diff -r fcc0e6e54dca -r 74846cb0fff9 CookBook/Package/Ind_Examples.thy --- a/CookBook/Package/Ind_Examples.thy Thu Feb 19 14:44:53 2009 +0000 +++ /dev/null Thu Jan 01 00:00:00 1970 +0000 @@ -1,317 +0,0 @@ -theory Ind_Examples -imports Main LaTeXsugar -begin - -section{* Examples of Inductive Definitions \label{sec:ind-examples} *} - -text {* - Let us first give three examples showing how to define inductive - predicates by hand and then also how to prove by hand characteristic properties - about them, such as introduction rules and induction principles. From - these examples, we will figure out a general method for defining inductive - predicates. The aim in this section is \emph{not} to write proofs that are as - beautiful as possible, but as close as possible to the ML-code we will - develop later. - - - As a first example, let us consider the transitive closure of a relation @{text - R}. It is an inductive predicate characterised by the two introduction rules: - - \begin{center} - @{prop[mode=Axiom] "trcl R x x"} \hspace{5mm} - @{prop[mode=Rule] "R x y \ trcl R y z \ trcl R x z"} - \end{center} - - Note that the @{text trcl} predicate has two different kinds of parameters: the - first parameter @{text R} stays \emph{fixed} throughout the definition, whereas - the second and third parameter changes in the ``recursive call''. This will - become important later on when we deal with fixed parameters and locales. - - Since an inductively defined predicate is the least predicate closed under - a collection of introduction rules, we define the predicate @{text "trcl R x y"} in - such a way that it holds if and only if @{text "P x y"} holds for every predicate - @{text P} closed under the rules above. This gives rise to the definition -*} - -definition "trcl R x y \ - \P. (\x. P x x) \ (\x y z. R x y \ P y z \ P x z) \ P x y" - -text {* - where we quantify over the predicate @{text P}. Note that we have to use the - object implication @{text "\"} and object quantification @{text "\"} for - stating this definition (there is no other way for definitions in - HOL). However, the introduction rules and induction principles derived later - should use the corresponding meta-connectives since they simplify the - reasoning for the user. - - With this definition, the proof of the induction principle for the transitive - closure is almost immediate. It suffices to convert all the meta-level - connectives in the lemma to object-level connectives using the - proof method @{text atomize} (Line 4), expand the definition of @{text trcl} - (Line 5 and 6), eliminate the universal quantifier contained in it (Line 7), - and then solve the goal by assumption (Line 8). - -*} - -lemma %linenos trcl_induct: - assumes asm: "trcl R x y" - shows "(\x. P x x) \ (\x y z. R x y \ P y z \ P x z) \ P x y" -apply(atomize (full)) -apply(cut_tac asm) -apply(unfold trcl_def) -apply(drule spec[where x=P]) -apply(assumption) -done - -text {* - The proofs for the introduction are slightly more complicated. We need to prove - the facs @{prop "trcl R x x"} and @{prop "R x y \ trcl R y z \ trcl R x z"}. - In order to prove the first fact, we again unfold the definition and - then apply the introdution rules for @{text "\"} and @{text "\"} as often as possible. - We then end up in the goal state: -*} - -(*<*)lemma "trcl R x x" -apply (unfold trcl_def) -apply (rule allI impI)+(*>*) -txt {* @{subgoals [display]} *} -(*<*)oops(*>*) - -text {* - The two assumptions correspond to the introduction rules, where @{text "trcl - R"} has been replaced by P. Thus, all we have to do is to eliminate the - universal quantifier in front of the first assumption, and then solve the - goal by assumption. Thus the proof is: -*} - -lemma trcl_base: "trcl R x x" -apply(unfold trcl_def) -apply(rule allI impI)+ -apply(drule spec) -apply(assumption) -done - -text {* - Since the second @{text trcl}-rule has premises, the proof of its - introduction rule is not as easy. After unfolding the definitions and - applying the introduction rules for @{text "\"} and @{text "\"}, we get the - goal state: -*} - -(*<*)lemma "R x y \ trcl R y z \ trcl R x z" -apply (unfold trcl_def) -apply (rule allI impI)+(*>*) -txt {*@{subgoals [display]} *} -(*<*)oops(*>*) - -text {* - The third and fourth assumption correspond to the first and second - introduction rule, respectively, whereas the first and second assumption - corresponds to the pre\-mises of the introduction rule. Since we want to prove - the second introduction rule, we apply the fourth assumption to the goal - @{term "P x z"}. In order for the assumption to be applicable as a rule, we have to - eliminate the universal quantifier and turn the object-level implications - into meta-level ones. This can be accomplished using the @{text rule_format} - attribute. Applying the assumption produces the two new subgoals -*} - -(*<*)lemma "R x y \ trcl R y z \ trcl R x z" -apply (unfold trcl_def) -apply (rule allI impI)+ -proof - - case (goal1 P) - have a4: "\x y z. R x y \ P y z \ P x z" by fact - show ?case - apply (rule a4[rule_format])(*>*) -txt {*@{subgoals [display]} *} -(*<*)oops(*>*) - -text {* - which can be - solved using the first and second assumption. The second assumption again - involves a quantifier and an implications that have to be eliminated before it - can be applied. To avoid potential problems with higher-order unification, - we should explcitly instantiate the universally quantified - predicate variable to @{text "P"} and also match explicitly the implications - with the the third and fourth