--- a/CookBook/Package/Ind_Examples.thy Thu Feb 19 14:44:53 2009 +0000
+++ /dev/null Thu Jan 01 00:00:00 1970 +0000
@@ -1,317 +0,0 @@
-theory Ind_Examples
-imports Main LaTeXsugar
-begin
-
-section{* Examples of Inductive Definitions \label{sec:ind-examples} *}
-
-text {*
- Let us first give three examples showing how to define inductive
- predicates by hand and then also how to prove by hand characteristic properties
- about them, such as introduction rules and induction principles. From
- these examples, we will figure out a general method for defining inductive
- predicates. The aim in this section is \emph{not} to write proofs that are as
- beautiful as possible, but as close as possible to the ML-code we will
- develop later.
-
-
- As a first example, let us consider the transitive closure of a relation @{text
- R}. It is an inductive predicate characterised by the two introduction rules:
-
- \begin{center}
- @{prop[mode=Axiom] "trcl R x x"} \hspace{5mm}
- @{prop[mode=Rule] "R x y \<Longrightarrow> trcl R y z \<Longrightarrow> trcl R x z"}
- \end{center}
-
- Note that the @{text trcl} predicate has two different kinds of parameters: the
- first parameter @{text R} stays \emph{fixed} throughout the definition, whereas
- the second and third parameter changes in the ``recursive call''. This will
- become important later on when we deal with fixed parameters and locales.
-
- Since an inductively defined predicate is the least predicate closed under
- a collection of introduction rules, we define the predicate @{text "trcl R x y"} in
- such a way that it holds if and only if @{text "P x y"} holds for every predicate
- @{text P} closed under the rules above. This gives rise to the definition
-*}
-
-definition "trcl R x y \<equiv>
- \<forall>P. (\<forall>x. P x x) \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>x y z. R x y \<longrightarrow> P y z \<longrightarrow> P x z) \<longrightarrow> P x y"
-
-text {*
- where we quantify over the predicate @{text P}. Note that we have to use the
- object implication @{text "\<longrightarrow>"} and object quantification @{text "\<forall>"} for
- stating this definition (there is no other way for definitions in
- HOL). However, the introduction rules and induction principles derived later
- should use the corresponding meta-connectives since they simplify the
- reasoning for the user.
-
- With this definition, the proof of the induction principle for the transitive
- closure is almost immediate. It suffices to convert all the meta-level
- connectives in the lemma to object-level connectives using the
- proof method @{text atomize} (Line 4), expand the definition of @{text trcl}
- (Line 5 and 6), eliminate the universal quantifier contained in it (Line 7),
- and then solve the goal by assumption (Line 8).
-
-*}
-
-lemma %linenos trcl_induct:
- assumes asm: "trcl R x y"
- shows "(\<And>x. P x x) \<Longrightarrow> (\<And>x y z. R x y \<Longrightarrow> P y z \<Longrightarrow> P x z) \<Longrightarrow> P x y"
-apply(atomize (full))
-apply(cut_tac asm)
-apply(unfold trcl_def)
-apply(drule spec[where x=P])
-apply(assumption)
-done
-
-text {*
- The proofs for the introduction are slightly more complicated. We need to prove
- the facs @{prop "trcl R x x"} and @{prop "R x y \<Longrightarrow> trcl R y z \<Longrightarrow> trcl R x z"}.
- In order to prove the first fact, we again unfold the definition and
- then apply the introdution rules for @{text "\<forall>"} and @{text "\<longrightarrow>"} as often as possible.
