Journal/Paper.thy
author urbanc
Fri, 05 Aug 2011 05:34:11 +0000
changeset 187 9f46a9571e37
parent 186 07a269d9642b
child 190 b73478aaf33e
permissions -rw-r--r--
more on the derivatives section

(*<*)
theory Paper
imports "../Closures" "../Attic/Prefix_subtract" 
begin

declare [[show_question_marks = false]]

consts
 REL :: "(string \<times> string) \<Rightarrow> bool"
 UPLUS :: "'a set \<Rightarrow> 'a set \<Rightarrow> (nat \<times> 'a) set"

abbreviation
  "EClass x R \<equiv> R `` {x}"

abbreviation 
  "Append_rexp2 r_itm r \<equiv> Append_rexp r r_itm"


abbreviation
  "pow" (infixl "\<up>" 100)
where
  "A \<up> n \<equiv> A ^^ n"

syntax (latex output)
  "_Collect" :: "pttrn => bool => 'a set"              ("(1{_ | _})")
  "_CollectIn" :: "pttrn => 'a set => bool => 'a set"   ("(1{_ \<in> _ | _})")
translations
  "_Collect p P"      <= "{p. P}"
  "_Collect p P"      <= "{p|xs. P}"
  "_CollectIn p A P"  <= "{p : A. P}"

abbreviation "ZERO \<equiv> Zero"
abbreviation "ONE \<equiv> One"
abbreviation "ATOM \<equiv> Atom"
abbreviation "PLUS \<equiv> Plus"
abbreviation "TIMES \<equiv> Times"
abbreviation "TIMESS \<equiv> Timess"
abbreviation "STAR \<equiv> Star"


notation (latex output)
  str_eq ("\<approx>\<^bsub>_\<^esub>") and
  str_eq_applied ("_ \<approx>\<^bsub>_\<^esub> _") and
  conc (infixr "\<cdot>" 100) and
  star ("_\<^bsup>\<star>\<^esup>") and
  pow ("_\<^bsup>_\<^esup>" [100, 100] 100) and
  Suc ("_+1" [100] 100) and
  quotient ("_ \<^raw:\ensuremath{\!\sslash\!}> _" [90, 90] 90) and
  REL ("\<approx>") and
  UPLUS ("_ \<^raw:\ensuremath{\uplus}> _" [90, 90] 90) and
  lang ("\<^raw:\ensuremath{\cal{L}}>" 101) and
  lang ("\<^raw:\ensuremath{\cal{L}}>'(_')" [0] 101) and
  lang_trm ("\<^raw:\ensuremath{\cal{L}}>'(_')" [0] 101) and
  Lam ("\<lambda>'(_')" [100] 100) and 
  Trn ("'(_, _')" [100, 100] 100) and 
  EClass ("\<lbrakk>_\<rbrakk>\<^bsub>_\<^esub>" [100, 100] 100) and
  transition ("_ \<^raw:\ensuremath{\stackrel{\text{>_\<^raw:}}{\Longmapsto}}> _" [100, 100, 100] 100) and
  Setalt ("\<^raw:\ensuremath{\bigplus}>_" [1000] 999) and
  Append_rexp2 ("_ \<^raw:\ensuremath{\triangleleft}> _" [100, 100] 100) and
  Append_rexp_rhs ("_ \<^raw:\ensuremath{\triangleleft}> _" [100, 100] 50) and
  
  uminus ("\<^raw:\ensuremath{\overline{>_\<^raw:}}>" [100] 100) and
  tag_Plus ("+tag _ _" [100, 100] 100) and
  tag_Plus ("+tag _ _ _" [100, 100, 100] 100) and
  tag_Times ("\<times>tag _ _" [100, 100] 100) and
  tag_Times ("\<times>tag _ _ _" [100, 100, 100] 100) and
  tag_Star ("\<star>tag _" [100] 100) and
  tag_Star ("\<star>tag _ _" [100, 100] 100) and
  tag_eq ("\<^raw:$\threesim$>\<^bsub>_\<^esub>") and
  Delta ("\<Delta>'(_')") and
  nullable ("\<delta>'(_')") and
  Cons ("_ :: _" [100, 100] 100) and
  Rev ("Rev _" [1000] 100) and
  Der ("Der _ _" [1000, 1000] 100) and
  ONE ("ONE" 999) and
  ZERO ("ZERO" 999)

lemma meta_eq_app:
  shows "f \<equiv> \<lambda>x. g x \<Longrightarrow> f x \<equiv> g x"
  by auto

lemma str_eq_def':
  shows "x \<approx>A y \<equiv> (\<forall>z. x @ z \<in> A \<longleftrightarrow> y @ z \<in> A)"
unfolding str_eq_def by simp

lemma conc_def':
  "A \<cdot> B = {s\<^isub>1 @ s\<^isub>2 | s\<^isub>1 s\<^isub>2. s\<^isub>1 \<in> A \<and> s\<^isub>2 \<in> B}"
unfolding conc_def by simp

lemma conc_Union_left: 
  shows "B \<cdot> (\<Union>n. A \<up> n) = (\<Union>n. B \<cdot> (A \<up> n))"
unfolding conc_def by auto

lemma test:
  assumes X_in_eqs: "(X, rhs) \<in> Init (UNIV // \<approx>A)"
  shows "X = \<Union> (lang_trm `  rhs)"
using assms l_eq_r_in_eqs by (simp)


(* THEOREMS *)

notation (Rule output)
  "==>"  ("\<^raw:\mbox{}\inferrule{\mbox{>_\<^raw:}}>\<^raw:{\mbox{>_\<^raw:}}>")

syntax (Rule output)
  "_bigimpl" :: "asms \<Rightarrow> prop \<Rightarrow> prop"
  ("\<^raw:\mbox{}\inferrule{>_\<^raw:}>\<^raw:{\mbox{>_\<^raw:}}>")

  "_asms" :: "prop \<Rightarrow> asms \<Rightarrow> asms" 
  ("\<^raw:\mbox{>_\<^raw:}\\>/ _")

  "_asm" :: "prop \<Rightarrow> asms" ("\<^raw:\mbox{>_\<^raw:}>")

notation (Axiom output)
  "Trueprop"  ("\<^raw:\mbox{}\inferrule{\mbox{}}{\mbox{>_\<^raw:}}>")

notation (IfThen output)
  "==>"  ("\<^raw:{\normalsize{}>If\<^raw:\,}> _/ \<^raw:{\normalsize \,>then\<^raw:\,}>/ _.")
syntax (IfThen output)
  "_bigimpl" :: "asms \<Rightarrow> prop \<Rightarrow> prop"
  ("\<^raw:{\normalsize{}>If\<^raw:\,}> _ /\<^raw:{\normalsize \,>then\<^raw:\,}>/ _.")
  "_asms" :: "prop \<Rightarrow> asms \<Rightarrow> asms" ("\<^raw:\mbox{>_\<^raw:}> /\<^raw:{\normalsize \,>and\<^raw:\,}>/ _")
  "_asm" :: "prop \<Rightarrow> asms" ("\<^raw:\mbox{>_\<^raw:}>")

notation (IfThenNoBox output)
  "==>"  ("\<^raw:{\normalsize{}>If\<^raw:\,}> _/ \<^raw:{\normalsize \,>then\<^raw:\,}>/ _.")
syntax (IfThenNoBox output)
  "_bigimpl" :: "asms \<Rightarrow> prop \<Rightarrow> prop"
  ("\<^raw:{\normalsize{}>If\<^raw:\,}> _ /\<^raw:{\normalsize \,>then\<^raw:\,}>/ _.")
  "_asms" :: "prop \<Rightarrow> asms \<Rightarrow> asms" ("_ /\<^raw:{\normalsize \,>and\<^raw:\,}>/ _")
  "_asm" :: "prop \<Rightarrow> asms" ("_")


(*>*)


section {* Introduction *}

text {*
  \noindent
  Regular languages are an important and well-understood subject in Computer
  Science, with many beautiful theorems and many useful algorithms. There is a
  wide range of textbooks on this subject, many of which are aimed at students
  and contain very detailed `pencil-and-paper' proofs (e.g.~\cite{Kozen97,
  HopcroftUllman69}). It seems natural to exercise theorem provers by
  formalising the theorems and by verifying formally the algorithms.  

