|
1 theory Ind_Prelims |
|
2 imports Main LaTeXsugar"../Base" Simple_Inductive_Package |
|
3 begin |
|
4 |
|
5 section{* Preliminaries *} |
|
6 |
|
7 text {* |
|
8 The user will just give a specification of an inductive predicate and |
|
9 expects from the package to produce a convenient reasoning |
|
10 infrastructure. This infrastructure needs to be derived from the definition |
|
11 that correspond to the specified predicate. This will roughly mean that the |
|
12 package has three main parts, namely: |
|
13 |
|
14 |
|
15 \begin{itemize} |
|
16 \item parsing the specification and typing the parsed input, |
|
17 \item making the definitions and deriving the reasoning infrastructure, and |
|
18 \item storing the results in the theory. |
|
19 \end{itemize} |
|
20 |
|
21 Before we start with explaining all parts, let us first give three examples |
|
22 showing how to define inductive predicates by hand and then also how to |
|
23 prove by hand important properties about them. From these examples, we will |
|
24 figure out a general method for defining inductive predicates. The aim in |
|
25 this section is \emph{not} to write proofs that are as beautiful as |
|
26 possible, but as close as possible to the ML-code we will develop in later |
|
27 sections. |
|
28 |
|
29 |
|
30 We first consider the transitive closure of a relation @{text R}. It is |
|
31 an inductive predicate characterised by the two introduction rules: |
|
32 |
|
33 \begin{center}\small |
|
34 @{prop[mode=Axiom] "trcl R x x"} \hspace{5mm} |
|
35 @{prop[mode=Rule] "R x y \<Longrightarrow> trcl R y z \<Longrightarrow> trcl R x z"} |
|
36 \end{center} |
|
37 |
|
38 In Isabelle, the user will state for @{term trcl\<iota>} the specification: |
|
39 *} |
|
40 |
|
41 simple_inductive |
|
42 trcl\<iota> :: "('a \<Rightarrow> 'a \<Rightarrow> bool) \<Rightarrow> 'a \<Rightarrow> 'a \<Rightarrow> bool" |
|
43 where |
|
44 base: "trcl\<iota> R x x" |
|
45 | step: "trcl\<iota> R x y \<Longrightarrow> R y z \<Longrightarrow> trcl\<iota> R x z" |
|
46 |
|
47 text {* |
|
48 As said above the package has to make an appropriate definition and provide |
|
49 lemmas to reason about the predicate @{term trcl\<iota>}. Since an inductively |
|
50 defined predicate is the least predicate closed under a collection of |
|
51 introduction rules, the predicate @{text "trcl R x y"} can be defined so |
|
52 that it holds if and only if @{text "P x y"} holds for every predicate |
|
53 @{text P} closed under the rules above. This gives rise to the definition |
|
54 *} |
|
55 |
|
56 definition "trcl \<equiv> |
|
57 \<lambda>R x y. \<forall>P. (\<forall>x. P x x) |
|
58 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>x y z. R x y \<longrightarrow> P y z \<longrightarrow> P x z) \<longrightarrow> P x y" |
|
59 |
|
60 text {* |
|
61 where we quantify over the predicate @{text P}. We have to use the |
|
62 object implication @{text "\<longrightarrow>"} and object quantification @{text "\<forall>"} for |
|
63 stating this definition (there is no other way for definitions in |
|
64 HOL). However, the introduction rules and induction principles |
|
65 should use the meta-connectives since they simplify the |
|
66 reasoning for the user. |
|
67 |
|
68 With this definition, the proof of the induction principle for @{term trcl} |
|
69 is almost immediate. It suffices to convert all the meta-level |
|
70 connectives in the lemma to object-level connectives using the |
|
71 proof method @{text atomize} (Line 4), expand the definition of @{term trcl} |
|
72 (Line 5 and 6), eliminate the universal quantifier contained in it (Line~7), |
|
73 and then solve the goal by assumption (Line 8). |
|
74 |
|
75 *} |
|
76 |
|
77 lemma %linenos trcl_induct: |
|
78 assumes "trcl R x y" |
|
79 shows "(\<And>x. P x x) \<Longrightarrow> (\<And>x y z. R x y \<Longrightarrow> P y z \<Longrightarrow> P x z) \<Longrightarrow> P x y" |
