theory Tactical
imports Base FirstSteps
begin
chapter {* Tactical Reasoning\label{chp:tactical} *}
text {*
The main reason for descending to the ML-level of Isabelle is to be able to
implement automatic proof procedures. Such proof procedures usually lessen
considerably the burden of manual reasoning, for example, when introducing
new definitions. These proof procedures are centred around refining a goal
state using tactics. This is similar to the \isacommand{apply}-style
reasoning at the user level, where goals are modified in a sequence of proof
steps until all of them are solved. However, there are also more structured
operations available on the ML-level that help with the handling of
variables and assumptions.
*}
section {* Basics of Reasoning with Tactics*}
text {*
To see how tactics work, let us first transcribe a simple \isacommand{apply}-style proof
into ML. Consider the following proof.
*}
lemma disj_swap: "P \<or> Q \<Longrightarrow> Q \<or> P"
apply(erule disjE)
apply(rule disjI2)
apply(assumption)
apply(rule disjI1)
apply(assumption)
done
text {*
This proof translates to the following ML-code.
@{ML_response_fake [display,gray]
"let
val ctxt = @{context}
val goal = @{prop \"P \<or> Q \<Longrightarrow> Q \<or> P\"}
in
Goal.prove ctxt [\"P\", \"Q\"] [] goal
(fn _ =>
etac @{thm disjE} 1
THEN rtac @{thm disjI2} 1
THEN atac 1
THEN rtac @{thm disjI1} 1
THEN atac 1)
end" "?P \<or> ?Q \<Longrightarrow> ?Q \<or> ?P"}
To start the proof, the function @{ML "Goal.prove"}~@{text "ctxt xs As C
tac"} sets up a goal state for proving the goal @{text C}
(that is @{prop "P \<or> Q \<Longrightarrow> Q \<or> P"} in the proof at hand) under the
assumptions @{text As} (happens to be empty) with the variables
@{text xs} that will be generalised once the goal is proved (in our case
@{text P} and @{text Q}). The @{text "tac"} is the tactic that proves the goal;
it can make use of the local assumptions (there are none in this example).
The functions @{ML etac}, @{ML rtac} and @{ML atac} correspond to
@{text erule}, @{text rule} and @{text assumption}, respectively.
The operator @{ML THEN} strings the tactics together.
\begin{readmore}
To learn more about the function @{ML Goal.prove} see \isccite{sec:results}
and the file @{ML_file "Pure/goal.ML"}. For more information about the
internals of goals see \isccite{sec:tactical-goals}. See @{ML_file
"Pure/tactic.ML"} and @{ML_file "Pure/tctical.ML"} for the code of basic
tactics and tactic combinators; see also Chapters 3 and 4 in the old
Isabelle Reference Manual.
\end{readmore}
Note that we used antiquotations for referencing the theorems. Many theorems
also have ML-bindings with the same name. Therefore, we could also just have
written @{ML "etac disjE 1"}, or in case there are no ML-binding obtained
the theorem dynamically using the theorem @{ML thm}; for example @{ML "etac
(thm \"disjE\") 1"}. Both ways however are considered bad style. The reason
is that the binding for @{ML disjE} can be re-assigned by the user and thus
one does not have complete control over which theorem is actually
applied. This problem is nicely prevented by using antiquotations, because
then the theorems are fixed statically at compile-time.
During the development of automatic proof procedures, you will often find it
necessary to test a tactic on examples. This can be conveniently
done with the command \isacommand{apply}@{text "(tactic \<verbopen> \<dots> \<verbclose>)"}.
Consider the following sequence of tactics
*}
ML{*val foo_tac =
(etac @{thm disjE} 1
THEN rtac @{thm disjI2} 1
THEN atac 1
THEN rtac @{thm disjI1} 1
THEN atac 1)*}
text {* and the Isabelle proof: *}
lemma "P \<or> Q \<Longrightarrow> Q \<or> P"
apply(tactic {* foo_tac *})
done
text {*
By using @{text "tactic \<verbopen> \<dots> \<verbclose>"} you can call from the
user level of Isabelle the tactic @{ML foo_tac} or
any other function that returns a tactic.