  A popular choice for a theorem prover would be one based on Higher-Order
  Logic (HOL), for example HOL4, HOLlight or Isabelle/HOL. For the development
  presented in this paper we will use the latter. HOL is a predicate calculus
  that allows quantification over predicate variables. Its type system is
  based on Church's Simple Theory of Types \cite{Church40}.  Although many
  mathematical concepts can be conveniently expressed in HOL, there are some
  limitations that hurt badly, if one attempts a simple-minded formalisation
  of regular languages in it.  The typical approach to regular languages is to
  introduce finite automata and then define everything in terms of them
  \cite{Kozen97}.  For example, a regular language is normally defined as:

  \begin{dfntn}\label{baddef}
  A language @{text A} is \emph{regular}, provided there is a 
  finite deterministic automaton that recognises all strings of @{text "A"}.
  \end{dfntn}

  \noindent  
  This approach has many benefits. Among them is the fact that it is easy to
  convince oneself that regular languages are closed under complementation:
  one just has to exchange the accepting and non-accepting states in the
  corresponding automaton to obtain an automaton for the complement language.
  The problem, however, lies with formalising such reasoning in a HOL-based
  theorem prover. Automata are built up from states and transitions that need
  to be represented as graphs, matrices or functions, none of which can be
  defined as an inductive datatype.

  In case of graphs and matrices, this means we have to build our own
  reasoning infrastructure for them, as neither Isabelle/HOL nor HOL4 nor
  HOLlight support them with libraries. Even worse, reasoning about graphs and
  matrices can be a real hassle in HOL-based theorem provers, because
  we have to be able to combine automata.  Consider for
  example the operation of sequencing two automata, say $A_1$ and $A_2$, by
  connecting the accepting states of $A_1$ to the initial state of $A_2$:
  %  

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{ccc}
  \begin{tikzpicture}[scale=1]
  %\draw[step=2mm] (-1,-1) grid (1,1);
  
  \draw[rounded corners=1mm, very thick] (-1.0,-0.3) rectangle (-0.2,0.3);
  \draw[rounded corners=1mm, very thick] ( 0.2,-0.3) rectangle ( 1.0,0.3);

  \node (A) at (-1.0,0.0) [circle, very thick, draw, fill=white, inner sep=0.4mm] {};
  \node (B) at ( 0.2,0.0) [circle, very thick, draw, fill=white, inner sep=0.4mm] {};
  
  \node (C) at (-0.2, 0.13) [circle, very thick, draw, fill=white, inner sep=0.4mm] {};
  \node (D) at (-0.2,-0.13) [circle, very thick, draw, fill=white, inner sep=0.4mm] {};

  \node (E) at (1.0, 0.2) [circle, very thick, draw, fill=white, inner sep=0.4mm] {};
  \node (F) at (1.0,-0.0) [circle, very thick, draw, fill=white, inner sep=0.4mm] {};
  \node (G) at (1.0,-0.2) [circle, very thick, draw, fill=white, inner sep=0.4mm] {};

  \draw (-0.6,0.0) node {\small$A_1$};
  \draw ( 0.6,0.0) node {\small$A_2$};
  \end{tikzpicture}

  & 

  \raisebox{1.1mm}{\bf\Large$\;\;\;\Rightarrow\,\;\;$}

  &

  \begin{tikzpicture}[scale=1]
  %\draw[step=2mm] (-1,-1) grid (1,1);
  
  \draw[rounded corners=1mm, very thick] (-1.0,-0.3) rectangle (-0.2,0.3);
  \draw[rounded corners=1mm, very thick] ( 0.2,-0.3) rectangle ( 1.0,0.3);

  \node (A) at (-1.0,0.0) [circle, very thick, draw, fill=white, inner sep=0.4mm] {};
  \node (B) at ( 0.2,0.0) [circle, very thick, draw, fill=white, inner sep=0.4mm] {};
  
  \node (C) at (-0.2, 0.13) [circle, very thick, draw, fill=white, inner sep=0.4mm] {};
  \node (D) at (-0.2,-0.13) [circle, very thick, draw, fill=white, inner sep=0.4mm] {};

  \node (E) at (1.0, 0.2) [circle, very thick, draw, fill=white, inner sep=0.4mm] {};
  \node (F) at (1.0,-0.0) [circle, very thick, draw, fill=white, inner sep=0.4mm] {};
  \node (G) at (1.0,-0.2) [circle, very thick, draw, fill=white, inner sep=0.4mm] {};
  
  \draw (C) to [very thick, bend left=45] (B);
  \draw (D) to [very thick, bend right=45] (B);

  \draw (-0.6,0.0) node {\small$A_1$};
  \draw ( 0.6,0.0) node {\small$A_2$};
  \end{tikzpicture}

  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  On `paper' we can define the corresponding 
  graph in terms of the disjoint 
  union of the state nodes. Unfortunately in HOL, the standard definition for disjoint 
  union, namely 
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{disjointunion}
  @{text "A\<^isub>1 \<uplus> A\<^isub>2 \<equiv> {(1, x) | x \<in> A\<^isub>1} \<union> {(2, y) | y \<in> A\<^isub>2}"}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  changes the type---the disjoint union is not a set, but a set of
  pairs. Using this definition for disjoint union means we do not have a
  single type for automata. As a result we will not be able to define a regular
  language as one for which there exists an automaton that recognises all its
  strings. This is because we cannot make a definition in HOL that is polymorphic in 
  the state type and there is no type quantification available in HOL (unlike 
  in Coq, for example).\footnote{Slind already pointed out this problem in an email 
  to the HOL4 mailing list on 21st April 2005.}

  An alternative, which provides us with a single type for automata, is to give every 
  state node an identity, for example a natural
  number, and then be careful to rename these identities apart whenever
  connecting two automata. This results in clunky proofs
  establishing that properties are invariant under renaming. Similarly,
  connecting two automata represented as matrices results in very adhoc
  constructions, which are not pleasant to reason about.

  Functions are much better supported in Isabelle/HOL, but they still lead to similar
  problems as with graphs.  Composing, for example, two non-deterministic automata in parallel
  requires also the formalisation of disjoint unions. Nipkow \cite{Nipkow98} 
  dismisses for this the option of using identities, because it leads according to 
  him to ``messy proofs''. Since he does not need to define what regular
  languages are, Nipkow opts for a variant of \eqref{disjointunion} using bit lists, but writes 

  \begin{quote}
  \it%
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}p{0.88\textwidth}@ {}}
  `` & All lemmas appear obvious given a picture of the composition of automata\ldots
       Yet their proofs require a painful amount of detail.''
  \end{tabular}
  \end{quote}

  \noindent
  and
  
  \begin{quote}
  \it%
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}p{0.88\textwidth}@ {}}
  `` & If the reader finds the above treatment in terms of bit lists revoltingly
       concrete, I cannot disagree. A more abstract approach is clearly desirable.''
  \end{tabular}
  \end{quote}


  \noindent
  Moreover, it is not so clear how to conveniently impose a finiteness
  condition upon functions in order to represent \emph{finite} automata. The
  best is probably to resort to more advanced reasoning frameworks, such as
  \emph{locales} or \emph{type classes}, which are \emph{not} available in all
  HOL-based theorem provers.

  Because of these problems to do with representing automata, there seems to
  be no substantial formalisation of automata theory and regular languages
  carried out in HOL-based theorem provers. Nipkow \cite{Nipkow98} establishes
  the link between regular expressions and automata in the context of
  lexing. Berghofer and Reiter \cite{BerghoferReiter09} formalise automata
  working over bit strings in the context of Presburger arithmetic.  The only
  larger formalisations of automata theory are carried out in Nuprl
  \cite{Constable00} and in Coq \cite{Filliatre97}.