|
80 apply(atomize (full)) |
|
81 apply(cut_tac prems) |
|
82 apply(unfold trcl_def) |
|
83 apply(drule spec[where x=P]) |
|
84 apply(assumption) |
|
85 done |
|
86 |
|
87 text {* |
|
88 The proofs for the introduction rules are slightly more complicated. |
|
89 For the first one, we need to prove the following lemma: |
|
90 *} |
|
91 |
|
92 lemma %linenos trcl_base: |
|
93 shows "trcl R x x" |
|
94 apply(unfold trcl_def) |
|
95 apply(rule allI impI)+ |
|
96 apply(drule spec) |
|
97 apply(assumption) |
|
98 done |
|
99 |
|
100 text {* |
|
101 We again unfold first the definition and apply introduction rules |
|
102 for @{text "\<forall>"} and @{text "\<longrightarrow>"} as often as possible (Lines 3 and 4). |
|
103 We then end up in the goal state: |
|
104 *} |
|
105 |
|
106 (*<*)lemma "trcl R x x" |
|
107 apply (unfold trcl_def) |
|
108 apply (rule allI impI)+(*>*) |
|
109 txt {* @{subgoals [display]} *} |
|
110 (*<*)oops(*>*) |
|
111 |
|
112 text {* |
|
113 The two assumptions correspond to the introduction rules. Thus, all we have |
|
114 to do is to eliminate the universal quantifier in front of the first |
|
115 assumption (Line 5), and then solve the goal by assumption (Line 6). |
|
116 *} |
|
117 |
|
118 text {* |
|
119 Next we have to show that the second introduction rule also follows from the |
|
120 definition. Since this rule has premises, the proof is a bit more |
|
121 involved. After unfolding the definitions and applying the introduction |
|
122 rules for @{text "\<forall>"} and @{text "\<longrightarrow>"} |
|
123 *} |
|
124 |
|
125 lemma trcl_step: |
|
126 shows "R x y \<Longrightarrow> trcl R y z \<Longrightarrow> trcl R x z" |
|
127 apply (unfold trcl_def) |
|
128 apply (rule allI impI)+ |
|
129 |
|
130 txt {* |
|
131 we obtain the goal state |
|
132 |
|
133 @{subgoals [display]} |
|
134 |
|
135 To see better where we are, let us explicitly name the assumptions |
|
136 by starting a subproof. |
|
137 *} |
|
138 |
|
139 proof - |
|
140 case (goal1 P) |
|
141 have p1: "R x y" by fact |
|
142 have p2: "\<forall>P. (\<forall>x. P x x) |
|
143 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>x y z. R x y \<longrightarrow> P y z \<longrightarrow> P x z) \<longrightarrow> P y z" by fact |
|
144 have r1: "\<forall>x. P x x" by fact |
|
145 have r2: "\<forall>x y z. R x y \<longrightarrow> P y z \<longrightarrow> P x z" by fact |
|
146 show "P x z" |
|
147 |
|
148 txt {* |
|
149 The assumptions @{text "p1"} and @{text "p2"} correspond to the premises of |
|
150 the second introduction rule; the assumptions @{text "r1"} and @{text "r2"} |
|
151 correspond to the introduction rules. We apply @{text "r2"} to the goal |
|
152 @{term "P x z"}. In order for the assumption to be applicable as a rule, we |
|
153 have to eliminate the universal quantifier and turn the object-level |
|
154 implications into meta-level ones. This can be accomplished using the @{text |
|
155 rule_format} attribute. So we continue the proof with: |
|
156 |
|
157 *} |
|
158 |
|
159 apply (rule r2[rule_format]) |
|
160 |
|
161 txt {* |
|
162 This gives us two new subgoals |
|
163 |
|
164 @{subgoals [display]} |
|
165 |
|
166 which can be solved using assumptions @{text p1} and @{text p2}. The latter |
|
167 involves a quantifier and implications that have to be eliminated before it |
|
168 can be applied. To avoid potential problems with higher-order unification, |
|
169 we explicitly instantiate the quantifier to @{text "P"} and also match |
|
170 explicitly the implications with @{text "r1"} and @{text "r2"}. This gives |
|
171 the proof: |
|
172 *} |
|
173 |
|
174 apply(rule p1) |
|
175 apply(rule p2[THEN spec[where x=P], THEN mp, THEN mp, OF r1, OF r2]) |
|
176 done |
|
177 qed |
|
178 |
|
179 text {* |
|
