diff -r a9eb69749c93 -r 1dc03eaa7cb9 ProgTutorial/Package/Ind_Prelims.thy --- a/ProgTutorial/Package/Ind_Prelims.thy Mon Mar 30 17:40:20 2009 +0200 +++ b/ProgTutorial/Package/Ind_Prelims.thy Wed Apr 01 12:28:14 2009 +0100 @@ -1,52 +1,33 @@ theory Ind_Prelims -imports Main LaTeXsugar"../Base" Simple_Inductive_Package +imports Main LaTeXsugar "../Base" begin section{* Preliminaries *} text {* - The user will just give a specification of an inductive predicate and + The user will just give a specification of inductive predicate(s) and expects from the package to produce a convenient reasoning infrastructure. This infrastructure needs to be derived from the definition - that correspond to the specified predicate. This will roughly mean that the - package has three main parts, namely: + that correspond to the specified predicate(s). Before we start with + explaining all parts of the package, let us first give some examples + showing how to define inductive predicates and then also how + to generate a reasoning infrastructure for them. From the examples + we will figure out a general method for + defining inductive predicates. The aim in this section is \emph{not} to + write proofs that are as beautiful as possible, but as close as possible to + the ML-code we will develop in later sections. - \begin{itemize} - \item parsing the specification and typing the parsed input, - \item making the definitions and deriving the reasoning infrastructure, and - \item storing the results in the theory. - \end{itemize} - Before we start with explaining all parts, let us first give three examples - showing how to define inductive predicates by hand and then also how to - prove by hand important properties about them. From these examples, we will - figure out a general method for defining inductive predicates. The aim in - this section is \emph{not} to write proofs that are as beautiful as - possible, but as close as possible to the ML-code we will develop in later - sections. - - - We first consider the transitive closure of a relation @{text R}. It is - an inductive predicate characterised by the two introduction rules: + We first consider the transitive closure of a relation @{text R}. The + ``pencil-and-paper'' specification for the transitive closure is: \begin{center}\small @{prop[mode=Axiom] "trcl R x x"} \hspace{5mm} @{prop[mode=Rule] "R x y \ trcl R y z \ trcl R x z"} \end{center} - In Isabelle, the user will state for @{term trcl\} the specification: -*} - -simple_inductive - trcl\ :: "('a \ 'a \ bool) \ 'a \ 'a \ bool" -where - base: "trcl\ R x x" -| step: "trcl\ R x y \ R y z \ trcl\ R x z" - -text {* - As said above the package has to make an appropriate definition and provide - lemmas to reason about the predicate @{term trcl\}. Since an inductively + The package has to make an appropriate definition. Since an inductively defined predicate is the least predicate closed under a collection of introduction rules, the predicate @{text "trcl R x y"} can be defined so that it holds if and only if @{text "P x y"} holds for every predicate @@ -58,25 +39,25 @@ \ (\x y z. R x y \ P y z \ P x z) \ P x y" text {* - where we quantify over the predicate @{text P}. We have to use the - object implication @{text "\"} and object quantification @{text "\"} for - stating this definition (there is no other way for definitions in - HOL). However, the introduction rules and induction principles - should use the meta-connectives since they simplify the - reasoning for the user. + We have to use the object implication @{text "\"} and object quantification + @{text "\"} for stating this definition (there is no other way for + definitions in HOL). However, the introduction rules and induction + principles associated with the transitive closure should use the meta-connectives, + since they simplify the reasoning for the user. + With this definition, the proof of the induction principle for @{term trcl} is almost immediate. It suffices to convert all the meta-level connectives in the lemma to object-level connectives using the - proof method @{text atomize} (Line 4), expand the definition of @{term trcl} + proof method @{text atomize} (Line 4 below), expand the definition of @{term trcl} (Line 5 and 6), eliminate