- We then end up in the goal state:
-*}
-
-(*<*)lemma "trcl R x x"
-apply (unfold trcl_def)
-apply (rule allI impI)+(*>*)
-txt {* @{subgoals [display]} *}
-(*<*)oops(*>*)
-
-text {*
- The two assumptions correspond to the introduction rules, where @{text "trcl
- R"} has been replaced by P. Thus, all we have to do is to eliminate the
- universal quantifier in front of the first assumption, and then solve the
- goal by assumption. Thus the proof is:
-*}
-
-lemma trcl_base: "trcl R x x"
-apply(unfold trcl_def)
-apply(rule allI impI)+
-apply(drule spec)
-apply(assumption)
-done
-
-text {*
- Since the second @{text trcl}-rule has premises, the proof of its
- introduction rule is not as easy. After unfolding the definitions and
- applying the introduction rules for @{text "\<forall>"} and @{text "\<longrightarrow>"}, we get the
- goal state:
-*}
-
-(*<*)lemma "R x y \<Longrightarrow> trcl R y z \<Longrightarrow> trcl R x z"
-apply (unfold trcl_def)
-apply (rule allI impI)+(*>*)
-txt {*@{subgoals [display]} *}
-(*<*)oops(*>*)
-
-text {*
- The third and fourth assumption correspond to the first and second
- introduction rule, respectively, whereas the first and second assumption
- corresponds to the pre\-mises of the introduction rule. Since we want to prove
- the second introduction rule, we apply the fourth assumption to the goal
- @{term "P x z"}. In order for the assumption to be applicable as a rule, we have to
- eliminate the universal quantifier and turn the object-level implications
- into meta-level ones. This can be accomplished using the @{text rule_format}
- attribute. Applying the assumption produces the two new subgoals
-*}
-
-(*<*)lemma "R x y \<Longrightarrow> trcl R y z \<Longrightarrow> trcl R x z"
-apply (unfold trcl_def)
-apply (rule allI impI)+
-proof -
- case (goal1 P)
- have a4: "\<forall>x y z. R x y \<longrightarrow> P y z \<longrightarrow> P x z" by fact
- show ?case
- apply (rule a4[rule_format])(*>*)
-txt {*@{subgoals [display]} *}
-(*<*)oops(*>*)
-
-text {*
- which can be
- solved using the first and second assumption. The second assumption again
- involves a quantifier and an implications that have to be eliminated before it
- can be applied. To avoid potential problems with higher-order unification,
- we should explcitly instantiate the universally quantified
- predicate variable to @{text "P"} and also match explicitly the implications
- with the the third and fourth assumption. This gives the proof:
-*}
-
-
-lemma trcl_step: "R x y \<Longrightarrow> trcl R y z \<Longrightarrow> trcl R x z"
-apply(unfold trcl_def)
-apply(rule allI impI)+
-proof -
- case (goal1 P)
- have a1: "R x y" by fact
- have a2: "\<forall>P. (\<forall>x. P x x)
- \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>x y z. R x y \<longrightarrow> P y z \<longrightarrow> P x z) \<longrightarrow> P y z" by fact
- have a3: "\<forall>x. P x x" by fact
- have a4: "\<forall>x y z. R x y \<longrightarrow> P y z \<longrightarrow> P x z" by fact
- show "P x z"
- apply(rule a4[rule_format])
- apply(rule a1)
- apply(rule a2[THEN spec[where x=P], THEN mp, THEN mp, OF a3, OF a4])
- done
-qed
-
-text {*
- It might be surprising that we are not using the automatic tactics available in
- Isabelle for proving this lemmas. After all @{text "blast"} would easily
- dispense of it.
-*}
-
-lemma trcl_step_blast: "R x y \<Longrightarrow> trcl R y z \<Longrightarrow> trcl R x z"
-apply(unfold trcl_def)
-apply(blast)
-done
-
-text {*
- Experience has shown that it is generally a bad idea to rely heavily on
- @{text blast}, @{text auto} and the like in automated proofs. The reason is
- that you do not have precise control over them (the user can, for example,
- declare new intro- or simplification rules that can throw automatic tactics
- off course) and also it is very hard to debug proofs involving automatic
- tactics whenever something goes wrong. Therefore if possible, automatic
- tactics should be avoided or sufficiently constrained.
-
- The method of defining inductive predicates by impredicative quantification
- also generalises to mutually inductive predicates. The next example defines
- the predicates @{text even} and @{text odd} characterised by the following
- rules:
-
- \begin{center}
- @{prop[mode=Axiom] "even (0::nat)"} \hspace{5mm}
- @{prop[mode=Rule] "odd m \<Longrightarrow> even (Suc m)"} \hspace{5mm}
- @{prop[mode=Rule] "even m \<Longrightarrow> odd (Suc m)"}
- \end{center}
-
- Since the predicates are mutually inductive, each definition
- quantifies over both predicates, below named @{text P} and @{text Q}.
-*}
-
-definition "even n \<equiv>
- \<forall>P Q. P 0 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. Q m \<longrightarrow> P (Suc m))
- \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. P m \<longrightarrow> Q (Suc m)) \<longrightarrow> P n"
-
-definition "odd n \<equiv>
- \<forall>P Q. P 0 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. Q m \<longrightarrow> P (Suc m))
- \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. P m \<longrightarrow> Q (Suc m)) \<longrightarrow> Q n"
-
-text {*
- For proving the induction principles, we use exactly the same technique
- as in the transitive closure example, namely:
-*}
-
-lemma even_induct:
- assumes asm: "even n"
- shows "P 0 \<Longrightarrow>
- (\<And>m. Q m \<Longrightarrow> P (Suc m)) \<Longrightarrow> (\<And>m. P m \<Longrightarrow> Q (Suc m)) \<Longrightarrow> P n"
-apply(atomize (full))
-apply(cut_tac asm)
-apply(unfold even_def)
-apply(drule spec[where x=P])
-apply(drule spec[where x=Q])
-apply(assumption)
-done
-
-text {*
- We omit the other induction principle that has @{term "Q n"} as conclusion.
