1 theory Ind_Prelims |
1 theory Ind_Prelims |
2 imports Main LaTeXsugar"../Base" Simple_Inductive_Package |
2 imports Main LaTeXsugar "../Base" |
3 begin |
3 begin |
4 |
4 |
5 section{* Preliminaries *} |
5 section{* Preliminaries *} |
6 |
6 |
7 text {* |
7 text {* |
8 The user will just give a specification of an inductive predicate and |
8 The user will just give a specification of inductive predicate(s) and |
9 expects from the package to produce a convenient reasoning |
9 expects from the package to produce a convenient reasoning |
10 infrastructure. This infrastructure needs to be derived from the definition |
10 infrastructure. This infrastructure needs to be derived from the definition |
11 that correspond to the specified predicate. This will roughly mean that the |
11 that correspond to the specified predicate(s). Before we start with |
12 package has three main parts, namely: |
12 explaining all parts of the package, let us first give some examples |
13 |
13 showing how to define inductive predicates and then also how |
14 |
14 to generate a reasoning infrastructure for them. From the examples |
15 \begin{itemize} |
15 we will figure out a general method for |
16 \item parsing the specification and typing the parsed input, |
16 defining inductive predicates. The aim in this section is \emph{not} to |
17 \item making the definitions and deriving the reasoning infrastructure, and |
17 write proofs that are as beautiful as possible, but as close as possible to |
18 \item storing the results in the theory. |
18 the ML-code we will develop in later sections. |
19 \end{itemize} |
19 |
20 |
20 |
21 Before we start with explaining all parts, let us first give three examples |
21 |
22 showing how to define inductive predicates by hand and then also how to |
22 We first consider the transitive closure of a relation @{text R}. The |
23 prove by hand important properties about them. From these examples, we will |
23 ``pencil-and-paper'' specification for the transitive closure is: |
24 figure out a general method for defining inductive predicates. The aim in |
|
25 this section is \emph{not} to write proofs that are as beautiful as |
|
26 possible, but as close as possible to the ML-code we will develop in later |
|
27 sections. |
|
28 |
|
29 |
|
30 We first consider the transitive closure of a relation @{text R}. It is |
|
31 an inductive predicate characterised by the two introduction rules: |
|
32 |
24 |
33 \begin{center}\small |
25 \begin{center}\small |
34 @{prop[mode=Axiom] "trcl R x x"} \hspace{5mm} |
26 @{prop[mode=Axiom] "trcl R x x"} \hspace{5mm} |
35 @{prop[mode=Rule] "R x y \<Longrightarrow> trcl R y z \<Longrightarrow> trcl R x z"} |
27 @{prop[mode=Rule] "R x y \<Longrightarrow> trcl R y z \<Longrightarrow> trcl R x z"} |
36 \end{center} |
28 \end{center} |
37 |
29 |
38 In Isabelle, the user will state for @{term trcl\<iota>} the specification: |
30 The package has to make an appropriate definition. Since an inductively |
39 *} |
|
40 |
|
41 simple_inductive |
|
42 trcl\<iota> :: "('a \<Rightarrow> 'a \<Rightarrow> bool) \<Rightarrow> 'a \<Rightarrow> 'a \<Rightarrow> bool" |
|
43 where |
|
44 base: "trcl\<iota> R x x" |
|
45 | step: "trcl\<iota> R x y \<Longrightarrow> R y z \<Longrightarrow> trcl\<iota> R x z" |
|
46 |
|
47 text {* |
|
48 As said above the package has to make an appropriate definition and provide |
|
49 lemmas to reason about the predicate @{term trcl\<iota>}. Since an inductively |
|
50 defined predicate is the least predicate closed under a collection of |
31 defined predicate is the least predicate closed under a collection of |
51 introduction rules, the predicate @{text "trcl R x y"} can be defined so |
32 introduction rules, the predicate @{text "trcl R x y"} can be defined so |