  Also one might consider automata theory as a well-worn stock subject where
  everything is crystal clear. However, paper proofs about automata often
  involve subtle side-conditions which are easily overlooked, but which make
  formal reasoning rather painful. For example Kozen's proof of the
  Myhill-Nerode theorem requires that automata do not have inaccessible
  states \cite{Kozen97}. Another subtle side-condition is completeness of
  automata, that is automata need to have total transition functions and at most one
  `sink' state from which there is no connection to a final state (Brzozowski
  mentions this side-condition in the context of state complexity
  of automata \cite{Brzozowski10}). Such side-conditions mean that if we define a regular
  language as one for which there exists \emph{a} finite automaton that
  recognises all its strings (see Def.~\ref{baddef}), then we need a lemma which
  ensures that another equivalent one can be found satisfying the
  side-condition. Unfortunately, such `little' and `obvious' lemmas make
  a formalisation of automata theory a hair-pulling experience.


  In this paper, we will not attempt to formalise automata theory in
  Isabelle/HOL nor will we attempt to formalise automata proofs from the
  literature, but take a different approach to regular languages than is
  usually taken. Instead of defining a regular language as one where there
  exists an automaton that recognises all its strings, we define a
  regular language as:

  \begin{dfntn}\label{regular}
  A language @{text A} is \emph{regular}, provided there is a regular expression 
  that matches all strings of @{text "A"}.
  \end{dfntn}
  
  \noindent
  The reason is that regular expressions, unlike graphs, matrices and
  functions, can be easily defined as an inductive datatype. A reasoning
  infrastructure (like induction and recursion) comes then for free in
  HOL. Moreover, no side-conditions will be needed for regular expressions,
  like we need for automata. This convenience of regular expressions has
  recently been exploited in HOL4 with a formalisation of regular expression
  matching based on derivatives \cite{OwensSlind08} and with an equivalence
  checker for regular expressions in Isabelle/HOL \cite{KraussNipkow11}.  The
  main purpose of this paper is to show that a central result about regular
  languages---the Myhill-Nerode theorem---can be recreated by only using
  regular expressions. This theorem gives necessary and sufficient conditions
  for when a language is regular. As a corollary of this theorem we can easily
  establish the usual closure properties, including complementation, for
  regular languages.\medskip
  
  \noindent 
  {\bf Contributions:} There is an extensive literature on regular languages.
  To our best knowledge, our proof of the Myhill-Nerode theorem is the first
  that is based on regular expressions, only. The part of this theorem stating
  that finitely many partitions imply regularity of the language is proved by
  an argument about solving equational systems.  This argument appears to be
  folklore. For the other part, we give two proofs: one direct proof using
  certain tagging-functions, and another indirect proof using Antimirov's
  partial derivatives \cite{Antimirov95}. Again to our best knowledge, the
  tagging-functions have not been used before to establish the Myhill-Nerode
  theorem. Derivatives of regular expressions have been used recently quite
  widely in the literature; partial derivatives, in contrast, attracted much
  less attention. However, partial derivatives are more suitable in the
  context of the Myhill-Nerode theorem, since it is easier to establish
  formally their finiteness result. We have not found any proof that uses
  either of them in order to prove the Myhill-Nerode theorem.
*}

section {* Preliminaries *}

text {*
  \noindent
  Strings in Isabelle/HOL are lists of characters with the \emph{empty string}
  being represented by the empty list, written @{term "[]"}.  We assume there
  are only finitely many different characters.  \emph{Languages} are sets of
  strings. The language containing all strings is written in Isabelle/HOL as
  @{term "UNIV::string set"}. The concatenation of two languages is written
  @{term "A \<cdot> B"} and a language raised to the power @{text n} is written
  @{term "A \<up> n"}. They are defined as usual

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{l@ {\hspace{1mm}}c@ {\hspace{1mm}}l}
  @{thm (lhs) conc_def'[THEN eq_reflection, where A1="A" and B1="B"]}
  & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) conc_def'[THEN eq_reflection, where A1="A" and B1="B"]}\\

  @{thm (lhs) lang_pow.simps(1)[THEN eq_reflection, where A1="A"]}
  & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) lang_pow.simps(1)[THEN eq_reflection, where A1="A"]}\\

  @{thm (lhs) lang_pow.simps(2)[THEN eq_reflection, where A1="A" and n1="n"]}
  & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) lang_pow.simps(2)[THEN eq_reflection, where A1="A" and n1="n"]}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  where @{text "@"} is the list-append operation. The Kleene-star of a language @{text A}
  is defined as the union over all powers, namely @{thm star_def}. In the paper
  we will make use of the following properties of these constructions.
  
  \begin{prpstn}\label{langprops}\mbox{}\\
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}lp{10cm}}
  (i)   & @{thm star_unfold_left}     \\ 
  (ii)  & @{thm[mode=IfThen] pow_length}\\
  (iii) & @{thm conc_Union_left} \\ 
  (iv)  & If @{thm (prem 1) star_decom} and @{thm (prem 2) star_decom} then
          there exists an @{text "x\<^isub>p"} and @{text "x\<^isub>s"} with @{text "x = x\<^isub>p @ x\<^isub>s"} 
          and @{term "x\<^isub>p \<noteq> []"} such that @{term "x\<^isub>p \<in> A"} and @{term "x\<^isub>s \<in> A\<star>"}.
  \end{tabular}
  \end{prpstn}

  \noindent
  In @{text "(ii)"} we use the notation @{term "length s"} for the length of a
  string; this property states that if \mbox{@{term "[] \<notin> A"}} then the lengths of
  the strings in @{term "A \<up> (Suc n)"} must be longer than @{text n}.  We omit
  the proofs for these properties, but invite the reader to consult our
  formalisation.\footnote{Available at \url{http://www4.in.tum.de/~urbanc/regexp.html}}

  The notation in Isabelle/HOL for the quotient of a language @{text A}
  according to an equivalence relation @{term REL} is @{term "A // REL"}. We
  will write @{text "\<lbrakk>x\<rbrakk>\<^isub>\<approx>"} for the equivalence class defined as
  \mbox{@{text "{y | y \<approx> x}"}}, and have @{text "x \<approx> y"} if and only if @{text
  "\<lbrakk>x\<rbrakk>\<^isub>\<approx> = \<lbrakk>y\<rbrakk>\<^isub>\<approx>"}.


  Central to our proof will be the solution of equational systems
  involving equivalence classes of languages. For this we will use Arden's Lemma 
  (see \cite[Page 100]{Sakarovitch09}),
  which solves equations of the form @{term "X = A \<cdot> X \<union> B"} provided
  @{term "[] \<notin> A"}. However we will need the following `reverse' 
  version of Arden's Lemma (`reverse' in the sense of changing the order of @{term "A \<cdot> X"} to
  \mbox{@{term "X \<cdot> A"}}).

  \begin{lmm}[Reverse Arden's Lemma]\label{arden}\mbox{}\\
  If @{thm (prem 1) arden} then
  @{thm (lhs) arden} if and only if
  @{thm (rhs) arden}.
  \end{lmm}

  \begin{proof}
  For the right-to-left direction we assume @{thm (rhs) arden} and show
  that @{thm (lhs) arden} holds. From Prop.~\ref{langprops}@{text "(i)"} 
  we have @{term "A\<star> = A \<cdot> A\<star> \<union> {[]}"},
  which is equal to @{term "A\<star> = A\<star> \<cdot> A \<union> {[]}"}. Adding @{text B} to both 
  sides gives @{term "B \<cdot> A\<star> = B \<cdot> (A\<star> \<cdot> A \<union> {[]})"}, whose right-hand side
  is equal to @{term "(B \<cdot> A\<star>) \<cdot> A \<union> B"}. This completes this direction. 