The tactic @{ML foo_tac} is just a sequence of simple tactics stringed
together by @{ML THEN}. As can be seen, each simple tactic in @{ML foo_tac}
has a hard-coded number that stands for the subgoal analysed by the
tactic (@{text "1"} stands for the first, or top-most, subgoal). This hard-coding
of goals is sometimes wanted, but usually it is not. To avoid the explicit numbering,
you can write
*}
ML{*val foo_tac' =
(etac @{thm disjE}
THEN' rtac @{thm disjI2}
THEN' atac
THEN' rtac @{thm disjI1}
THEN' atac)*}
text {*
and then give the number for the subgoal explicitly when the tactic is
called. So in the next proof you can first discharge the second subgoal, and
after that the first.
*}
lemma "P1 \<or> Q1 \<Longrightarrow> Q1 \<or> P1"
and "P2 \<or> Q2 \<Longrightarrow> Q2 \<or> P2"
apply(tactic {* foo_tac' 2 *})
apply(tactic {* foo_tac' 1 *})
done
text {*
This kind of addressing is more difficult to achieve when the goal is
hard-coded inside the tactic. For every operator that combines tactics
(@{ML THEN} is only one such operator) a ``primed'' version exists.
The tactics @{ML foo_tac} and @{ML foo_tac'} are very specific for
analysing goals being only of the form @{prop "P \<or> Q \<Longrightarrow> Q \<or> P"}. If the goal is not
of this form, then they throw the error message:
\begin{isabelle}
@{text "*** empty result sequence -- proof command failed"}\\
@{text "*** At command \"apply\"."}
\end{isabelle}
Meaning the tactics failed. The reason for this error message is that tactics
are functions that map a goal state to a (lazy) sequence of successor states,
hence the type of a tactic is:
@{text [display, gray] "type tactic = thm -> thm Seq.seq"}
It is custom that if a tactic fails, it should return the empty sequence:
therefore your own tactics should not raise exceptions willy-nilly.
The simplest tactics are @{ML no_tac} and @{ML all_tac}. The first returns
the empty sequence and is defined as
*}
ML{*fun no_tac thm = Seq.empty*}
text {*
which means @{ML no_tac} always fails. The second returns the given theorem wrapped
as a single member sequence. It is defined as
*}
ML{*fun all_tac thm = Seq.single thm*}
text {*
which means @{ML all_tac} always succeeds (but also does not make any progress
with the proof).
The lazy list of possible successor states shows through at the user-level
of Isabelle when using the command \isacommand{back}. For instance in the
following proof, there are two possibilities for how to apply
@{ML foo_tac'}.
*}
lemma "\<lbrakk>P \<or> Q; P \<or> Q\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> Q \<or> P"
apply(tactic {* foo_tac' 1 *})
back
done
text {*
By using \isacommand{back}, we construct the proof that uses the
second assumption. In more interesting situations, different possibilities
can lead to different proofs and even often need to be explored when
a first proof attempt is unsuccessful.
\begin{readmore}
See @{ML_file "Pure/General/seq.ML"} for the implementation of lazy
sequences. However in day-to-day Isabelle programming, one rarely
constructs sequences explicitly, but uses the predefined functions
instead.
\end{readmore}
It might be surprising that tactics, which transform
one proof state to the next, are functions from theorems to theorem
(sequences). The surprise resolves by knowing that every
goal state is indeed a theorem. To shed more light on this,
let us modify the code of @{ML all_tac} to obtain the following
tactic
*}
ML{*fun my_print_tac ctxt thm =
let
val _ = warning (str_of_thm ctxt thm)
in
Seq.single thm
end*}
text {*
which prints out the given theorem (using the string-function defined
in Section~\ref{sec:printing}) and then behaves like @{ML all_tac}. We
now can inspect every proof state in a proof. Consider the proof below: on
the left-hand side we show the goal state as shown by Isabelle; on the
right-hand side the print out from @{ML my_print_tac}.