52 that it holds if and only if @{text "P x y"} holds for every predicate |
33 that it holds if and only if @{text "P x y"} holds for every predicate |
53 @{text P} closed under the rules above. This gives rise to the definition |
34 @{text P} closed under the rules above. This gives rise to the definition |
54 *} |
35 *} |
56 definition "trcl \<equiv> |
37 definition "trcl \<equiv> |
57 \<lambda>R x y. \<forall>P. (\<forall>x. P x x) |
38 \<lambda>R x y. \<forall>P. (\<forall>x. P x x) |
58 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>x y z. R x y \<longrightarrow> P y z \<longrightarrow> P x z) \<longrightarrow> P x y" |
39 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>x y z. R x y \<longrightarrow> P y z \<longrightarrow> P x z) \<longrightarrow> P x y" |
59 |
40 |
60 text {* |
41 text {* |
61 where we quantify over the predicate @{text P}. We have to use the |
42 We have to use the object implication @{text "\<longrightarrow>"} and object quantification |
62 object implication @{text "\<longrightarrow>"} and object quantification @{text "\<forall>"} for |
43 @{text "\<forall>"} for stating this definition (there is no other way for |
63 stating this definition (there is no other way for definitions in |
44 definitions in HOL). However, the introduction rules and induction |
64 HOL). However, the introduction rules and induction principles |
45 principles associated with the transitive closure should use the meta-connectives, |
65 should use the meta-connectives since they simplify the |
46 since they simplify the reasoning for the user. |
66 reasoning for the user. |
47 |
67 |
48 |
68 With this definition, the proof of the induction principle for @{term trcl} |
49 With this definition, the proof of the induction principle for @{term trcl} |
69 is almost immediate. It suffices to convert all the meta-level |
50 is almost immediate. It suffices to convert all the meta-level |
70 connectives in the lemma to object-level connectives using the |
51 connectives in the lemma to object-level connectives using the |
71 proof method @{text atomize} (Line 4), expand the definition of @{term trcl} |
52 proof method @{text atomize} (Line 4 below), expand the definition of @{term trcl} |
72 (Line 5 and 6), eliminate the universal quantifier contained in it (Line~7), |
53 (Line 5 and 6), eliminate the universal quantifier contained in it (Line~7), |
73 and then solve the goal by assumption (Line 8). |
54 and then solve the goal by @{text assumption} (Line 8). |
74 |
55 |
75 *} |
56 *} |
76 |
57 |
77 lemma %linenos trcl_induct: |
58 lemma %linenos trcl_induct: |
78 assumes "trcl R x y" |
59 assumes "trcl R x y" |
79 shows "(\<And>x. P x x) \<Longrightarrow> (\<And>x y z. R x y \<Longrightarrow> P y z \<Longrightarrow> P x z) \<Longrightarrow> P x y" |
60 shows "(\<And>x. P x x) \<Longrightarrow> (\<And>x y z. R x y \<Longrightarrow> P y z \<Longrightarrow> P x z) \<Longrightarrow> P x y" |
80 apply(atomize (full)) |
61 apply(atomize (full)) |
81 apply(cut_tac prems) |
62 apply(cut_tac prems) |
82 apply(unfold trcl_def) |
63 apply(unfold trcl_def) |
83 apply(drule spec[where x=P]) |
64 apply(drule spec[where x=P]) |
84 apply(assumption) |
65 apply(assumption) |
108 apply (rule allI impI)+(*>*) |
89 apply (rule allI impI)+(*>*) |
109 txt {* @{subgoals [display]} *} |
90 txt {* @{subgoals [display]} *} |
110 (*<*)oops(*>*) |
91 (*<*)oops(*>*) |
111 |
92 |
112 text {* |
93 text {* |
113 The two assumptions correspond to the introduction rules. Thus, all we have |
94 The two assumptions come from the definition of @{term trcl} and correspond |
114 to do is to eliminate the universal quantifier in front of the first |
95 to the introduction rules. Thus, all we have to do is to eliminate the |