  For the other direction we assume @{thm (lhs) arden}. By a simple induction
  on @{text n}, we can establish the property

  \begin{center}
  @{text "(*)"}\hspace{5mm} @{thm (concl) arden_helper}
  \end{center}
  
  \noindent
  Using this property we can show that @{term "B \<cdot> (A \<up> n) \<subseteq> X"} holds for
  all @{text n}. From this we can infer @{term "B \<cdot> A\<star> \<subseteq> X"} using the definition
  of @{text "\<star>"}.
  For the inclusion in the other direction we assume a string @{text s}
  with length @{text k} is an element in @{text X}. Since @{thm (prem 1) arden}
  we know by Prop.~\ref{langprops}@{text "(ii)"} that 
  @{term "s \<notin> X \<cdot> (A \<up> Suc k)"} since its length is only @{text k}
  (the strings in @{term "X \<cdot> (A \<up> Suc k)"} are all longer). 
  From @{text "(*)"} it follows then that
  @{term s} must be an element in @{term "(\<Union>m\<in>{0..k}. B \<cdot> (A \<up> m))"}. This in turn
  implies that @{term s} is in @{term "(\<Union>n. B \<cdot> (A \<up> n))"}. Using Prop.~\ref{langprops}@{text "(iii)"} 
  this is equal to @{term "B \<cdot> A\<star>"}, as we needed to show.
  \end{proof}

  \noindent
  Regular expressions are defined as the inductive datatype

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{rcl}
  @{text r} & @{text "::="} & @{term ZERO}\\
   & @{text"|"} & @{term One}\\ 
   & @{text"|"} & @{term "Atom c"}\\
   & @{text"|"} & @{term "Times r r"}\\
   & @{text"|"} & @{term "Plus r r"}\\
   & @{text"|"} & @{term "Star r"}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  and the language matched by a regular expression is defined as

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{r@ {\hspace{2mm}}c@ {\hspace{2mm}}l}
  @{thm (lhs) lang.simps(1)} & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) lang.simps(1)}\\
  @{thm (lhs) lang.simps(2)} & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) lang.simps(2)}\\
  @{thm (lhs) lang.simps(3)[where a="c"]} & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) lang.simps(3)[where a="c"]}\\
  @{thm (lhs) lang.simps(4)[where ?r="r\<^isub>1" and ?s="r\<^isub>2"]} & @{text "\<equiv>"} &
       @{thm (rhs) lang.simps(4)[where ?r="r\<^isub>1" and ?s="r\<^isub>2"]}\\
  @{thm (lhs) lang.simps(5)[where ?r="r\<^isub>1" and ?s="r\<^isub>2"]} & @{text "\<equiv>"} &
       @{thm (rhs) lang.simps(5)[where ?r="r\<^isub>1" and ?s="r\<^isub>2"]}\\
  @{thm (lhs) lang.simps(6)[where r="r"]} & @{text "\<equiv>"} &
      @{thm (rhs) lang.simps(6)[where r="r"]}\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  Given a finite set of regular expressions @{text rs}, we will make use of the operation of generating 
  a regular expression that matches the union of all languages of @{text rs}. We only need to know the 
  existence
  of such a regular expression and therefore we use Isabelle/HOL's @{const "fold_graph"} and Hilbert's
  @{text "\<epsilon>"} to define @{term "\<Uplus>rs"}. This operation, roughly speaking, folds @{const PLUS} over the 
  set @{text rs} with @{const ZERO} for the empty set. We can prove that for a finite set @{text rs}
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{uplus}
  \mbox{@{thm (lhs) folds_alt_simp} @{text "= \<Union> (\<calL> ` rs)"}}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  holds, whereby @{text "\<calL> ` rs"} stands for the 
  image of the set @{text rs} under function @{text "\<calL>"}.
*}


section {* The Myhill-Nerode Theorem, First Part *}

text {*
  \noindent
  \footnote{Folklore: Henzinger (arden-DFA-regexp.pdf); Hofmann}
  The key definition in the Myhill-Nerode theorem is the
  \emph{Myhill-Nerode relation}, which states that w.r.t.~a language two 
  strings are related, provided there is no distinguishing extension in this
  language. This can be defined as a tertiary relation.

  \begin{dfntn}[Myhill-Nerode Relation]\label{myhillneroderel} 
  Given a language @{text A}, two strings @{text x} and
  @{text y} are Myhill-Nerode related provided
  \begin{center}
  @{thm str_eq_def'}
  \end{center}
  \end{dfntn}

  \noindent
  It is easy to see that @{term "\<approx>A"} is an equivalence relation, which
  partitions the set of all strings, @{text "UNIV"}, into a set of disjoint
  equivalence classes. To illustrate this quotient construction, let us give a simple 
  example: consider the regular language containing just
  the string @{text "[c]"}. The relation @{term "\<approx>({[c]})"} partitions @{text UNIV}
  into three equivalence classes @{text "X\<^isub>1"}, @{text "X\<^isub>2"} and  @{text "X\<^isub>3"}
  as follows
  
  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{l}
  @{text "X\<^isub>1 = {[]}"}\\
  @{text "X\<^isub>2 = {[c]}"}\\
  @{text "X\<^isub>3 = UNIV - {[], [c]}"}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  One direction of the Myhill-Nerode theorem establishes 
  that if there are finitely many equivalence classes, like in the example above, then 
  the language is regular. In our setting we therefore have to show:
  
  \begin{thrm}\label{myhillnerodeone}
  @{thm[mode=IfThen] Myhill_Nerode1}
  \end{thrm}

  \noindent
  To prove this theorem, we first define the set @{term "finals A"} as those equivalence
  classes from @{term "UNIV // \<approx>A"} that contain strings of @{text A}, namely
  %
  \begin{equation} 
  @{thm finals_def}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  In our running example, @{text "X\<^isub>2"} is the only 
  equivalence class in @{term "finals {[c]}"}.
  It is straightforward to show that in general 

  \begin{equation}\label{finalprops}
  @{thm lang_is_union_of_finals}\hspace{15mm} 
  @{thm finals_in_partitions} 
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  hold. 
  Therefore if we know that there exists a regular expression for every
  equivalence class in \mbox{@{term "finals A"}} (which by assumption must be
  a finite set), then we can use @{text "\<bigplus>"} to obtain a regular expression 
  that matches every string in @{text A}.


  Our proof of Thm.~\ref{myhillnerodeone} relies on a method that can calculate a
  regular expression for \emph{every} equivalence class, not just the ones 
  in @{term "finals A"}. We
  first define the notion of \emph{one-character-transition} between 
  two equivalence classes
  %
  \begin{equation} 
  @{thm transition_def}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  which means that if we concatenate the character @{text c} to the end of all 
  strings in the equivalence class @{text Y}, we obtain a subset of 
  @{text X}. Note that we do not define an automaton here, we merely relate two sets
  (with the help of a character). In our concrete example we have 
  @{term "X\<^isub>1 \<Turnstile>c\<Rightarrow> X\<^isub>2"}, @{term "X\<^isub>1 \<Turnstile>d\<^isub>i\<Rightarrow> X\<^isub>3"} with @{text "d\<^isub>i"} being any 
  other character than @{text c}, and @{term "X\<^isub>3 \<Turnstile>c\<^isub>j\<Rightarrow> X\<^isub>3"} for any 
  caracter @{text "c\<^isub>j"}.
  
