original aspect of the nominal logic work of Pitts is a general |
351 |
definition for the notion of ``the set of free variables of an object @{text |
|
352 |
"x"}''. This notion, written @{term "supp x"}, is general in the sense that |
|
353 |
it applies not only to lambda-terms alpha-equated or not, but also to lists, |
|
354 |
products, sets and even functions. The definition depends only on the |
|
355 |
permutation operation and on the notion of equality defined for the type of |
|
356 |
@{text x}, namely: |
|
1493
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
357 |
|
1506
7c607df46a0a
slightly more in the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1493
diff
changeset
|
358 |
@{thm[display,indent=5] supp_def[no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]} |
1493
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
359 |
|
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
360 |
\noindent |
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
361 |
There is also the derived notion for when an atom @{text a} is \emph{fresh} |
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
362 |
for an @{text x}, defined as |
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
363 |
|
1506
7c607df46a0a
slightly more in the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1493
diff
changeset
|
364 |
@{thm[display,indent=5] fresh_def[no_vars]} |
1493
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
365 |
|
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
366 |
\noindent |
1517
62d6f7acc110
corrected the strong induction principle in the lambda-calculus case; gave a second (oartial) version that is more elegant
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1506
diff
changeset
|
367 |
We also use for sets of atoms the abbreviation |
62d6f7acc110
corrected the strong induction principle in the lambda-calculus case; gave a second (oartial) version that is more elegant
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1506
diff
changeset
|
368 |
@{thm (lhs) fresh_star_def[no_vars]} defined as |
62d6f7acc110
corrected the strong induction principle in the lambda-calculus case; gave a second (oartial) version that is more elegant
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1506
diff
changeset
|
369 |
@{thm (rhs) fresh_star_def[no_vars]}. |
1493
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
370 |
A striking consequence of these definitions is that we can prove |
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
371 |
without knowing anything about the structure of @{term x} that |
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
372 |
swapping two fresh atoms, say @{text a} and @{text b}, leave |
1506
7c607df46a0a
slightly more in the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1493
diff
changeset
|
373 |
@{text x} unchanged. |
7c607df46a0a
slightly more in the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1493
diff
changeset
|
374 |
|
1517
62d6f7acc110
corrected the strong induction principle in the lambda-calculus case; gave a second (oartial) version that is more elegant
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1506
diff
changeset
|
375 |
\begin{property} |
1506
7c607df46a0a
slightly more in the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1493
diff
changeset
|
376 |
@{thm[mode=IfThen] swap_fresh_fresh[no_vars]} |
1517
62d6f7acc110
corrected the strong induction principle in the lambda-calculus case; gave a second (oartial) version that is more elegant
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1506
diff
changeset
|
377 |
\end{property} |
1506
7c607df46a0a
slightly more in the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1493
diff
changeset
|
378 |
|
1517
62d6f7acc110
corrected the strong induction principle in the lambda-calculus case; gave a second (oartial) version that is more elegant
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1506
diff
changeset
|
379 |
\noindent |
62d6f7acc110
corrected the strong induction principle in the lambda-calculus case; gave a second (oartial) version that is more elegant
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1506
diff
changeset
|
380 |