*}
lemma shows "\<lbrakk>A; B\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> A \<and> B"
apply(tactic {* my_print_tac @{context} *})
txt{* \small
\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}p{0.7\textwidth}@ {}}
\begin{minipage}[t]{0.3\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage} &
\hfill@{text "(\<lbrakk>A; B\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> A \<and> B) \<Longrightarrow> (\<lbrakk>A; B\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> A \<and> B)"}
\end{tabular}
*}
apply(rule conjI)
apply(tactic {* my_print_tac @{context} *})
txt{* \small
\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}p{0.76\textwidth}@ {}}
\begin{minipage}[t]{0.26\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage} &
\hfill@{text "(\<lbrakk>A; B\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> A) \<Longrightarrow> (\<lbrakk>A; B\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> B) \<Longrightarrow> (\<lbrakk>A; B\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> A \<and> B)"}
\end{tabular}
*}
apply(assumption)
apply(tactic {* my_print_tac @{context} *})
txt{* \small
\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}p{0.7\textwidth}@ {}}
\begin{minipage}[t]{0.3\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage} &
\hfill@{text "(\<lbrakk>A; B\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> B) \<Longrightarrow> (\<lbrakk>A; B\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> A \<and> B)"}
\end{tabular}
*}
apply(assumption)
apply(tactic {* my_print_tac @{context} *})
txt{* \small
\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}p{0.7\textwidth}@ {}}
\begin{minipage}[t]{0.3\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage} &
\hfill@{text "\<lbrakk>A; B\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> A \<and> B"}
\end{tabular}
*}
done
text {*
As can be seen, internally every goal state is an implication of the form
@{text[display] "A\<^isub>1 \<Longrightarrow> \<dots> \<Longrightarrow> A\<^isub>n \<Longrightarrow> (C)"}
where @{term C} is the goal to be proved and the @{term "A\<^isub>i"} are the
subgoals. So after setting up the lemma, the goal state is always of the form
@{text "C \<Longrightarrow> (C)"}. Since the goal @{term C} can potentially be an implication,
there is a ``protector'' wrapped around it (in from of an outermost constant
@{text "Const (\"prop\", bool \<Rightarrow> bool)"} applied to each goal;
however this constant is invisible in the print out above). This
prevents that premises of @{text C} are misinterpreted as open subgoals.
While tactics can operate on the subgoals (the @{text "A\<^isub>i"} above), they
are expected to leave the conclusion @{term C} intact, with the
exception of possibly instantiating schematic variables.
*}
section {* Simple Tactics *}
text {*
A simple tactic is @{ML print_tac}, which is useful for low-level debugging of tactics.
It just prints out a message and the current goal state.
*}
lemma shows "False \<Longrightarrow> True"
apply(tactic {* print_tac "foo message" *})
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
Another simple tactic is the function @{ML atac}, which, as shown in the previous
section, corresponds to the assumption command.
*}
lemma shows "P \<Longrightarrow> P"
apply(tactic {* atac 1 *})
done
text {*
Similarly, @{ML rtac}, @{ML dtac}, @{ML etac} and @{ML ftac} correspond
to @{text rule}, @{text drule}, @{text erule} and @{text frule},
respectively. Each of them takes a theorem as argument. Below are three
examples with the resulting goal state. How
they work should be self-explanatory.
*}
lemma shows "P \<and> Q"
apply(tactic {* rtac @{thm conjI} 1 *})
txt{*\begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage}*}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
lemma shows "P \<and> Q \<Longrightarrow> False"
apply(tactic {* etac @{thm conjE} 1 *})
txt{*\begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage}*}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
lemma shows "False \<and> True \<Longrightarrow> False"
apply(tactic {* dtac @{thm conjunct2} 1 *})
txt{*\begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage}*}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
As mentioned in the previous section, most basic tactics take a number as
argument, which addresses the subgoal they are analysing. In the proof below,
we first break up the second subgoal by focusing on this subgoal first.
*}
lemma shows "Foo" and "P \<and> Q"
apply(tactic {* rtac @{thm conjI} 2 *})
txt {*\begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage}*}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
The function @{ML resolve_tac} is similar to @{ML rtac}, except that it
expects a list of theorems as arguments. From this list it will apply the
first applicable theorem (later theorems that are also applicable can be
explored via the lazy sequences mechanism). Given the code
*}
ML{*val resolve_tac_xmp = resolve_tac [@{thm impI}, @{thm conjI}]*}
text {*
an example for @{ML resolve_tac} is the following proof where first an outermost
implication is analysed and then an outermost conjunction.
*}
lemma shows "C \<longrightarrow> (A \<and> B)" and "(A \<longrightarrow> B) \<and> C"
apply(tactic {* resolve_tac_xmp 1 *})
apply(tactic {* resolve_tac_xmp 2 *})
txt{*\begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage}*}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
Similarly versions exists for @{ML atac} (@{ML assume_tac}), @{ML etac}
(@{ML eresolve_tac}) and so on.