  Next we construct an \emph{initial equational system} that
  contains an equation for each equivalence class. We first give
  an informal description of this construction. Suppose we have 
  the equivalence classes @{text "X\<^isub>1,\<dots>,X\<^isub>n"}, there must be one and only one that
  contains the empty string @{text "[]"} (since equivalence classes are disjoint).
  Let us assume @{text "[] \<in> X\<^isub>1"}. We build the following equational system
  
  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{rcl}
  @{text "X\<^isub>1"} & @{text "="} & @{text "(Y\<^isub>1\<^isub>1, ATOM c\<^isub>1\<^isub>1) + \<dots> + (Y\<^isub>1\<^isub>p, ATOM c\<^isub>1\<^isub>p) + \<lambda>(ONE)"} \\
  @{text "X\<^isub>2"} & @{text "="} & @{text "(Y\<^isub>2\<^isub>1, ATOM c\<^isub>2\<^isub>1) + \<dots> + (Y\<^isub>2\<^isub>o, ATOM c\<^isub>2\<^isub>o)"} \\
  & $\vdots$ \\
  @{text "X\<^isub>n"} & @{text "="} & @{text "(Y\<^isub>n\<^isub>1, ATOM c\<^isub>n\<^isub>1) + \<dots> + (Y\<^isub>n\<^isub>q, ATOM c\<^isub>n\<^isub>q)"}\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  where the terms @{text "(Y\<^isub>i\<^isub>j, ATOM c\<^isub>i\<^isub>j)"}
  stand for all transitions @{term "Y\<^isub>i\<^isub>j \<Turnstile>c\<^isub>i\<^isub>j\<Rightarrow>
  X\<^isub>i"}. 
  %The intuition behind the equational system is that every 
  %equation @{text "X\<^isub>i = rhs\<^isub>i"} in this system
  %corresponds roughly to a state of an automaton whose name is @{text X\<^isub>i} and its predecessor states 
  %are the @{text "Y\<^isub>i\<^isub>j"}; the @{text "c\<^isub>i\<^isub>j"} are the labels of the transitions from these 
  %predecessor states to @{text X\<^isub>i}. 
  There can only be
  finitely many terms of the form @{text "(Y\<^isub>i\<^isub>j, ATOM c\<^isub>i\<^isub>j)"} in a right-hand side 
  since by assumption there are only finitely many
  equivalence classes and only finitely many characters.
  The term @{text "\<lambda>(ONE)"} in the first equation acts as a marker for the initial state, that
  is the equivalence class
  containing @{text "[]"}.\footnote{Note that we mark, roughly speaking, the
  single `initial' state in the equational system, which is different from
  the method by Brzozowski \cite{Brzozowski64}, where he marks the
  `terminal' states. We are forced to set up the equational system in our
  way, because the Myhill-Nerode relation determines the `direction' of the
  transitions---the successor `state' of an equivalence class @{text Y} can
  be reached by adding a character to the end of @{text Y}. This is also the
  reason why we have to use our reverse version of Arden's Lemma.}
  In our running example we have the initial equational system

  \begin{equation}\label{exmpcs}
  \mbox{\begin{tabular}{l@ {\hspace{1mm}}c@ {\hspace{1mm}}l}
  @{term "X\<^isub>1"} & @{text "="} & @{text "\<lambda>(ONE)"}\\
  @{term "X\<^isub>2"} & @{text "="} & @{text "(X\<^isub>1, ATOM c)"}\\
  @{term "X\<^isub>3"} & @{text "="} & @{text "(X\<^isub>1, ATOM d\<^isub>1) + \<dots> + (X\<^isub>1, ATOM d\<^isub>n)"}\\
               & & \mbox{}\hspace{10mm}@{text "+ (X\<^isub>3, ATOM c\<^isub>1) + \<dots> + (X\<^isub>3, ATOM c\<^isub>m)"}
  \end{tabular}}
  \end{equation}
  
  \noindent
  where @{text "d\<^isub>1\<dots>d\<^isub>n"} is the sequence of all characters
  but not containing @{text c}, and @{text "c\<^isub>1\<dots>c\<^isub>m"} is the sequence of all
  characters.  

  Overloading the function @{text \<calL>} for the two kinds of terms in the
  equational system, we have
  
  \begin{center}
  @{text "\<calL>(Y, r) \<equiv>"} %
  @{thm (rhs) lang_trm.simps(2)[where X="Y" and r="r", THEN eq_reflection]}\hspace{10mm}
  @{thm lang_trm.simps(1)[where r="r", THEN eq_reflection]}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  and we can prove for @{text "X\<^isub>2\<^isub>.\<^isub>.\<^isub>n"} that the following equations
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{inv1}
  @{text "X\<^isub>i = \<calL>(Y\<^isub>i\<^isub>1, ATOM c\<^isub>i\<^isub>1) \<union> \<dots> \<union> \<calL>(Y\<^isub>i\<^isub>q, ATOM c\<^isub>i\<^isub>q)"}.
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  hold. Similarly for @{text "X\<^isub>1"} we can show the following equation
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{inv2}
  @{text "X\<^isub>1 = \<calL>(Y\<^isub>1\<^isub>1, ATOM c\<^isub>1\<^isub>1) \<union> \<dots> \<union> \<calL>(Y\<^isub>1\<^isub>p, ATOM c\<^isub>1\<^isub>p) \<union> \<calL>(\<lambda>(ONE))"}.
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  holds. The reason for adding the @{text \<lambda>}-marker to our initial equational system is 
  to obtain this equation: it only holds with the marker, since none of 
  the other terms contain the empty string. The point of the initial equational system is
  that solving it means we will be able to extract a regular expression for every equivalence class. 

  Our representation for the equations in Isabelle/HOL are pairs,
  where the first component is an equivalence class (a set of strings)
  and the second component
  is a set of terms. Given a set of equivalence
  classes @{text CS}, our initial equational system @{term "Init CS"} is thus 
  formally defined as
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{initcs}
  \mbox{\begin{tabular}{rcl}     
  @{thm (lhs) Init_rhs_def} & @{text "\<equiv>"} & 
  @{text "if"}~@{term "[] \<in> X"}\\
  & & @{text "then"}~@{term "{Trn Y (ATOM c) | Y c. Y \<in> CS \<and> Y \<Turnstile>c\<Rightarrow> X} \<union> {Lam ONE}"}\\
  & & @{text "else"}~@{term "{Trn Y (ATOM c)| Y c. Y \<in> CS \<and> Y \<Turnstile>c\<Rightarrow> X}"}\\
  @{thm (lhs) Init_def}     & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) Init_def}
  \end{tabular}}
  \end{equation}

  

  \noindent
  Because we use sets of terms 
  for representing the right-hand sides of equations, we can 
  prove \eqref{inv1} and \eqref{inv2} more concisely as
  %
  \begin{lmm}\label{inv}
  If @{thm (prem 1) test} then @{text "X = \<Union> \<calL> ` rhs"}.
  \end{lmm}

  \noindent
  Our proof of Thm.~\ref{myhillnerodeone} will proceed by transforming the
  initial equational system into one in \emph{solved form} maintaining the invariant
  in Lem.~\ref{inv}. From the solved form we will be able to read
  off the regular expressions. 