115 assumption (Line 5), and then solve the goal by assumption (Line 6). |
96 universal quantifier in front of the first assumption (Line 5), and then |
|
97 solve the goal by @{text assumption} (Line 6). |
116 *} |
98 *} |
117 |
99 |
118 text {* |
100 text {* |
119 Next we have to show that the second introduction rule also follows from the |
101 Next we have to show that the second introduction rule also follows from the |
120 definition. Since this rule has premises, the proof is a bit more |
102 definition. Since this rule has premises, the proof is a bit more |
121 involved. After unfolding the definitions and applying the introduction |
103 involved. After unfolding the definitions and applying the introduction |
122 rules for @{text "\<forall>"} and @{text "\<longrightarrow>"} |
104 rules for @{text "\<forall>"} and @{text "\<longrightarrow>"} |
123 *} |
105 *} |
124 |
106 |
125 lemma trcl_step: |
107 lemma trcl_step: |
126 shows "R x y \<Longrightarrow> trcl R y z \<Longrightarrow> trcl R x z" |
108 shows "R x y \<Longrightarrow> trcl R y z \<Longrightarrow> trcl R x z" |
127 apply (unfold trcl_def) |
109 apply (unfold trcl_def) |
128 apply (rule allI impI)+ |
110 apply (rule allI impI)+ |
129 |
111 |
130 txt {* |
112 txt {* |
131 we obtain the goal state |
113 we obtain the goal state |
145 have r2: "\<forall>x y z. R x y \<longrightarrow> P y z \<longrightarrow> P x z" by fact |
127 have r2: "\<forall>x y z. R x y \<longrightarrow> P y z \<longrightarrow> P x z" by fact |
146 show "P x z" |
128 show "P x z" |
147 |
129 |
148 txt {* |
130 txt {* |
149 The assumptions @{text "p1"} and @{text "p2"} correspond to the premises of |
131 The assumptions @{text "p1"} and @{text "p2"} correspond to the premises of |
150 the second introduction rule; the assumptions @{text "r1"} and @{text "r2"} |
132 the second introduction rule (unfolded); the assumptions @{text "r1"} and @{text "r2"} |
151 correspond to the introduction rules. We apply @{text "r2"} to the goal |
133 come from the definition of @{term trcl}. We apply @{text "r2"} to the goal |
152 @{term "P x z"}. In order for the assumption to be applicable as a rule, we |
134 @{term "P x z"}. In order for this assumption to be applicable as a rule, we |
153 have to eliminate the universal quantifier and turn the object-level |
135 have to eliminate the universal quantifier and turn the object-level |
154 implications into meta-level ones. This can be accomplished using the @{text |
136 implications into meta-level ones. This can be accomplished using the @{text |
155 rule_format} attribute. So we continue the proof with: |
137 rule_format} attribute. So we continue the proof with: |
156 |
138 |
157 *} |
139 *} |
193 @{text blast}, @{text auto} and the like in automated proofs. The reason is |
175 @{text blast}, @{text auto} and the like in automated proofs. The reason is |
194 that you do not have precise control over them (the user can, for example, |
176 that you do not have precise control over them (the user can, for example, |
195 declare new intro- or simplification rules that can throw automatic tactics |
177 declare new intro- or simplification rules that can throw automatic tactics |
196 off course) and also it is very hard to debug proofs involving automatic |
178 off course) and also it is very hard to debug proofs involving automatic |
197 tactics whenever something goes wrong. Therefore if possible, automatic |
179 tactics whenever something goes wrong. Therefore if possible, automatic |
198 tactics should be avoided or sufficiently constrained. |
180 tactics should be avoided or be constrained sufficiently. |
199 |
181 |
200 The method of defining inductive predicates by impredicative quantification |
182 The method of defining inductive predicates by impredicative quantification |