180 Now we are done. It might be surprising that we are not using the automatic |
|
181 tactics available in Isabelle for proving this lemmas. After all @{text |
|
182 "blast"} would easily dispense of it. |
|
183 *} |
|
184 |
|
185 lemma trcl_step_blast: |
|
186 shows "R x y \<Longrightarrow> trcl R y z \<Longrightarrow> trcl R x z" |
|
187 apply(unfold trcl_def) |
|
188 apply(blast) |
|
189 done |
|
190 |
|
191 text {* |
|
192 Experience has shown that it is generally a bad idea to rely heavily on |
|
193 @{text blast}, @{text auto} and the like in automated proofs. The reason is |
|
194 that you do not have precise control over them (the user can, for example, |
|
195 declare new intro- or simplification rules that can throw automatic tactics |
|
196 off course) and also it is very hard to debug proofs involving automatic |
|
197 tactics whenever something goes wrong. Therefore if possible, automatic |
|
198 tactics should be avoided or sufficiently constrained. |
|
199 |
|
200 The method of defining inductive predicates by impredicative quantification |
|
201 also generalises to mutually inductive predicates. The next example defines |
|
202 the predicates @{text even} and @{text odd} characterised by the following |
|
203 rules: |
|
204 |
|
205 \begin{center}\small |
|
206 @{prop[mode=Axiom] "even (0::nat)"} \hspace{5mm} |
|
207 @{prop[mode=Rule] "odd n \<Longrightarrow> even (Suc n)"} \hspace{5mm} |
|
208 @{prop[mode=Rule] "even n \<Longrightarrow> odd (Suc n)"} |
|
209 \end{center} |
|
210 |
|
211 The user will state for this inductive definition the specification: |
|
212 *} |
|
213 |
|
214 simple_inductive |
|
215 even and odd |
|
216 where |
|
217 even0: "even 0" |
|
218 | evenS: "odd n \<Longrightarrow> even (Suc n)" |
|
219 | oddS: "even n \<Longrightarrow> odd (Suc n)" |
|
220 |
|
221 text {* |
|
222 Since the predicates @{term even} and @{term odd} are mutually inductive, each |
|
223 corresponding definition must quantify over both predicates (we name them |
|
224 below @{text "P"} and @{text "Q"}). |
|
225 *} |
|
226 |
|
227 definition "even\<iota> \<equiv> |
|
228 \<lambda>n. \<forall>P Q. P 0 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. Q m \<longrightarrow> P (Suc m)) |
|
229 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. P m \<longrightarrow> Q (Suc m)) \<longrightarrow> P n" |
|
230 |
|
231 definition "odd\<iota> \<equiv> |
|
232 \<lambda>n. \<forall>P Q. P 0 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. Q m \<longrightarrow> P (Suc m)) |
|
233 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. P m \<longrightarrow> Q (Suc m)) \<longrightarrow> Q n" |
|
234 |
|
235 text {* |
|
236 For proving the induction principles, we use exactly the same technique |
|
237 as in the transitive closure example, namely: |
|
238 *} |
|
239 |
|
240 lemma even_induct: |
|
241 assumes "even n" |
|
242 shows "P 0 \<Longrightarrow> |
|
243 (\<And>m. Q m \<Longrightarrow> P (Suc m)) \<Longrightarrow> (\<And>m. P m \<Longrightarrow> Q (Suc m)) \<Longrightarrow> P n" |
|
244 apply(atomize (full)) |
|
245 apply(cut_tac prems) |
|
246 apply(unfold even_def) |
|
247 apply(drule spec[where x=P]) |
|
248 apply(drule spec[where x=Q]) |
|
249 apply(assumption) |
|
250 done |
|
251 |
|
252 text {* |
|
253 The only difference with the proof @{text "trcl_induct"} is that we have to |
|
254 instantiate here two universal quantifiers. We omit the other induction |
|
255 principle that has @{term "Q n"} as conclusion. The proofs of the |
|
256 introduction rules are also very similar to the ones in the @{text |
|
257 "trcl"}-example. We only show the proof of the second introduction rule. |
|
258 |
|
259 *} |
|
260 |
|
261 lemma %linenos evenS: |
|
262 shows "odd m \<Longrightarrow> even (Suc m)" |
|
263 apply (unfold odd_def even_def) |
|
264 apply (rule allI impI)+ |
|
265 proof - |
|