  In order to transform an equational system into solved form, we have two 
  operations: one that takes an equation of the form @{text "X = rhs"} and removes
  any recursive occurrences of @{text X} in the @{text rhs} using our variant of Arden's 
  Lemma. The other operation takes an equation @{text "X = rhs"}
  and substitutes @{text X} throughout the rest of the equational system
  adjusting the remaining regular expressions appropriately. To define this adjustment 
  we define the \emph{append-operation} taking a term and a regular expression as argument

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{r@ {\hspace{2mm}}c@ {\hspace{2mm}}l}
  @{thm (lhs) Append_rexp.simps(2)[where X="Y" and r="r\<^isub>1" and rexp="r\<^isub>2", THEN eq_reflection]}
  & @{text "\<equiv>"} & 
  @{thm (rhs) Append_rexp.simps(2)[where X="Y" and r="r\<^isub>1" and rexp="r\<^isub>2", THEN eq_reflection]}\\
  @{thm (lhs) Append_rexp.simps(1)[where r="r\<^isub>1" and rexp="r\<^isub>2", THEN eq_reflection]}
  & @{text "\<equiv>"} & 
  @{thm (rhs) Append_rexp.simps(1)[where r="r\<^isub>1" and rexp="r\<^isub>2", THEN eq_reflection]}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  We lift this operation to entire right-hand sides of equations, written as
  @{thm (lhs) Append_rexp_rhs_def[where rexp="r"]}. With this we can define
  the \emph{arden-operation} for an equation of the form @{text "X = rhs"} as:
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{arden_def}
  \mbox{\begin{tabular}{rc@ {\hspace{2mm}}r@ {\hspace{1mm}}l}
  @{thm (lhs) Arden_def} & @{text "\<equiv>"}~~\mbox{} & \multicolumn{2}{@ {\hspace{-2mm}}l}{@{text "let"}}\\ 
   & & @{text "rhs' ="} & @{term "rhs - {Trn X r | r. Trn X r \<in> rhs}"} \\
   & & @{text "r' ="}   & @{term "Star (\<Uplus> {r. Trn X r \<in> rhs})"}\\
   & &  \multicolumn{2}{@ {\hspace{-2mm}}l}{@{text "in"}~~@{term "Append_rexp_rhs rhs' r'"}}\\ 
  \end{tabular}}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  In this definition, we first delete all terms of the form @{text "(X, r)"} from @{text rhs};
  then we calculate the combined regular expressions for all @{text r} coming 
  from the deleted @{text "(X, r)"}, and take the @{const Star} of it;
  finally we append this regular expression to @{text rhs'}. If we apply this
  operation to the right-hand side of @{text "X\<^isub>3"} in \eqref{exmpcs}, we obtain
  the equation:

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{l@ {\hspace{1mm}}c@ {\hspace{1mm}}l}
  @{term "X\<^isub>3"} & @{text "="} & 
    @{text "(X\<^isub>1, TIMES (ATOM d\<^isub>1) (STAR \<^raw:\ensuremath{\bigplus}>{ATOM c\<^isub>1,\<dots>, ATOM c\<^isub>m})) + \<dots> "}\\
  & & \mbox{}\hspace{13mm}
     @{text "\<dots> + (X\<^isub>1, TIMES (ATOM d\<^isub>n) (STAR \<^raw:\ensuremath{\bigplus}>{ATOM c\<^isub>1,\<dots>, ATOM c\<^isub>m}))"}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}


  \noindent
  That means we eliminated the dependency of @{text "X\<^isub>3"} on the
  right-hand side.  Note we used the abbreviation 
  @{text "\<^raw:\ensuremath{\bigplus}>{ATOM c\<^isub>1,\<dots>, ATOM c\<^isub>m}"} 
  to stand for a regular expression that matches with every character. In 
  our algorithm we are only interested in the existence of such a regular expression
  and do not specify it any further. 

  It can be easily seen that the @{text "Arden"}-operation mimics Arden's
  Lemma on the level of equations. To ensure the non-emptiness condition of
  Arden's Lemma we say that a right-hand side is @{text ardenable} provided

  \begin{center}
  @{thm ardenable_def}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  This allows us to prove a version of Arden's Lemma on the level of equations.

  \begin{lmm}\label{ardenable}
  Given an equation @{text "X = rhs"}.
  If @{text "X = \<Union>\<calL> ` rhs"},
  @{thm (prem 2) Arden_preserves_soundness}, and
  @{thm (prem 3) Arden_preserves_soundness}, then
  @{text "X = \<Union>\<calL> ` (Arden X rhs)"}.
  \end{lmm}
  
  \noindent
  Our @{text ardenable} condition is slightly stronger than needed for applying Arden's Lemma,
  but we can still ensure that it holds troughout our algorithm of transforming equations
  into solved form. The \emph{substitution-operation} takes an equation
  of the form @{text "X = xrhs"} and substitutes it into the right-hand side @{text rhs}.

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{rc@ {\hspace{2mm}}r@ {\hspace{1mm}}l}
  @{thm (lhs) Subst_def} & @{text "\<equiv>"}~~\mbox{} & \multicolumn{2}{@ {\hspace{-2mm}}l}{@{text "let"}}\\ 
   & & @{text "rhs' ="} & @{term "rhs - {Trn X r | r. Trn X r \<in> rhs}"} \\
   & & @{text "r' ="}   & @{term "\<Uplus> {r. Trn X r \<in> rhs}"}\\
   & &  \multicolumn{2}{@ {\hspace{-2mm}}l}{@{text "in"}~~@{term "rhs' \<union> Append_rexp_rhs xrhs r'"}}\\ 
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  We again delete first all occurrences of @{text "(X, r)"} in @{text rhs}; we then calculate
  the regular expression corresponding to the deleted terms; finally we append this
  regular expression to @{text "xrhs"} and union it up with @{text rhs'}. When we use
  the substitution operation we will arrange it so that @{text "xrhs"} does not contain
  any occurrence of @{text X}. For example substituting the first equation in
  \eqref{exmpcs} into the right-hand side of the second, thus eliminating the equivalence 
  class @{text "X\<^isub>1"}, gives us the equation

  \begin{equation}\label{exmpresult}
  \mbox{\begin{tabular}{l@ {\hspace{1mm}}c@ {\hspace{1mm}}l}
  @{term "X\<^isub>2"} & @{text "="} & @{text "\<lambda>(TIMES ONE (ATOM c))"}\\
  \end{tabular}}
  \end{equation}

  With these two operations in place, we can define the operation that removes one equation
  from an equational systems @{text ES}. The operation @{const Subst_all}
  substitutes an equation @{text "X = xrhs"} throughout an equational system @{text ES}; 
  @{const Remove} then completely removes such an equation from @{text ES} by substituting 
  it to the rest of the equational system, but first eliminating all recursive occurrences
  of @{text X} by applying @{const Arden} to @{text "xrhs"}.

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{rcl}
  @{thm (lhs) Subst_all_def} & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) Subst_all_def}\\
  @{thm (lhs) Remove_def}    & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) Remove_def}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  Finally, we can define how an equational system should be solved. For this 
  we will need to iterate the process of eliminating equations until only one equation
  will be left in the system. However, we do not just want to have any equation
  as being the last one, but the one involving the equivalence class for 
  which we want to calculate the regular 
  expression. Let us suppose this equivalence class is @{text X}. 
  Since @{text X} is the one to be solved, in every iteration step we have to pick an
  equation to be eliminated that is different from @{text X}. In this way 
  @{text X} is kept to the final step. The choice is implemented using Hilbert's choice 
  operator, written @{text SOME} in the definition below.
  
  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{rc@ {\hspace{4mm}}r@ {\hspace{1mm}}l}
  @{thm (lhs) Iter_def} & @{text "\<equiv>"}~~\mbox{} & \multicolumn{2}{@ {\hspace{-4mm}}l}{@{text "let"}}\\ 
   & & @{text "(Y, yrhs) ="} & @{term "SOME (Y, yrhs). (Y, yrhs) \<in> ES \<and> X \<noteq> Y"} \\
   & &  \multicolumn{2}{@ {\hspace{-4mm}}l}{@{text "in"}~~@{term "Remove ES Y yrhs"}}\\ 
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  The last definition we need applies @{term Iter} over and over until a condition 
  @{text Cond} is \emph{not} satisfied anymore. This condition states that there
  are more than one equation left in the equational system @{text ES}. To solve
  an equational system we use Isabelle/HOL's @{text while}-operator as follows:
  
  \begin{center}
  @{thm Solve_def}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  We are not concerned here with the definition of this operator
  (see Berghofer and Nipkow \cite{BerghoferNipkow00}), but note that we eliminate
  in each @{const Iter}-step a single equation, and therefore 
  have a well-founded termination order by taking the cardinality 
  of the equational system @{text ES}. This enables us to prove
  properties about our definition of @{const Solve} when we `call' it with
  the equivalence class @{text X} and the initial equational system 
  @{term "Init (UNIV // \<approx>A)"} from
  \eqref{initcs} using the principle:
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{whileprinciple}
  \mbox{\begin{tabular}{l}
  @{term "invariant (Init (UNIV // \<approx>A))"} \\
  @{term "\<forall>ES. invariant ES \<and> Cond ES \<longrightarrow> invariant (Iter X ES)"}\\
  @{term "\<forall>ES. invariant ES \<and> Cond ES \<longrightarrow> card (Iter X ES) < card ES"}\\
  @{term "\<forall>ES. invariant ES \<and> \<not> Cond ES \<longrightarrow> P ES"}\\
  \hline
  \multicolumn{1}{c}{@{term "P (Solve X (Init (UNIV // \<approx>A)))"}}
  \end{tabular}}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  This principle states that given an invariant (which we will specify below) 
  we can prove a property
  @{text "P"} involving @{const Solve}. For this we have to discharge the following
  proof obligations: first the
  initial equational system satisfies the invariant; second the iteration
  step @{text "Iter"} preserves the invariant as long as the condition @{term Cond} holds;
  third @{text "Iter"} decreases the termination order, and fourth that
  once the condition does not hold anymore then the property @{text P} must hold.