For a proof see \cite{HuffmanUrban10}. |
62d6f7acc110
corrected the strong induction principle in the lambda-calculus case; gave a second (oartial) version that is more elegant
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1506
diff
changeset
|
381 |
|
62d6f7acc110
corrected the strong induction principle in the lambda-calculus case; gave a second (oartial) version that is more elegant
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1506
diff
changeset
|
382 |
\begin{property} |
1506
7c607df46a0a
slightly more in the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1493
diff
changeset
|
383 |
@{thm[mode=IfThen] at_set_avoiding[no_vars]} |
1517
62d6f7acc110
corrected the strong induction principle in the lambda-calculus case; gave a second (oartial) version that is more elegant
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1506
diff
changeset
|
384 |
\end{property} |
1493
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
385 |
|
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
386 |
*} |
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
387 |
|
1485
c004e7448dca
temporarily disabled tests in Nominal/ROOT
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1484
diff
changeset
|
388 |
|
1556 | 389 |
section {* General Binders *} |
1485
c004e7448dca
temporarily disabled tests in Nominal/ROOT
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1484
diff
changeset
|
390 |
|
1517
62d6f7acc110
corrected the strong induction principle in the lambda-calculus case; gave a second (oartial) version that is more elegant
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1506
diff
changeset
|
391 |
text {* |
1587 | 392 |
In Nominal Isabelle, the user is expected to write down a specification of a |
393 |
term-calculus and then a reasoning infrastructure is automatically derived |
|
1579 | 394 |
from this specifcation (remember that Nominal Isabelle is a definitional |
1587 | 395 |
extension of Isabelle/HOL, which does not introduce any new axioms). |
1579 | 396 |
|
1556 | 397 |
|
1579 | 398 |
In order to keep our work manageable, we will wherever possible state |
399 |
definitions and perform proofs inside Isabelle, as opposed to write custom |
|
400 |
ML-code that generates them for each instance of a term-calculus. To that |
|
401 |
end, we will consider pairs @{text "(as, x)"} of type @{text "(atom set) \<times> \<beta>"}. |
|
402 |
These pairs are intended to represent the abstraction, or binding, of the set $as$ |
|
403 |
in the body $x$. |
|
1570 | 404 |
|
1579 | 405 |
The first question we have to answer is when the pairs $(as, x)$ and $(bs, y)$ are |
406 |
alpha-equivalent? (At the moment we are interested in |
|
1570 | 407 |
the notion of alpha-equivalence that is \emph{not} preserved by adding |
1579 | 408 |
vacuous binders.) To answer this, we identify four conditions: {\it i)} given |
409 |
a free-variable function $\fv$ of type \mbox{@{text "\<beta> \<Rightarrow> atom set"}}, then $x$ and $y$ |
|
1572 | 410 |
need to have the same set of free variables; moreover there must be a permutation, |
1579 | 411 |
$p$ so that {\it ii)} it leaves the free variables $x$ and $y$ unchanged, |
412 |
but {\it iii)} ``moves'' their bound names such that we obtain modulo a relation, |
|
1572 | 413 |
say \mbox{@{text "_ R _"}}, two equal terms. We also require {\it iv)} that $p$ makes |
1579 | 414 |
the abstracted sets $as$ and $bs$ equal. The requirements {\it i)} to {\it iv)} can |
415 |
be stated formally as follows: |
|
1556 | 416 |
% |
1572 | 417 |
\begin{equation}\label{alphaset} |
418 |
\begin{array}{@ {\hspace{10mm}}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l} |
|
1579 | 419 |
\multicolumn{2}{l}{(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}_{set}^{\fv, R, p} (bs, y) \;\dn\hspace{30mm}\;}\\[1mm] |
1572 | 420 |
& @{text "fv(x) - as = fv(y) - bs"}\\ |
421 |
\wedge & @{text "fv(x) - as #* p"}\\ |
|
422 |
\wedge & @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"}\\ |
|
423 |
\wedge & @{text "(p \<bullet> as) = bs"}\\ |
|
424 |
\end{array} |
|
1556 | 425 |
\end{equation} |
426 |
||
427 |
\noindent |
|
1579 | 428 |
Note that this relation is dependent on $p$. Alpha-equivalence is then the relation where |