201 also generalises to mutually inductive predicates. The next example defines |
183 also generalises to mutually inductive predicates. The next example defines |
202 the predicates @{text even} and @{text odd} characterised by the following |
184 the predicates @{text even} and @{text odd} given by |
203 rules: |
185 |
204 |
|
205 \begin{center}\small |
186 \begin{center}\small |
206 @{prop[mode=Axiom] "even (0::nat)"} \hspace{5mm} |
187 @{prop[mode=Axiom] "even (0::nat)"} \hspace{5mm} |
207 @{prop[mode=Rule] "odd n \<Longrightarrow> even (Suc n)"} \hspace{5mm} |
188 @{prop[mode=Rule] "odd n \<Longrightarrow> even (Suc n)"} \hspace{5mm} |
208 @{prop[mode=Rule] "even n \<Longrightarrow> odd (Suc n)"} |
189 @{prop[mode=Rule] "even n \<Longrightarrow> odd (Suc n)"} |
209 \end{center} |
190 \end{center} |
210 |
191 |
211 The user will state for this inductive definition the specification: |
|
212 *} |
|
213 |
|
214 simple_inductive |
|
215 even and odd |
|
216 where |
|
217 even0: "even 0" |
|
218 | evenS: "odd n \<Longrightarrow> even (Suc n)" |
|
219 | oddS: "even n \<Longrightarrow> odd (Suc n)" |
|
220 |
|
221 text {* |
|
222 Since the predicates @{term even} and @{term odd} are mutually inductive, each |
192 Since the predicates @{term even} and @{term odd} are mutually inductive, each |
223 corresponding definition must quantify over both predicates (we name them |
193 corresponding definition must quantify over both predicates (we name them |
224 below @{text "P"} and @{text "Q"}). |
194 below @{text "P"} and @{text "Q"}). |
225 *} |
195 *} |
226 |
196 |
227 definition "even\<iota> \<equiv> |
197 definition "even \<equiv> |
228 \<lambda>n. \<forall>P Q. P 0 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. Q m \<longrightarrow> P (Suc m)) |
198 \<lambda>n. \<forall>P Q. P 0 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. Q m \<longrightarrow> P (Suc m)) |
229 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. P m \<longrightarrow> Q (Suc m)) \<longrightarrow> P n" |
199 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. P m \<longrightarrow> Q (Suc m)) \<longrightarrow> P n" |
230 |
200 |
231 definition "odd\<iota> \<equiv> |
201 definition "odd \<equiv> |
232 \<lambda>n. \<forall>P Q. P 0 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. Q m \<longrightarrow> P (Suc m)) |
202 \<lambda>n. \<forall>P Q. P 0 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. Q m \<longrightarrow> P (Suc m)) |
233 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. P m \<longrightarrow> Q (Suc m)) \<longrightarrow> Q n" |
203 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. P m \<longrightarrow> Q (Suc m)) \<longrightarrow> Q n" |
234 |
204 |
235 text {* |
205 text {* |
236 For proving the induction principles, we use exactly the same technique |
206 For proving the induction principles, we use exactly the same technique |
237 as in the transitive closure example, namely: |
207 as in the transitive closure example, namely: |
238 *} |
208 *} |
239 |
209 |
240 lemma even_induct: |
210 lemma even_induct: |
241 assumes "even n" |
211 assumes "even n" |
242 shows "P 0 \<Longrightarrow> |
212 shows "P 0 \<Longrightarrow> (\<And>m. Q m \<Longrightarrow> P (Suc m)) \<Longrightarrow> (\<And>m. P m \<Longrightarrow> Q (Suc m)) \<Longrightarrow> P n" |
243 (\<And>m. Q m \<Longrightarrow> P (Suc m)) \<Longrightarrow> (\<And>m. P m \<Longrightarrow> Q (Suc m)) \<Longrightarrow> P n" |
|
244 apply(atomize (full)) |
213 apply(atomize (full)) |
245 apply(cut_tac prems) |
214 apply(cut_tac prems) |
246 apply(unfold even_def) |
215 apply(unfold even_def) |
247 apply(drule spec[where x=P]) |
216 apply(drule spec[where x=P]) |
248 apply(drule spec[where x=Q]) |
217 apply(drule spec[where x=Q]) |
250 done |