266 case (goal1 P Q) |
|
267 have p1: "\<forall>P Q. P 0 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. Q m \<longrightarrow> P (Suc m)) |
|
268 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. P m \<longrightarrow> Q (Suc m)) \<longrightarrow> Q m" by fact |
|
269 have r1: "P 0" by fact |
|
270 have r2: "\<forall>m. Q m \<longrightarrow> P (Suc m)" by fact |
|
271 have r3: "\<forall>m. P m \<longrightarrow> Q (Suc m)" by fact |
|
272 show "P (Suc m)" |
|
273 apply(rule r2[rule_format]) |
|
274 apply(rule p1[THEN spec[where x=P], THEN spec[where x=Q], |
|
275 THEN mp, THEN mp, THEN mp, OF r1, OF r2, OF r3]) |
|
276 done |
|
277 qed |
|
278 |
|
279 text {* |
|
280 In Line 13, we apply the assumption @{text "r2"} (since we prove the second |
|
281 introduction rule). In Lines 14 and 15 we apply assumption @{text "p1"} (if |
|
282 the second introduction rule had more premises we have to do that for all |
|
283 of them). In order for this assumption to be applicable, the quantifiers |
|
284 need to be instantiated and then also the implications need to be resolved |
|
285 with the other rules. |
|
286 |
|
287 |
|
288 As a final example, we define the accessible part of a relation @{text R} characterised |
|
289 by the introduction rule |
|
290 |
|
291 \begin{center}\small |
|
292 \mbox{\inferrule{@{term "\<And>y. R y x \<Longrightarrow> accpart R y"}}{@{term "accpart R x"}}} |
|
293 \end{center} |
|
294 |
|
295 whose premise involves a universal quantifier and an implication. The |
|
296 definition of @{text accpart} is: |
|
297 *} |
|
298 |
|
299 definition "accpart \<equiv> \<lambda>R x. \<forall>P. (\<forall>x. (\<forall>y. R y x \<longrightarrow> P y) \<longrightarrow> P x) \<longrightarrow> P x" |
|
300 |
|
301 text {* |
|
302 The proof of the induction principle is again straightforward. |
|
303 *} |
|
304 |
|
305 lemma accpart_induct: |
|
306 assumes "accpart R x" |
|
307 shows "(\<And>x. (\<And>y. R y x \<Longrightarrow> P y) \<Longrightarrow> P x) \<Longrightarrow> P x" |
|
308 apply(atomize (full)) |
|
309 apply(cut_tac prems) |
|
310 apply(unfold accpart_def) |
|
311 apply(drule spec[where x=P]) |
|
312 apply(assumption) |
|
313 done |
|
314 |
|
315 text {* |
|
316 Proving the introduction rule is a little more complicated, because the quantifier |
|
317 and the implication in the premise. The proof is as follows. |
|
318 *} |
|
319 |
|
320 lemma %linenos accpartI: |
|
321 shows "(\<And>y. R y x \<Longrightarrow> accpart R y) \<Longrightarrow> accpart R x" |
|
322 apply (unfold accpart_def) |
|
323 apply (rule allI impI)+ |
|
324 proof - |
|
325 case (goal1 P) |
|
326 have p1: "\<And>y. R y x \<Longrightarrow> |
|
327 (\<forall>P. (\<forall>x. (\<forall>y. R y x \<longrightarrow> P y) \<longrightarrow> P x) \<longrightarrow> P y)" by fact |
|
328 have r1: "\<forall>x. (\<forall>y. R y x \<longrightarrow> P y) \<longrightarrow> P x" by fact |
|
329 show "P x" |
|
330 apply(rule r1[rule_format]) |
|
331 proof - |
|
332 case (goal1 y) |
|
333 have r1_prem: "R y x" by fact |
|
334 show "P y" |
|
335 apply(rule p1[OF r1_prem, THEN spec[where x=P], THEN mp, OF r1]) |
|
336 done |
|
337 qed |
|
338 qed |
|
339 |
|
340 text {* |
|
341 In Line 11, applying the assumption @{text "r1"} generates a goal state with |
|
342 the new local assumption @{term "R y x"}, named @{text "r1_prem"} in the |
|
343 proof above (Line 14). This local assumption is used to solve |
|
344 the goal @{term "P y"} with the help of assumption @{text "p1"}. |
|
345 |
|
346 The point of these examples is to get a feeling what the automatic proofs |
|
347 should do in order to solve all inductive definitions we throw at them. |
|
348 This is usually the first step in writing a package. We next explain |
|
349 the parsing and typing part of the package. |
|
350 |
|
351 *} |
|
352 (*<*)end(*>*) |