  The property @{term P} in our proof will state that @{term "Solve X (Init (UNIV // \<approx>A))"}
  returns with a single equation @{text "X = xrhs"} for some @{text "xrhs"}, and
  that this equational system still satisfies the invariant. In order to get
  the proof through, the invariant is composed of the following six properties:

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}rcl@ {\hspace{-13mm}}l @ {}}
  @{text "invariant ES"} & @{text "\<equiv>"} &
      @{term "finite ES"} & @{text "(finiteness)"}\\
  & @{text "\<and>"} & @{thm (rhs) finite_rhs_def} & @{text "(finiteness rhs)"}\\
  & @{text "\<and>"} & @{text "\<forall>(X, rhs)\<in>ES. X = \<Union>\<calL> ` rhs"} & @{text "(soundness)"}\\
  & @{text "\<and>"} & @{thm (rhs) distinctness_def}\\
  &             &  & @{text "(distinctness)"}\\
  & @{text "\<and>"} & @{thm (rhs) ardenable_all_def} & @{text "(ardenable)"}\\   
  & @{text "\<and>"} & @{thm (rhs) validity_def} & @{text "(validity)"}\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}
 
  \noindent
  The first two ensure that the equational system is always finite (number of equations
  and number of terms in each equation); the third makes sure the `meaning' of the 
  equations is preserved under our transformations. The other properties are a bit more
  technical, but are needed to get our proof through. Distinctness states that every
  equation in the system is distinct. @{text Ardenable} ensures that we can always
  apply the @{text Arden} operation. 
  The last property states that every @{text rhs} can only contain equivalence classes
  for which there is an equation. Therefore @{text lhss} is just the set containing 
  the first components of an equational system,
  while @{text "rhss"} collects all equivalence classes @{text X} in the terms of the 
  form @{term "Trn X r"}. That means formally @{thm (lhs) lhss_def}~@{text "\<equiv> {X | (X, rhs) \<in> ES}"} 
  and @{thm (lhs) rhss_def}~@{text "\<equiv> {X | (X, r) \<in> rhs}"}.
  

  It is straightforward to prove that the initial equational system satisfies the
  invariant.

  \begin{lmm}\label{invzero}
  @{thm[mode=IfThen] Init_ES_satisfies_invariant}
  \end{lmm}

  \begin{proof}
  Finiteness is given by the assumption and the way how we set up the 
  initial equational system. Soundness is proved in Lem.~\ref{inv}. Distinctness
  follows from the fact that the equivalence classes are disjoint. The @{text ardenable}
  property also follows from the setup of the initial equational system, as does 
  validity.
  \end{proof}

  \noindent
  Next we show that @{text Iter} preserves the invariant.

  \begin{lmm}\label{iterone}
  @{thm[mode=IfThen] iteration_step_invariant[where xrhs="rhs"]}
  \end{lmm}

  \begin{proof} 
  The argument boils down to choosing an equation @{text "Y = yrhs"} to be eliminated
  and to show that @{term "Subst_all (ES - {(Y, yrhs)}) Y (Arden Y yrhs)"} 
  preserves the invariant.
  We prove this as follows:

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}}
  @{text "\<forall> ES."}\\ \mbox{}\hspace{5mm}@{thm (prem 1) Subst_all_satisfies_invariant} implies
  @{thm (concl) Subst_all_satisfies_invariant}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  Finiteness is straightforward, as the @{const Subst} and @{const Arden} operations 
  keep the equational system finite. These operations also preserve soundness 
  and distinctness (we proved soundness for @{const Arden} in Lem.~\ref{ardenable}).
  The property @{text ardenable} is clearly preserved because the append-operation
  cannot make a regular expression to match the empty string. Validity is
  given because @{const Arden} removes an equivalence class from @{text yrhs}
  and then @{const Subst_all} removes @{text Y} from the equational system.
  Having proved the implication above, we can instantiate @{text "ES"} with @{text "ES - {(Y, yrhs)}"}
  which matches with our proof-obligation of @{const "Subst_all"}. Since
  \mbox{@{term "ES = ES - {(Y, yrhs)} \<union> {(Y, yrhs)}"}}, we can use the assumption 
  to complete the proof.
  \end{proof}

  \noindent
  We also need the fact that @{text Iter} decreases the termination measure.

  \begin{lmm}\label{itertwo}
  @{thm[mode=IfThen] iteration_step_measure[simplified (no_asm), where xrhs="rhs"]}
  \end{lmm}

  \begin{proof}
  By assumption we know that @{text "ES"} is finite and has more than one element.
  Therefore there must be an element @{term "(Y, yrhs) \<in> ES"} with 
  @{term "(Y, yrhs) \<noteq> (X, rhs)"}. Using the distinctness property we can infer
  that @{term "Y \<noteq> X"}. We further know that @{text "Remove ES Y yrhs"}
  removes the equation @{text "Y = yrhs"} from the system, and therefore 
  the cardinality of @{const Iter} strictly decreases.
  \end{proof}

  \noindent
  This brings us to our property we want to establish for @{text Solve}.


  \begin{lmm}
  If @{thm (prem 1) Solve} and @{thm (prem 2) Solve} then there exists
  a @{text rhs} such that  @{term "Solve X (Init (UNIV // \<approx>A)) = {(X, rhs)}"}
  and @{term "invariant {(X, rhs)}"}.
  \end{lmm}

  \begin{proof} 
  In order to prove this lemma using \eqref{whileprinciple}, we have to use a slightly
  stronger invariant since Lem.~\ref{iterone} and \ref{itertwo} have the precondition 
  that @{term "(X, rhs) \<in> ES"} for some @{text rhs}. This precondition is needed
  in order to choose in the @{const Iter}-step an equation that is not \mbox{@{term "X = rhs"}}.
  Therefore our invariant cannot be just @{term "invariant ES"}, but must be 
  @{term "invariant ES \<and> (\<exists>rhs. (X, rhs) \<in> ES)"}. By assumption 
  @{thm (prem 2) Solve} and Lem.~\ref{invzero}, the more general invariant holds for
  the initial equational system. This is premise 1 of~\eqref{whileprinciple}.
  Premise 2 is given by Lem.~\ref{iterone} and the fact that @{const Iter} might
  modify the @{text rhs} in the equation @{term "X = rhs"}, but does not remove it.
  Premise 3 of~\eqref{whileprinciple} is by Lem.~\ref{itertwo}. Now in premise 4
  we like to show that there exists a @{text rhs} such that @{term "ES = {(X, rhs)}"}
  and that @{text "invariant {(X, rhs)}"} holds, provided the condition @{text "Cond"}
  does not holds. By the stronger invariant we know there exists such a @{text "rhs"}
  with @{term "(X, rhs) \<in> ES"}. Because @{text Cond} is not true, we know the cardinality
  of @{text ES} is @{text 1}. This means @{text "ES"} must actually be the set @{text "{(X, rhs)}"},
  for which the invariant holds. This allows us to conclude that 
  @{term "Solve X (Init (UNIV // \<approx>A)) = {(X, rhs)}"} and @{term "invariant {(X, rhs)}"} hold,
  as needed.
  \end{proof}