219 done |
251 |
220 |
252 text {* |
221 text {* |
253 The only difference with the proof @{text "trcl_induct"} is that we have to |
222 The only difference with the proof @{text "trcl_induct"} is that we have to |
254 instantiate here two universal quantifiers. We omit the other induction |
223 instantiate here two universal quantifiers. We omit the other induction |
255 principle that has @{term "Q n"} as conclusion. The proofs of the |
224 principle that has @{prop "even n"} as premise and @{term "Q n"} as conclusion. |
256 introduction rules are also very similar to the ones in the @{text |
225 The proofs of the introduction rules are also very similar to the ones in |
257 "trcl"}-example. We only show the proof of the second introduction rule. |
226 the @{text "trcl"}-example. We only show the proof of the second introduction |
258 |
227 rule. |
259 *} |
228 *} |
260 |
229 |
261 lemma %linenos evenS: |
230 lemma %linenos evenS: |
262 shows "odd m \<Longrightarrow> even (Suc m)" |
231 shows "odd m \<Longrightarrow> even (Suc m)" |
263 apply (unfold odd_def even_def) |
232 apply (unfold odd_def even_def) |
264 apply (rule allI impI)+ |
233 apply (rule allI impI)+ |
265 proof - |
234 proof - |
266 case (goal1 P Q) |
235 case (goal1 P Q) |
267 have p1: "\<forall>P Q. P 0 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. Q m \<longrightarrow> P (Suc m)) |
236 have p1: "\<forall>P Q. P 0 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. Q m \<longrightarrow> P (Suc m)) |
275 THEN mp, THEN mp, THEN mp, OF r1, OF r2, OF r3]) |
244 THEN mp, THEN mp, THEN mp, OF r1, OF r2, OF r3]) |
276 done |
245 done |
277 qed |
246 qed |
278 |
247 |
279 text {* |
248 text {* |
|
249 The interesting lines are 7 to 15. The assumptions fall into two categories: |
|
250 @{text p1} corresponds to the premise of the introduction rule; @{text "r1"} |
|
251 to @{text "r3"} come from the definition of @{text "even"}. |
280 In Line 13, we apply the assumption @{text "r2"} (since we prove the second |
252 In Line 13, we apply the assumption @{text "r2"} (since we prove the second |
281 introduction rule). In Lines 14 and 15 we apply assumption @{text "p1"} (if |
253 introduction rule). In Lines 14 and 15 we apply assumption @{text "p1"} (if |
282 the second introduction rule had more premises we have to do that for all |
254 the second introduction rule had more premises we have to do that for all |
283 of them). In order for this assumption to be applicable, the quantifiers |
255 of them). In order for this assumption to be applicable, the quantifiers |
284 need to be instantiated and then also the implications need to be resolved |
256 need to be instantiated and then also the implications need to be resolved |
285 with the other rules. |
257 with the other rules. |
286 |
258 |
287 |
259 Next we define the accessible part of a relation @{text R} given by |
288 As a final example, we define the accessible part of a relation @{text R} characterised |
260 the single rule: |
289 by the introduction rule |
261 |
290 |
|
291 \begin{center}\small |
262 \begin{center}\small |
292 \mbox{\inferrule{@{term "\<And>y. R y x \<Longrightarrow> accpart R y"}}{@{term "accpart R x"}}} |
263 \mbox{\inferrule{@{term "\<And>y. R y x \<Longrightarrow> accpart R y"}}{@{term "accpart R x"}}} |
293 \end{center} |
264 \end{center} |
294 |
265 |
295 whose premise involves a universal quantifier and an implication. The |
266 The definition of @{text "accpart"} is: |
296 definition of @{text accpart} is: |
|
297 *} |
267 *} |
298 |
268 |
299 definition "accpart \<equiv> \<lambda>R x. \<forall>P. (\<forall>x. (\<forall>y. R y x \<longrightarrow> P y) \<longrightarrow> P x) \<longrightarrow> P x" |