(FIXME: @{ML cut_facts_tac})
Since rules are applied using higher-order unification, an automatic proof
procedure might become too fragile, if it just applies inference rules shown
in the fashion above. More constraints can be introduced by
pre-instantiating theorems with other theorems. You can do this using the
function @{ML RS}. For example
@{ML_response_fake [display,gray]
"@{thm disjI1} RS @{thm conjI}" "\<lbrakk>?P1; ?Q\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> (?P1 \<or> ?Q1) \<and> ?Q"}
instantiates the first premise of the @{text conjI}-rule with the
rule @{text disjI1}. The function @{ML RSN} is similar, but
takes a number and makes explicit which premise should be instantiated.
To improve readability we are going use the following function
*}
ML{*fun no_vars ctxt thm =
let
val ((_, [thm']), _) = Variable.import_thms true [thm] ctxt
in
thm'
end*}
text {*
to transform the schematic variables of a theorem into free variables.
This means for the @{ML RS}-expression above:
@{ML_response_fake [display,gray]
"no_vars @{context} (@{thm disjI1} RS @{thm conjI})" "\<lbrakk>P; Q\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> (P \<or> Qa) \<and> Q"}
If you want to instantiate more than one premise, you can use the function
@{ML MRS}:
@{ML_response_fake [display,gray]
"no_vars @{context} ([@{thm disjI1}, @{thm disjI2}] MRS @{thm conjI})"
"\<lbrakk>P; Q\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> (P \<or> Qa) \<and> (Pa \<or> Q)"}
If you need to instantiate lists of theorems, you can use the
functions @{ML RL} and @{ML MRL}. For example below every
theorem in the first list is instantiated against every theorem
in the second.
@{ML_response_fake [display,gray]
"[@{thm impI}, @{thm disjI2}] RL [@{thm conjI}, @{thm disjI1}]"
"[\<lbrakk>P \<Longrightarrow> Q; Qa\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> (P \<longrightarrow> Q) \<and> Qa,
\<lbrakk>Q; Qa\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> (P \<or> Q) \<and> Qa,
(P \<Longrightarrow> Q) \<Longrightarrow> (P \<longrightarrow> Q) \<or> Qa,
Q \<Longrightarrow> (P \<or> Q) \<or> Qa]"}
\begin{readmore}
The combinators for instantiating theorems are defined in @{ML_file "Pure/drule.ML"}.
\end{readmore}
Often proofs involve elaborate operations on assumptions and
@{text "\<And>"}-quantified variables. To do such operations on the ML-level
using the basic tactics is very unwieldy and brittle. Some convenience and
safety is provided by the tactic @{ML SUBPROOF}. This tactic fixes the parameters
and binds the various components of a proof state into a record.
To see what happens, assume the function defined in Figure~\ref{fig:sptac}, which
takes a record as argument and just prints out the content of this record (using the
string transformation functions defined in Section~\ref{sec:printing}). Consider
now the proof
*}
text_raw{*
\begin{figure}
\begin{isabelle}
*}
ML{*fun sp_tac {prems, params, asms, concl, context, schematics} =
let
val str_of_params = str_of_cterms context params
val str_of_asms = str_of_cterms context asms
val str_of_concl = str_of_cterm context concl
val str_of_prems = str_of_thms context prems
val str_of_schms = str_of_cterms context (snd schematics)
val _ = (warning ("params: " ^ str_of_params);
warning ("schematics: " ^ str_of_schms);
warning ("assumptions: " ^ str_of_asms);
warning ("conclusion: " ^ str_of_concl);
warning ("premises: " ^ str_of_prems))
in
no_tac
end*}
text_raw{*
\end{isabelle}
\caption{A function that prints out the various parameters provided by the tactic
@{ML SUBPROOF}. It uses the functions defined in Section~\ref{sec:printing} for
extracting strings from @{ML_type cterm}s and @{ML_type thm}s.\label{fig:sptac}}
\end{figure}
*}
lemma shows "\<And>x y. A x y \<Longrightarrow> B y x \<longrightarrow> C (?z y) x"
apply(tactic {* SUBPROOF sp_tac @{context} 1 *})?
txt {*
which yields the printout:
\begin{quote}\small
\begin{tabular}{ll}
params: & @{term x}, @{term y}\\
schematics: & @{term z}\\
assumptions: & @{term "A x y"}\\
conclusion: & @{term "B y x \<longrightarrow> C (z y) x"}\\
premises: & @{term "A x y"}
\end{tabular}
\end{quote}
Note in the actual output the brown colour of the variables @{term x} and
@{term y}. Although they are parameters in the original goal, they are fixed inside
the subproof. Similarly the schematic variable @{term z}. The assumption
@{prop "A x y"} is bound as @{ML_type cterm} to the record-variable
@{text asms} but also as @{ML_type thm} to @{text prems}.