assumption. This gives the proof: -*} - - -lemma trcl_step: "R x y \ trcl R y z \ trcl R x z" -apply(unfold trcl_def) -apply(rule allI impI)+ -proof - - case (goal1 P) - have a1: "R x y" by fact - have a2: "\P. (\x. P x x) - \ (\x y z. R x y \ P y z \ P x z) \ P y z" by fact - have a3: "\x. P x x" by fact - have a4: "\x y z. R x y \ P y z \ P x z" by fact - show "P x z" - apply(rule a4[rule_format]) - apply(rule a1) - apply(rule a2[THEN spec[where x=P], THEN mp, THEN mp, OF a3, OF a4]) - done -qed - -text {* - It might be surprising that we are not using the automatic tactics available in - Isabelle for proving this lemmas. After all @{text "blast"} would easily - dispense of it. -*} - -lemma trcl_step_blast: "R x y \ trcl R y z \ trcl R x z" -apply(unfold trcl_def) -apply(blast) -done - -text {* - Experience has shown that it is generally a bad idea to rely heavily on - @{text blast}, @{text auto} and the like in automated proofs. The reason is - that you do not have precise control over them (the user can, for example, - declare new intro- or simplification rules that can throw automatic tactics - off course) and also it is very hard to debug proofs involving automatic - tactics whenever something goes wrong. Therefore if possible, automatic - tactics should be avoided or sufficiently constrained. - - The method of defining inductive predicates by impredicative quantification - also generalises to mutually inductive predicates. The next example defines - the predicates @{text even} and @{text odd} characterised by the following - rules: - - \begin{center} - @{prop[mode=Axiom] "even (0::nat)"} \hspace{5mm} - @{prop[mode=Rule] "odd m \ even (Suc m)"} \hspace{5mm} - @{prop[mode=Rule] "even m \ odd (Suc m)"} - \end{center} - - Since the predicates are mutually inductive, each definition - quantifies over both predicates, below named @{text P} and @{text Q}. -*} - -definition "even n \ - \P Q. P 0 \ (\m. Q m \ P (Suc m)) - \ (\m. P m \ Q (Suc m)) \ P n" - -definition "odd n \ - \P Q. P 0 \ (\m. Q m \ P (Suc m)) - \ (\m. P m \ Q (Suc m)) \ Q n" - -text {* - For proving the induction principles, we use exactly the same technique - as in the transitive closure example, namely: -*} - -lemma even_induct: - assumes asm: "even n" - shows "P 0 \ - (\m. Q m \ P (Suc m)) \ (\m. P m \ Q (Suc m)) \ P n" -apply(atomize (full)) -apply(cut_tac asm) -apply(unfold even_def) -apply(drule spec[where x=P]) -apply(drule spec[where x=Q]) -apply(assumption) -done - -text {* - We omit the other induction principle that has @{term "Q n"} as conclusion. - The proofs of the introduction rules are also very similar to the ones in the - @{text "trcl"}-example. We only show the proof of the second introduction rule. -*} - -lemma evenS: "odd m \ even (Suc m)" -apply (unfold odd_def even_def) -apply (rule allI impI)+ -proof - - case (goal1 P) - have a1: "\P Q. P 0 \ (\m. Q m \ P (Suc m)) - \ (\m. P m \ Q (Suc m)) \ Q m" by fact - have a2: "P 0" by fact - have a3: "\m. Q m \ P (Suc m)" by fact - have a4: "\m. P m \ Q (Suc m)" by fact - show "P (Suc m)" - apply(rule a3[rule_format]) - apply(rule a1[THEN spec[where x=P], THEN spec[where x=Q], - THEN mp, THEN mp, THEN mp, OF a2, OF a3, OF a4]) - done -qed - -text {* - As a final example, we define the accessible part of a relation @{text R} characterised - by the introduction rule - - \begin{center} - @{term[mode=Rule] "(\y. R y x \ accpart R y) \ accpart R x"} - \end{center} - - whose premise involves a universal quantifier and an implication. The - definition of @{text accpart} is: -*} - -definition "accpart R x \ \P. (\x. (\y. R y x \ P y) \ P x) \ P x" - -text {* - The proof of the induction principle is again straightforward. -*} - -lemma accpart_induct: - assumes asm: "accpart R x" - shows "(\x. (\y. R y x \ P y) \ P x) \ P x" -apply(atomize (full)) -apply(cut_tac asm) -apply(unfold accpart_def) -apply(drule spec[where x=P]) -apply(assumption) -done - -text {* - Proving the introduction rule is a little more complicated, because the quantifier - and the implication in the premise. We first convert the meta-level universal quantifier - and implication to their object-level counterparts. Unfolding the definition of - @{text accpart} and applying the introduction rules for @{text "\"} and @{text "\"} - yields the following goal state: -*} - -(*<*)lemma accpartI: "(\y. R y x \ accpart R y) \ accpart R x" -apply (unfold accpart_def) -apply (rule allI impI)+(*>*) -txt {* @{subgoals [display]} *} -(*<*)oops(*>*) - -text {* - Applying the second assumption produces a goal state with the new local assumption - @{term "R y x"}, which will then be used to solve the goal @{term "P y"} using the - first assumption. -*} - -lemma %small accpartI: "(\y. R y x \ accpart R y) \ accpart R x" -apply (unfold accpart_def) -apply (rule allI impI)+ -proof - - case (goal1 P) - have a1: "\y. R y x \ - (\P. (\x. (\y. R y x \ P y) \ P x) \ P y)" by fact - have a2: "\x. (\y. R y x \ P y) \ P x" by fact - show "P x" - apply(rule a2[rule_format]) - proof - - case (goal1 y) - have a3: "R y x" by fact - show "P y" - apply(rule a1[THEN spec[where x=y], THEN mp, OF a3, - THEN spec[where x=P], THEN mp, OF a2]) - done - qed -qed - -text {* - (FIXME check that the code works like as indicated) - - The point of these examples is to get a feeling what the automatic proofs - should do in order to solve all inductive definitions we throw at them. For this - it is instructive to look at the general construction principle - of inductive definitions, which we shall do in the next section. -*} - -end