269 definition "accpart \<equiv> \<lambda>R x. \<forall>P. (\<forall>x. (\<forall>y. R y x \<longrightarrow> P y) \<longrightarrow> P x) \<longrightarrow> P x" |
300 |
270 |
301 text {* |
271 text {* |
302 The proof of the induction principle is again straightforward. |
272 The proof of the induction principle is again straightforward and omitted. |
303 *} |
273 Proving the introduction rule is a little more complicated, because the |
304 |
274 quantifier and the implication in the premise. The proof is as follows. |
305 lemma accpart_induct: |
|
306 assumes "accpart R x" |
|
307 shows "(\<And>x. (\<And>y. R y x \<Longrightarrow> P y) \<Longrightarrow> P x) \<Longrightarrow> P x" |
|
308 apply(atomize (full)) |
|
309 apply(cut_tac prems) |
|
310 apply(unfold accpart_def) |
|
311 apply(drule spec[where x=P]) |
|
312 apply(assumption) |
|
313 done |
|
314 |
|
315 text {* |
|
316 Proving the introduction rule is a little more complicated, because the quantifier |
|
317 and the implication in the premise. The proof is as follows. |
|
318 *} |
275 *} |
319 |
276 |
320 lemma %linenos accpartI: |
277 lemma %linenos accpartI: |
321 shows "(\<And>y. R y x \<Longrightarrow> accpart R y) \<Longrightarrow> accpart R x" |
278 shows "(\<And>y. R y x \<Longrightarrow> accpart R y) \<Longrightarrow> accpart R x" |
322 apply (unfold accpart_def) |
279 apply (unfold accpart_def) |
323 apply (rule allI impI)+ |
280 apply (rule allI impI)+ |
324 proof - |
281 proof - |
325 case (goal1 P) |
282 case (goal1 P) |
326 have p1: "\<And>y. R y x \<Longrightarrow> |
283 have p1: "\<And>y. R y x \<Longrightarrow> |
336 done |
293 done |
337 qed |
294 qed |
338 qed |
295 qed |
339 |
296 |
340 text {* |
297 text {* |
341 In Line 11, applying the assumption @{text "r1"} generates a goal state with |
298 As you can see, there are now two subproofs. The assumptions fall again into |
342 the new local assumption @{term "R y x"}, named @{text "r1_prem"} in the |
299 two categories (Lines 7 to 9). In Line 11, applying the assumption @{text |
343 proof above (Line 14). This local assumption is used to solve |
300 "r1"} generates a goal state with the new local assumption @{term "R y x"}, |
344 the goal @{term "P y"} with the help of assumption @{text "p1"}. |
301 named @{text "r1_prem"} in the second subproof (Line 14). This local assumption is |
345 |
302 used to solve the goal @{term "P y"} with the help of assumption @{text |
346 The point of these examples is to get a feeling what the automatic proofs |
303 "p1"}. |
347 should do in order to solve all inductive definitions we throw at them. |
304 |
348 This is usually the first step in writing a package. We next explain |
305 |
|
306 \begin{exercise} |
|
307 Give the definition for the freshness predicate for lambda-terms. The rules |
|
308 for this predicate are: |
|
309 |
|
310 \begin{center}\small |
|
311 @{prop[mode=Rule] "a\<noteq>b \<Longrightarrow> fresh a (Var b)"}\hspace{5mm} |
|
312 @{prop[mode=Rule] "\<lbrakk>fresh a t; fresh a s\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> fresh a (App t s)"}\\[2mm] |
|
313 @{prop[mode=Axiom] "fresh a (Lam a t)"}\hspace{5mm} |
|
314 @{prop[mode=Rule] "\<lbrakk>a\<noteq>b; fresh a t\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> fresh a (Lam b t)"} |
|
315 \end{center} |
|
316 |
|
317 From the definition derive the induction principle and the introduction |
|
318 rules. |
|
319 \end{exercise} |
|
320 |
|
321 The point of all these examples is to get a feeling what the automatic |
|
322 proofs should do in order to solve all inductive definitions we throw at |
|
323 them. This is usually the first step in writing a package. We next explain |
349 the parsing and typing part of the package. |
324 the parsing and typing part of the package. |
350 |
325 |
351 *} |
326 *} |
352 (*<*)end(*>*) |
327 (*<*)end(*>*) |