Notice also that we had to append @{text "?"} to \isacommand{apply}. The
reason is that @{ML SUBPROOF} normally expects that the subgoal is solved completely.
Since in the function @{ML sp_tac} we returned the tactic @{ML no_tac}, the subproof
obviously fails. The question-mark allows us to recover from this failure
in a graceful manner so that the warning messages are not overwritten
by an error message.
If we continue the proof script by applying the @{text impI}-rule
*}
apply(rule impI)
apply(tactic {* SUBPROOF sp_tac @{context} 1 *})?
txt {*
then @{ML SUBPROOF} prints out
\begin{quote}\small
\begin{tabular}{ll}
params: & @{term x}, @{term y}\\
schematics: & @{term z}\\
assumptions: & @{term "A x y"}, @{term "B y x"}\\
conclusion: & @{term "C (z y) x"}\\
premises: & @{term "A x y"}, @{term "B y x"}
\end{tabular}
\end{quote}
*}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
where we now also have @{term "B y x"} as an assumption.
One convenience of @{ML SUBPROOF} is that we can apply the assumptions
using the usual tactics, because the parameter @{text prems}
contains them as theorems. With this we can easily
implement a tactic that almost behaves like @{ML atac}, namely:
*}
ML{*val atac' = SUBPROOF (fn {prems, ...} => resolve_tac prems 1)*}
lemma shows "\<And>x y. \<lbrakk>B x y; A x y; C x y\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> A x y"
apply(tactic {* atac' @{context} 1 *})
txt{* yields
@{subgoals [display]} *}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
The restriction in this tactic is that it cannot instantiate any
schematic variables. This might be seen as a defect, but is actually
an advantage in the situations for which @{ML SUBPROOF} was designed:
the reason is that instantiation of schematic variables can affect
several goals and can render them unprovable. @{ML SUBPROOF} is meant
to avoid this.
Notice that @{ML atac'} calls @{ML resolve_tac} with the subgoal
number @{text "1"} and also the ``outer'' call to @{ML SUBPROOF} in
the \isacommand{apply}-step uses @{text "1"}. Another advantage
of @{ML SUBGOAL} is that the addressing inside it is completely
local to the subproof inside. It is therefore possible to also apply
@{ML atac'} to the second goal:
*}
lemma shows "True" and "\<And>x y. \<lbrakk>B x y; A x y; C x y\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> A x y"
apply(tactic {* atac' @{context} 2 *})
apply(rule TrueI)
done
text {*
\begin{readmore}
The function @{ML SUBPROOF} is defined in @{ML_file "Pure/subgoal.ML"} and
also described in \isccite{sec:results}.
\end{readmore}
A similar but less powerful function than @{ML SUBPROOF} is @{ML SUBGOAL}.
It allows you to inspect a specified subgoal. With this you can implement
a tactic that applies a rule according to its topmost connective (we only
analyse a few connectives). The tactic is as follows:
*}
ML %linenumbers{*fun select_tac (t,i) =
case t of
@{term "Trueprop"} $ t' => select_tac (t',i)
| @{term "op \<and>"} $ _ $ _ => rtac @{thm conjI} i
| @{term "op \<longrightarrow>"} $ _ $ _ => rtac @{thm impI} i
| @{term "Not"} $ _ => rtac @{thm notI} i
| Const (@{const_name "All"}, _) $ _ => rtac @{thm allI} i
| _ => all_tac*}
text {*
In line 3 you need to decend under the outermost @{term "Trueprop"} in order
to get to the connective you like to analyse. Otherwise goals @{prop "A \<and> B"}
are not bropek up. In line 7, the pattern cannot be constructed using the
@{text "@term"}-antiquotation, because that would fix the type of the
quantified variable. In this case you really have to construct the pattern
by using the term-constructors. The other cases work, because their type
is always bool. In case that the goal does not fall into any of the categorories,
then we chose to just return @{ML all_tac} (i.e., the tactic never fails).