the universal quantifier contained in it (Line~7), - and then solve the goal by assumption (Line 8). + and then solve the goal by @{text assumption} (Line 8). *} lemma %linenos trcl_induct: - assumes "trcl R x y" - shows "(\x. P x x) \ (\x y z. R x y \ P y z \ P x z) \ P x y" +assumes "trcl R x y" +shows "(\x. P x x) \ (\x y z. R x y \ P y z \ P x z) \ P x y" apply(atomize (full)) apply(cut_tac prems) apply(unfold trcl_def) @@ -90,7 +71,7 @@ *} lemma %linenos trcl_base: - shows "trcl R x x" +shows "trcl R x x" apply(unfold trcl_def) apply(rule allI impI)+ apply(drule spec) @@ -110,9 +91,10 @@ (*<*)oops(*>*) text {* - The two assumptions correspond to the introduction rules. Thus, all we have - to do is to eliminate the universal quantifier in front of the first - assumption (Line 5), and then solve the goal by assumption (Line 6). + The two assumptions come from the definition of @{term trcl} and correspond + to the introduction rules. Thus, all we have to do is to eliminate the + universal quantifier in front of the first assumption (Line 5), and then + solve the goal by @{text assumption} (Line 6). *} text {* @@ -123,7 +105,7 @@ *} lemma trcl_step: - shows "R x y \ trcl R y z \ trcl R x z" +shows "R x y \ trcl R y z \ trcl R x z" apply (unfold trcl_def) apply (rule allI impI)+ @@ -147,9 +129,9 @@ txt {* The assumptions @{text "p1"} and @{text "p2"} correspond to the premises of - the second introduction rule; the assumptions @{text "r1"} and @{text "r2"} - correspond to the introduction rules. We apply @{text "r2"} to the goal - @{term "P x z"}. In order for the assumption to be applicable as a rule, we + the second introduction rule (unfolded); the assumptions @{text "r1"} and @{text "r2"} + come from the definition of @{term trcl}. We apply @{text "r2"} to the goal + @{term "P x z"}. In order for this assumption to be applicable as a rule, we have to eliminate the universal quantifier and turn the object-level implications into meta-level ones. This can be accomplished using the @{text rule_format} attribute. So we continue the proof with: @@ -183,7 +165,7 @@ *} lemma trcl_step_blast: - shows "R x y \ trcl R y z \ trcl R x z" +shows "R x y \ trcl R y z \ trcl R x z" apply(unfold trcl_def) apply(blast) done @@ -195,40 +177,28 @@ declare new intro- or simplification rules that can throw automatic tactics off course) and also it is very hard to debug proofs involving automatic tactics whenever something goes wrong. Therefore if possible, automatic - tactics should be avoided or sufficiently constrained. + tactics should be avoided or be constrained sufficiently. The method of defining inductive predicates by impredicative quantification also generalises to mutually inductive predicates. The next example defines - the predicates @{text even} and @{text odd} characterised by the following - rules: - + the predicates @{text even} and @{text odd} given by + \begin{center}\small @{prop[mode=Axiom] "even (0::nat)"} \hspace{5mm} @{prop[mode=Rule] "odd n \ even (Suc n)"} \hspace{5mm} @{prop[mode=Rule] "even n \ odd (Suc n)"} \end{center} - - The user will state for this inductive definition the specification: -*} -simple_inductive - even and odd -where - even0: "even 0" -| evenS: "odd n \ even (Suc n)" -| oddS: "even n \ odd (Suc n)" - -text {* Since the predicates @{term even} and @{term odd} are mutually inductive, each corresponding definition must quantify over both predicates (we name them below @{text "P"} and @{text "Q"}). *} -definition "even\ \ +definition "even \ \n. \P Q. P 0 \ (\m. Q m \ P (Suc m)) \ (\m. P m \ Q (Suc m)) \ P n" -definition "odd\ \ +definition "odd \ \n. \P Q. P 0 \ (\m. Q m \ P (Suc m)) \ (\m. P m \ Q (Suc m)) \ Q n" @@ -238,9 +208,8 @@ *} lemma even_induct: - assumes "even n" - shows "P 0 \ - (\m. Q m \ P (Suc m)) \ (\m. P m \ Q (Suc m)) \ P n" +assumes "even n" +shows "P 0 \ (\m. Q m \ P (Suc m)) \ (\m. P m \ Q (Suc m)) \ P n" apply(atomize (full)) apply(cut_tac prems) apply(unfold even_def) @@ -252,14 +221,14 @@ text {* The only difference with the proof @{text "trcl_induct"} is that we have to instantiate here two universal quantifiers. We omit the other induction - principle that has @{term "Q n"} as conclusion. The proofs of the - introduction