- The proofs of the introduction rules are also very similar to the ones in the
- @{text "trcl"}-example. We only show the proof of the second introduction rule.
-*}
-
-lemma evenS: "odd m \<Longrightarrow> even (Suc m)"
-apply (unfold odd_def even_def)
-apply (rule allI impI)+
-proof -
- case (goal1 P)
- have a1: "\<forall>P Q. P 0 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. Q m \<longrightarrow> P (Suc m))
- \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. P m \<longrightarrow> Q (Suc m)) \<longrightarrow> Q m" by fact
- have a2: "P 0" by fact
- have a3: "\<forall>m. Q m \<longrightarrow> P (Suc m)" by fact
- have a4: "\<forall>m. P m \<longrightarrow> Q (Suc m)" by fact
- show "P (Suc m)"
- apply(rule a3[rule_format])
- apply(rule a1[THEN spec[where x=P], THEN spec[where x=Q],
- THEN mp, THEN mp, THEN mp, OF a2, OF a3, OF a4])
- done
-qed
-
-text {*
- As a final example, we define the accessible part of a relation @{text R} characterised
- by the introduction rule
-
- \begin{center}
- @{term[mode=Rule] "(\<forall>y. R y x \<longrightarrow> accpart R y) \<Longrightarrow> accpart R x"}
- \end{center}
-
- whose premise involves a universal quantifier and an implication. The
- definition of @{text accpart} is:
-*}
-
-definition "accpart R x \<equiv> \<forall>P. (\<forall>x. (\<forall>y. R y x \<longrightarrow> P y) \<longrightarrow> P x) \<longrightarrow> P x"
-
-text {*
- The proof of the induction principle is again straightforward.
-*}
-
-lemma accpart_induct:
- assumes asm: "accpart R x"
- shows "(\<And>x. (\<forall>y. R y x \<longrightarrow> P y) \<Longrightarrow> P x) \<Longrightarrow> P x"
-apply(atomize (full))
-apply(cut_tac asm)
-apply(unfold accpart_def)
-apply(drule spec[where x=P])
-apply(assumption)
-done
-
-text {*
- Proving the introduction rule is a little more complicated, because the quantifier
- and the implication in the premise. We first convert the meta-level universal quantifier
- and implication to their object-level counterparts. Unfolding the definition of
- @{text accpart} and applying the introduction rules for @{text "\<forall>"} and @{text "\<longrightarrow>"}
- yields the following goal state:
-*}
-
-(*<*)lemma accpartI: "(\<forall>y. R y x \<longrightarrow> accpart R y) \<Longrightarrow> accpart R x"
-apply (unfold accpart_def)
-apply (rule allI impI)+(*>*)
-txt {* @{subgoals [display]} *}
-(*<*)oops(*>*)
-
-text {*
- Applying the second assumption produces a goal state with the new local assumption
- @{term "R y x"}, which will then be used to solve the goal @{term "P y"} using the
- first assumption.
-*}
-
-lemma %small accpartI: "(\<forall>y. R y x \<longrightarrow> accpart R y) \<Longrightarrow> accpart R x"
-apply (unfold accpart_def)
-apply (rule allI impI)+
-proof -
- case (goal1 P)
- have a1: "\<forall>y. R y x \<longrightarrow>
- (\<forall>P. (\<forall>x. (\<forall>y. R y x \<longrightarrow> P y) \<longrightarrow> P x) \<longrightarrow> P y)" by fact
- have a2: "\<forall>x. (\<forall>y. R y x \<longrightarrow> P y) \<longrightarrow> P x" by fact
- show "P x"
- apply(rule a2[rule_format])
- proof -
- case (goal1 y)
- have a3: "R y x" by fact
- show "P y"
- apply(rule a1[THEN spec[where x=y], THEN mp, OF a3,
- THEN spec[where x=P], THEN mp, OF a2])
- done
- qed
-qed
-
-text {*
- (FIXME check that the code works like as indicated)
-
- The point of these examples is to get a feeling what the automatic proofs
- should do in order to solve all inductive definitions we throw at them. For this
- it is instructive to look at the general construction principle
- of inductive definitions, which we shall do in the next section.
-*}
-
-end