429 |
we existentially quantify over this $p$. |
|
430 |
Also note that the relation is dependent on a free-variable function $\fv$ and a relation |
|
431 |
$R$. The reason for this extra generality is that we will use $\approx_{set}$ for both |
|
432 |
``raw'' terms and alpha-equated terms. In the latter case, $R$ will be replaced by |
|
433 |
equality $(op =)$ and we are going to prove that $\fv$ will be equal to the support |
|
434 |
of $x$ and $y$. To have these parameters means, however, we can derive properties about |
|
435 |
them generically. |
|
1572 | 436 |
|
437 |
The definition in \eqref{alphaset} does not make any distinction between the |
|
1579 | 438 |
order of abstracted variables. If we want this, then we can define alpha-equivalence |
439 |
for pairs of the form \mbox{@{text "(as, x)"}} with type @{text "(atom list) \<times> \<beta>"} |
|
440 |
as follows |
|
1572 | 441 |
% |
442 |
\begin{equation}\label{alphalist} |
|
443 |
\begin{array}{@ {\hspace{10mm}}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l} |
|
1579 | 444 |
\multicolumn{2}{l}{(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}_{list}^{\fv, R, p} (bs, y) \;\dn\hspace{30mm}\;}\\[1mm] |
1572 | 445 |
& @{text "fv(x) - (set as) = fv(y) - (set bs)"}\\ |
446 |
\wedge & @{text "fv(x) - (set as) #* p"}\\ |
|
447 |
\wedge & @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"}\\ |
|
448 |
\wedge & @{text "(p \<bullet> as) = bs"}\\ |
|
449 |
\end{array} |
|
450 |
\end{equation} |
|
451 |
||
452 |
\noindent |
|
453 |
where $set$ is just the function that coerces a list of atoms into a set of atoms. |
|
1556 | 454 |
|
1572 | 455 |
If we do not want to make any difference between the order of binders and |
1579 | 456 |
also allow vacuous binders, then we keep sets of binders, but drop the fourth |
457 |
condition in \eqref{alphaset}: |
|
1572 | 458 |
% |
1579 | 459 |
\begin{equation}\label{alphares} |
1572 | 460 |
\begin{array}{@ {\hspace{10mm}}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l} |
1579 | 461 |
\multicolumn{2}{l}{(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}_{res}^{\fv, R, p} (bs, y) \;\dn\hspace{30mm}\;}\\[1mm] |
1572 | 462 |
& @{text "fv(x) - as = fv(y) - bs"}\\ |
463 |
\wedge & @{text "fv(x) - as #* p"}\\ |
|
464 |
\wedge & @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"}\\ |
|
465 |
\end{array} |
|
466 |
\end{equation} |
|
1556 | 467 |
|
1579 | 468 |
\begin{exmple}\rm |
469 |
It might be useful to consider some examples for how these definitions pan out in practise. |
|
470 |
For this consider the case of abstracting a set of variables over types (as in type-schemes). |
|
471 |
We set $R$ to be the equality and for $\fv(T)$ we define |
|
1572 | 472 |
|
473 |
\begin{center} |
|
474 |
$\fv(x) = \{x\} \qquad \fv(T_1 \rightarrow T_2) = \fv(T_1) \cup \fv(T_2)$ |
|
475 |
\end{center} |
|
476 |
||
477 |
\noindent |
|
1579 | 478 |
Now recall the examples shown in \eqref{ex1}, \eqref{ex2} and \eqref{ex3}. It can be easily |
479 |
checked that @{text "({x, y}, x \<rightarrow> y)"} and |
|
480 |
@{text "({y, x}, y \<rightarrow> x)"} are equal according to $\approx_{set}$ and $\approx_{res}$ by taking $p$ to |
|
481 |
be the swapping @{term "(x \<rightleftharpoons> y)"}. In case of @{text "x \<noteq> y"} then |
|
482 |
$([x, y], x \rightarrow y) \not\approx_{list} ([y,x], x \rightarrow y)$ since there is no permutation that |
|
483 |
makes the lists @{text "[x, y]"} and @{text "[y, x]"} equal, and in addition leaves the |
|
484 |
type \mbox{@{text "x \<rightarrow> y"}} unchanged. Again if @{text "x \<noteq> y"}, we have that |
|
485 |
$(\{x\}, x) \approx_{res} (\{x,y\}, x)$ by taking $p$ to be the identity permutation. |
|
486 |
However $(\{x\}, x) \not\approx_{set} (\{x,y\}, x)$ since there is no permutation that makes |
|
487 |
the sets $\{x\}$ and $\{x,y\}$ equal (similarly for $\approx_{list}$). |
|
488 |
\end{exmple} |
|
489 |
||
490 |
\noindent |
|
491 |
Let $\star$ range over $\{set, res, list\}$. We prove next under which |
|
492 |
conditions the $\approx\hspace{0.05mm}_\star^{\fv, R, p}$ are equivalence |
|
493 |
relations and equivariant: |
|
494 |
||
495 |
\begin{lemma} |