rules are also very similar to the ones in the @{text - "trcl"}-example. We only show the proof of the second introduction rule. - + principle that has @{prop "even n"} as premise and @{term "Q n"} as conclusion. + The proofs of the introduction rules are also very similar to the ones in + the @{text "trcl"}-example. We only show the proof of the second introduction + rule. *} lemma %linenos evenS: - shows "odd m \ even (Suc m)" +shows "odd m \ even (Suc m)" apply (unfold odd_def even_def) apply (rule allI impI)+ proof - @@ -277,6 +246,9 @@ qed text {* + The interesting lines are 7 to 15. The assumptions fall into two categories: + @{text p1} corresponds to the premise of the introduction rule; @{text "r1"} + to @{text "r3"} come from the definition of @{text "even"}. In Line 13, we apply the assumption @{text "r2"} (since we prove the second introduction rule). In Lines 14 and 15 we apply assumption @{text "p1"} (if the second introduction rule had more premises we have to do that for all @@ -284,41 +256,26 @@ need to be instantiated and then also the implications need to be resolved with the other rules. + Next we define the accessible part of a relation @{text R} given by + the single rule: - As a final example, we define the accessible part of a relation @{text R} characterised - by the introduction rule - \begin{center}\small \mbox{\inferrule{@{term "\y. R y x \ accpart R y"}}{@{term "accpart R x"}}} \end{center} - whose premise involves a universal quantifier and an implication. The - definition of @{text accpart} is: + The definition of @{text "accpart"} is: *} definition "accpart \ \R x. \P. (\x. (\y. R y x \ P y) \ P x) \ P x" text {* - The proof of the induction principle is again straightforward. -*} - -lemma accpart_induct: - assumes "accpart R x" - shows "(\x. (\y. R y x \ P y) \ P x) \ P x" -apply(atomize (full)) -apply(cut_tac prems) -apply(unfold accpart_def) -apply(drule spec[where x=P]) -apply(assumption) -done - -text {* - Proving the introduction rule is a little more complicated, because the quantifier - and the implication in the premise. The proof is as follows. + The proof of the induction principle is again straightforward and omitted. + Proving the introduction rule is a little more complicated, because the + quantifier and the implication in the premise. The proof is as follows. *} lemma %linenos accpartI: - shows "(\y. R y x \ accpart R y) \ accpart R x" +shows "(\y. R y x \ accpart R y) \ accpart R x" apply (unfold accpart_def) apply (rule allI impI)+ proof - @@ -338,14 +295,32 @@ qed text {* - In Line 11, applying the assumption @{text "r1"} generates a goal state with - the new local assumption @{term "R y x"}, named @{text "r1_prem"} in the - proof above (Line 14). This local assumption is used to solve - the goal @{term "P y"} with the help of assumption @{text "p1"}. + As you can see, there are now two subproofs. The assumptions fall again into + two categories (Lines 7 to 9). In Line 11, applying the assumption @{text + "r1"} generates a goal state with the new local assumption @{term "R y x"}, + named @{text "r1_prem"} in the second subproof (Line 14). This local assumption is + used to solve the goal @{term "P y"} with the help of assumption @{text + "p1"}. + - The point of these examples is to get a feeling what the automatic proofs - should do in order to solve all inductive definitions we throw at them. - This is usually the first step in writing a package. We next explain + \begin{exercise} + Give the definition for the freshness predicate for lambda-terms. The rules + for this predicate are: + + \begin{center}\small + @{prop[mode=Rule] "a\b \ fresh a (Var b)"}\hspace{5mm} + @{prop[mode=Rule] "\fresh a t; fresh a s\ \ fresh a (App t s)"}\\[2mm] + @{prop[mode=Axiom] "fresh a (Lam a t)"}\hspace{5mm} + @{prop[mode=Rule] "\a\b; fresh a t\ \ fresh a (Lam b t)"} + \end{center} + + From the definition derive the induction principle and the introduction + rules. + \end{exercise} + + The point of all these examples is to get a feeling what the automatic + proofs should do in order to solve all inductive definitions we throw at + them. This is usually the first step in writing a package. We next explain the parsing and typing part of the package. *}