Let us now see how to apply this tactic.
*}
lemma shows "A \<and> B" and "A \<longrightarrow> B \<longrightarrow>C" and "\<forall>x. D x" and "E \<Longrightarrow> F"
apply(tactic {* SUBGOAL select_tac 4 *})
apply(tactic {* SUBGOAL select_tac 3 *})
apply(tactic {* SUBGOAL select_tac 2 *})
apply(tactic {* SUBGOAL select_tac 1 *})
txt{* @{subgoals [display]} *}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
Note that we applied it in ``reverse'' order. This is a trick in
order to be independent from what subgoals the rule produced. If we had
it applied in the other order
*}
lemma shows "A \<and> B" and "A \<longrightarrow> B \<longrightarrow>C" and "\<forall>x. D x" and "E \<Longrightarrow> F"
apply(tactic {* SUBGOAL select_tac 1 *})
apply(tactic {* SUBGOAL select_tac 3 *})
apply(tactic {* SUBGOAL select_tac 4 *})
apply(tactic {* SUBGOAL select_tac 5 *})
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
then we have to be careful to not apply the tactic to the two subgoals the
first goal produced. This can be messy in an automated proof script. The
reverse application, on the other hand, is easy to implement.
However, this example is contrived: there are much simpler ways to implement
such proof procedure that analyses a goal according to its topmost
connective. They will be explained in the next section.
*}
section {* Tactic Combinators *}
text {*
To be able to implement powerful tactics out of smaller component tactics,
Isabelle provides tactic combinators. In the previous section we already
used @{ML THEN} which strings two tactics together in sequence. For example:
*}
lemma shows "(Foo \<and> Bar) \<and> False"
apply(tactic {* rtac @{thm conjI} 1 THEN rtac @{thm conjI} 1 *})
txt {* \begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage} *}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
If you want to avoid the hard-coded subgoal addressing, then you can use
@{ML THEN'}. For example:
*}
lemma shows "(Foo \<and> Bar) \<and> False"
apply(tactic {* (rtac @{thm conjI} THEN' rtac @{thm conjI}) 1 *})
txt {* \begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage} *}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
For most tactic combinators such a ``primed'' version exists.
In what follows we will, whenever appropriate, prefer the primed version of
the tactic combinator and omit to mention the simple one.
With @{ML THEN} and @{ML THEN'} it must be guaranteed that both tactics
sucessfully apply; otherwise the whole tactic will fail. If you want to
try out either one tactic, then you can use @{ML ORELSE'}. For
example
*}
ML{*val orelse_xmp = (rtac @{thm disjI1} ORELSE' rtac @{thm conjI})*}
text {*
will first try out rule @{text disjI} and after that @{text conjI}.
*}
lemma shows "True \<and> False" and "Foo \<or> Bar"
apply(tactic {* orelse_xmp 1 *})
apply(tactic {* orelse_xmp 3 *})
txt {* @{subgoals [display]} *}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
applies
@{ML REPEAT} @{ML DETERM}
*}
section {* Rewriting and Simplifier Tactics *}
text {*
@{ML rewrite_goals_tac}
@{ML ObjectLogic.full_atomize_tac}
@{ML ObjectLogic.rulify_tac}
*}
section {* Structured Proofs *}
lemma True
proof
{
fix A B C
assume r: "A & B \<Longrightarrow> C"
assume A B
then have "A & B" ..
then have C by (rule r)
}
{
fix A B C
assume r: "A & B \<Longrightarrow> C"
assume A B
note conjI [OF this]
note r [OF this]
}
oops
ML {* fun prop ctxt s =
Thm.cterm_of (ProofContext.theory_of ctxt) (Syntax.read_prop ctxt s) *}
ML {*
val ctxt0 = @{context};
val ctxt = ctxt0;
val (_, ctxt) = Variable.add_fixes ["A", "B", "C"] ctxt;
val ([r], ctxt) = Assumption.add_assumes [prop ctxt "A & B \<Longrightarrow> C"] ctxt;
val (this, ctxt) = Assumption.add_assumes [prop ctxt "A", prop ctxt "B"] ctxt;
val this = [@{thm conjI} OF this];
val this = r OF this;
val this = Assumption.export false ctxt ctxt0 this
val this = Variable.export ctxt ctxt0 [this]
*}
end