|
496 |
{\it i)} Given the fact that $x\;R\;x$ holds, then |
|
497 |
$(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, 0}_\star (as, x)$. {\it ii)} Given |
|
498 |
that @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"} implies @{text "(-p \<bullet> y) R x"}, then |
|
499 |
$(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, p}_\star (bs, y)$ implies |
|
500 |
$(bs, y) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, - p}_\star (as, x)$. {\it iii)} Given |
|
501 |
that @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"} and @{text "(q \<bullet> y) R z"} implies |
|
502 |
@{text "((q + p) \<bullet> x) R z"}, then $(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, p}_\star (bs, y)$ |
|
503 |
and $(bs, y) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, q}_\star (cs, z)$ implies |
|
504 |
$(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, q + p}_\star (cs, z)$. Given |
|
505 |
@{text "(q \<bullet> x) R y"} implies @{text "(p \<bullet> (q \<bullet> x)) R (p \<bullet> y)"} and |
|
506 |
@{text "p \<bullet> (fv x) = fv (p \<bullet> x)"} then @{text "p \<bullet> (fv y) = fv (p \<bullet> y)"}, then |
|
507 |
$(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, q}_\star (bs, y)$ implies |
|
508 |
$(p \;\isasymbullet\; as, p \;\isasymbullet\; x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, q}_\star |
|
509 |
(p \;\isasymbullet\; bs, p \;\isasymbullet\; y)$. |
|
510 |
\end{lemma} |
|
511 |
||
512 |
\begin{proof} |
|
513 |
All properties are by unfolding the definitions and simple calculations. |
|
514 |
\end{proof} |
|
1587 | 515 |
|
516 |
||
517 |
\begin{lemma} |
|
518 |
$supp ([as]set. x) = supp x - as$ |
|
519 |
\end{lemma} |
|
1517
62d6f7acc110
corrected the strong induction principle in the lambda-calculus case; gave a second (oartial) version that is more elegant
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1506
diff
changeset
|
520 |
*} |
62d6f7acc110
corrected the strong induction principle in the lambda-calculus case; gave a second (oartial) version that is more elegant
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1506
diff
changeset
|
521 |
|
1491
f970ca9b5bec
paper uses now a heap file - does not compile so long anymore
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1485
diff
changeset
|
522 |
section {* Alpha-Equivalence and Free Variables *} |
f970ca9b5bec
paper uses now a heap file - does not compile so long anymore
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1485
diff
changeset
|
523 |
|
1520
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
524 |
text {* |
1611 | 525 |
The syntax of a specification for a term-calculus in Nominal Isabelle is |
526 |
heavily inspired by the syntax of the Ott-tool \cite{ott-jfp}. It is a |
|
527 |
collection of (possibly mutual recursive) type declarations, say |
|
528 |
$ty_{\alpha{}1}$, $ty_{\alpha{}2}$, \ldots $ty_{\alpha{}n}$, and a |
|
529 |
collection of associated binding function declarations, say |
|
1613 | 530 |
$bn_{\alpha{}1}$, \ldots $bn_{\alpha{}m}$. They are schematically |
531 |
written as follows: |
|
1587 | 532 |
|
533 |
\begin{center} |
|
1611 | 534 |
\begin{tabular}{@ {\hspace{-9mm}}p{1.8cm}l} |
535 |
types \mbox{declaration part} & |
|
536 |
$\begin{cases} |
|
537 |
\mbox{\begin{tabular}{l} |
|
538 |
\isacommand{nominal\_datatype} $ty_{\alpha{}1} = \ldots$\\ |
|
539 |
\isacommand{and} $ty_{\alpha{}2} = \ldots$\\ |
|
1587 | 540 |
$\ldots$\\ |
1611 | 541 |
\isacommand{and} $ty_{\alpha{}n} = \ldots$\\ |
542 |
\end{tabular}} |
|
543 |
\end{cases}$\\ |
|
544 |
binding \mbox{functions part} & |
|
545 |
$\begin{cases} |
|
546 |
\mbox{\begin{tabular}{l} |
|
547 |
\isacommand{with} $bn_{\alpha{}1}$ \isacommand{and} \ldots \isacommand{and} $bn_{\alpha{}m}$ |
|
1587 | 548 |
$\ldots$\\ |
1611 | 549 |
\isacommand{where}\\ |
1587 | 550 |
$\ldots$\\ |
1611 | 551 |
\end{tabular}} |
552 |
\end{cases}$\\ |
|
1587 | 553 |
\end{tabular} |
554 |
\end{center} |
|
555 |
||
556 |
\noindent |
|
1611 | 557 |
Each type declaration $ty_{\alpha{}i}$ consists of a collection of |
558 |
term-constructors, each of which comes with a list of labelled |
|
559 |
types that indicate the types of the arguments of the term-constructor, |
|
560 |
like |
|
561 |
||
562 |
\begin{center} |
|
563 |
$C_\alpha\;label_1\!::\!ty'_1\;\ldots label_j\!::\!ty'_j\;\;\textit{binding\_clauses}$ |
|
564 |
\end{center} |
|
1587 | 565 |
|
1611 | 566 |
\noindent |
567 |
The labels are optional and can be used in the (possibly empty) list of binding clauses. |
|
568 |
These clauses indicate the binders and the scope of the binders in a term-constructor. They |
|
569 |
are of the form |
|
1587 | 570 |
|
1611 | 571 |
\begin{center} |
572 |
\isacommand{bind}\; {\it binders}\; \isacommand{in}\; {\it label} |
|
573 |
\end{center} |
|
574 |
||
575 |
\noindent |
|
576 |
whereby we distinguish between \emph{shallow} binders and \emph{deep} binders. |
|
577 |
Shallow binders are just of the form \isacommand{bind}\; {\it label}\; |
|
578 |
\isacommand{in}\; {\it another\_label}. The only restriction on shallow binders |
|
579 |
is that the {\it label} must refer to either a type which is single atom or |
|
580 |
to a type which is a finite set of atoms. For example the specification of |
|
581 |
lambda-terms and type-schemes use them: |
|
582 |
||
583 |
\begin{center} |
|
1612 | 584 |
\begin{tabular}{@ {}cc@ {}} |
585 |
\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {\hspace{-1mm}}} |
|
586 |
\isacommand{nominal\_datatype} {\it lam} =\\ |
|
587 |
\hspace{5mm}\phantom{$\mid$} Var\;{\it name}\\ |
|
588 |
\hspace{5mm}$\mid$ App\;{\it lam}\;{\it lam}\\ |
|
589 |
\hspace{5mm}$\mid$ Lam\;{\it x::name}\;{\it t::lam}\\ |
|
590 |
\hspace{22mm}\isacommand{bind} {\it x} \isacommand{in} {\it t}\\ |
|
1611 | 591 |
\end{tabular} & |
1612 | 592 |
\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}} |
593 |
\isacommand{nominal\_datatype} {\it ty} =\\ |
|
594 |
\hspace{5mm}\phantom{$\mid$} TVar\;{\it name}\\ |
|
595 |
\hspace{5mm}$\mid$ TFun\;{\it ty}\;{\it ty}\\ |
|
596 |
\isacommand{and} {\it S} = All\;{\it xs::(name fset)}\;{\it T::ty}\\ |
|
597 |
\hspace{27mm}\isacommand{bind} {\it xs} \isacommand{in} {\it T}\\ |
|
1611 | 598 |
\end{tabular} |
599 |
\end{tabular} |
|
600 |
\end{center} |
|
1587 | 601 |
|
1612 | 602 |
\noindent |
1587 | 603 |
A specification of a term-calculus in Nominal Isabell is very similar to |
604 |
the usual datatype definition of Isabelle/HOL: |
|
605 |
||
606 |
||
607 |
Because of the problem Pottier pointed out in \cite{Pottier06}, the general |
|
608 |
binders from the previous section cannot be used directly to represent w |
|
609 |
be used directly |
|
610 |
*} |
|
611 |
||
612 |
||
613 |
||
614 |
text {* |
|
1520
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
615 |
Restrictions |
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
616 |
|
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
617 |
\begin{itemize} |
1572 | 618 |
\item non-emptiness |
1520
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
619 |
\item positive datatype definitions |
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
620 |
\item finitely supported abstractions |
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
621 |
\item respectfulness of the bn-functions\bigskip |
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
622 |
\item binders can only have a ``single scope'' |
1577 | 623 |
\item all bindings must have the same mode |
1520
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
624 |
\end{itemize} |
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
625 |
*} |
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
626 |
|
1493
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
627 |
section {* Examples *} |
1485
c004e7448dca
temporarily disabled tests in Nominal/ROOT
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1484
diff
changeset
|
628 |
|
1517
62d6f7acc110
corrected the strong induction principle in the lambda-calculus case; gave a second (oartial) version that is more elegant
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1506
diff
changeset
|
629 |
section {* Adequacy *} |
62d6f7acc110
corrected the strong induction principle in the lambda-calculus case; gave a second (oartial) version that is more elegant
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1506
diff
changeset
|
630 |
|
62d6f7acc110
corrected the strong induction principle in the lambda-calculus case; gave a second (oartial) version that is more elegant
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1506
diff
changeset
|
631 |
section {* Related Work *} |
62d6f7acc110
corrected the strong induction principle in the lambda-calculus case; gave a second (oartial) version that is more elegant
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1506
diff
changeset
|
632 |
|
1570 | 633 |
text {* |
634 |
Ott is better with list dot specifications; subgrammars |
|
635 |
||
636 |
untyped; |
|
637 |
||
638 |
*} |
|
639 |
||
640 |
||
1493
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
641 |
section {* Conclusion *} |
1485
c004e7448dca
temporarily disabled tests in Nominal/ROOT
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1484
diff
changeset
|
642 |
|
c004e7448dca
temporarily disabled tests in Nominal/ROOT
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1484
diff
changeset
|
643 |
text {* |
1520
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
644 |
Complication when the single scopedness restriction is lifted (two |
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
645 |
overlapping permutations) |
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
646 |
*} |
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
647 |
|
6ac75fd979d4
more of the introduction
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1517
diff
changeset
|
648 |
text {* |
1493
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
649 |
|
1517
62d6f7acc110
corrected the strong induction principle in the lambda-calculus case; gave a second (oartial) version that is more elegant
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1506
diff
changeset
|
650 |
TODO: function definitions: |
62d6f7acc110
corrected the strong induction principle in the lambda-calculus case; gave a second (oartial) version that is more elegant
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1506
diff
changeset
|
651 |
\medskip |
62d6f7acc110
corrected the strong induction principle in the lambda-calculus case; gave a second (oartial) version that is more elegant
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1506
diff
changeset
|
652 |
|
1493
52f68b524fd2
slightly more of the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1491
diff
changeset
|
653 |
\noindent |
1528
d6ee4a1b34ce
more tuning on the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1524
diff
changeset
|
654 |
{\bf Acknowledgements:} We are very grateful to Andrew Pitts for |
1506
7c607df46a0a
slightly more in the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1493
diff
changeset
|
655 |
many discussions about Nominal Isabelle. We thank Peter Sewell for |
7c607df46a0a
slightly more in the paper
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1493
diff
changeset
|
656 |
making the informal notes \cite{SewellBestiary} available to us and |
1556 | 657 |
also for patiently explaining some of the finer points about the abstract |
1545 | 658 |
definitions and about the implementation of the Ott-tool. |
1485
c004e7448dca
temporarily disabled tests in Nominal/ROOT
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
1484
diff
changeset
|
659 |
|
1577 | 660 |
Lookup: Merlin paper by James Cheney; Mark Shinwell PhD |
754
b85875d65b10
added a paper for possible notes
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
diff
changeset
|
661 |
|
1577 | 662 |
Future work: distinct list abstraction |
663 |
||
664 |
||
754
b85875d65b10
added a paper for possible notes
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
diff
changeset
|
665 |
*} |
b85875d65b10
added a paper for possible notes
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
diff
changeset
|
666 |
|
1484 | 667 |
|
668 |
||
754
b85875d65b10
added a paper for possible notes
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
diff
changeset
|
669 |
(*<*) |
b85875d65b10
added a paper for possible notes
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
diff
changeset
|
670 |
end |
b85875d65b10
added a paper for possible notes
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
diff
changeset
|
671 |
(*>*) |