  \noindent
  With this lemma in place we can show that for every equivalence class in @{term "UNIV // \<approx>A"}
  there exists a regular expression.

  \begin{lmm}\label{every_eqcl_has_reg}
  @{thm[mode=IfThen] every_eqcl_has_reg}
  \end{lmm}

  \begin{proof}
  By the preceding lemma, we know that there exists a @{text "rhs"} such
  that @{term "Solve X (Init (UNIV // \<approx>A))"} returns the equation @{text "X = rhs"},
  and that the invariant holds for this equation. That means we 
  know @{text "X = \<Union>\<calL> ` rhs"}. We further know that
  this is equal to \mbox{@{text "\<Union>\<calL> ` (Arden X rhs)"}} using the properties of the 
  invariant and Lem.~\ref{ardenable}. Using the validity property for the equation @{text "X = rhs"},
  we can infer that @{term "rhss rhs \<subseteq> {X}"} and because the @{text Arden} operation
  removes that @{text X} from @{text rhs}, that @{term "rhss (Arden X rhs) = {}"}.
  This means the right-hand side @{term "Arden X rhs"} can only consist of terms of the form @{term "Lam r"}.
  So we can collect those (finitely many) regular expressions @{text rs} and have @{term "X = lang (\<Uplus>rs)"}.
  With this we can conclude the proof.
  \end{proof}

  \noindent
  Lem.~\ref{every_eqcl_has_reg} allows us to finally give a proof for the first direction
  of the Myhill-Nerode theorem.

  \begin{proof}[of Thm.~\ref{myhillnerodeone}]
  By Lem.~\ref{every_eqcl_has_reg} we know that there exists a regular expression for
  every equivalence class in @{term "UNIV // \<approx>A"}. Since @{text "finals A"} is
  a subset of  @{term "UNIV // \<approx>A"}, we also know that for every equivalence class
  in @{term "finals A"} there exists a regular expression. Moreover by assumption 
  we know that @{term "finals A"} must be finite, and therefore there must be a finite
  set of regular expressions @{text "rs"} such that
  @{term "\<Union>(finals A) = lang (\<Uplus>rs)"}.
  Since the left-hand side is equal to @{text A}, we can use @{term "\<Uplus>rs"} 
  as the regular expression that is needed in the theorem.
  \end{proof}
*}




section {* Myhill-Nerode, Second Part *}

text {*
  \noindent
  In this section we will give a proof for establishing the second 
  part of the Myhill-Nerode theorem. It can be formulated in our setting as follows:

  \begin{thrm}
  Given @{text "r"} is a regular expression, then @{thm Myhill_Nerode2}.
  \end{thrm}  

  \noindent
  The proof will be by induction on the structure of @{text r}. It turns out
  the base cases are straightforward.


  \begin{proof}[Base Cases]
  The cases for @{const ZERO}, @{const ONE} and @{const ATOM} are routine, because 
  we can easily establish that

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{l}
  @{thm quot_zero_eq}\\
  @{thm quot_one_subset}\\
  @{thm quot_atom_subset}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  hold, which shows that @{term "UNIV // \<approx>(lang r)"} must be finite.
  \end{proof}

  \noindent
  Much more interesting, however, are the inductive cases. They seem hard to be solved 
  directly. The reader is invited to try. 

  In order to see how our proof proceeds consider the following suggestive picture 
  taken from Constable et al \cite{Constable00}:

  \begin{equation}\label{pics}
  \mbox{\begin{tabular}{c@ {\hspace{10mm}}c@ {\hspace{10mm}}c}
  \begin{tikzpicture}[scale=1]
  %Circle
  \draw[thick] (0,0) circle (1.1);    
  \end{tikzpicture}
  &
  \begin{tikzpicture}[scale=1]
  %Circle
  \draw[thick] (0,0) circle (1.1);    
  %Main rays
  \foreach \a in {0, 90,...,359}
    \draw[very thick] (0, 0) -- (\a:1.1);
  \foreach \a / \l in {45/1, 135/2, 225/3, 315/4}
      \draw (\a: 0.65) node {$a_\l$};
  \end{tikzpicture}
  &
  \begin{tikzpicture}[scale=1]
  %Circle
  \draw[thick] (0,0) circle (1.1);    
  %Main rays
  \foreach \a in {0, 45,...,359}
     \draw[very thick] (0, 0) -- (\a:1.1);
  \foreach \a / \l in {22.5/1.1, 67.5/1.2, 112.5/2.1, 157.5/2.2, 202.4/3.1, 247.5/3.2, 292.5/4.1, 337.5/4.2}
      \draw (\a: 0.77) node {$a_{\l}$};
  \end{tikzpicture}\\
  @{term UNIV} & @{term "UNIV // (\<approx>(lang r))"} & @{term "UNIV // R"}
  \end{tabular}}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  The relation @{term "\<approx>(lang r)"} partitions the set of all strings into some
  equivalence classes. To show that there are only finitely many of them, it
  suffices to show in each induction step that another relation, say @{text
  R}, has finitely many equivalence classes and refines @{term "\<approx>(lang r)"}. 

  \begin{dfntn}
  A relation @{text "R\<^isub>1"} is said to \emph{refine} @{text "R\<^isub>2"}
  provided @{text "R\<^isub>1 \<subseteq> R\<^isub>2"}. 
  \end{dfntn}

  \noindent
  For constructing @{text R} will
  rely on some \emph{tagging-functions} defined over strings. Given the
  inductive hypothesis, it will be easy to prove that the \emph{range} of
  these tagging-functions is finite. The range of a function @{text f} is
  defined as

  \begin{center}
  @{text "range f \<equiv> f ` UNIV"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  that means we take the image of @{text f} w.r.t.~all elements in the
  domain. With this we will be able to infer that the tagging-functions, seen
  as relations, give rise to finitely many equivalence classes. 
  Finally we will show that the tagging-relations are more refined than
  @{term "\<approx>(lang r)"}, which implies that @{term "UNIV // \<approx>(lang r)"} must
  also be finite.  We formally define the notion of a \emph{tagging-relation}
  as follows.


  \begin{dfntn}[Tagging-Relation] Given a tagging-function @{text tag}, then two strings @{text x}
  and @{text y} are \emph{tag-related} provided
  \begin{center}
  @{text "x \<^raw:$\threesim$>\<^bsub>tag\<^esub> y \<equiv> tag x = tag y"}\;.
  \end{center}
  \end{dfntn}


  In order to establish finiteness of a set @{text A}, we shall use the following powerful
  principle from Isabelle/HOL's library.
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{finiteimageD}
  @{thm[mode=IfThen] finite_imageD}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  It states that if an image of a set under an injective function @{text f} (injective over this set) 
  is finite, then the set @{text A} itself must be finite. We can use it to establish the following 
  two lemmas.

  \begin{lmm}\label{finone}
  @{thm[mode=IfThen] finite_eq_tag_rel}
  \end{lmm}

  \begin{proof}
  We set in \eqref{finiteimageD}, @{text f} to be @{text "X \<mapsto> tag ` X"}. We have
  @{text "range f"} to be a subset of @{term "Pow (range tag)"}, which we know must be
  finite by assumption. Now @{term "f (UNIV // =tag=)"} is a subset of @{text "range f"},
  and so also finite. Injectivity amounts to showing that @{text "X = Y"} under the
  assumptions that @{text "X, Y \<in> "}~@{term "UNIV // =tag="} and @{text "f X = f Y"}.
  From the assumptions we can obtain @{text "x \<in> X"} and @{text "y \<in> Y"} with 
  @{text "tag x = tag y"}. Since @{text x} and @{text y} are tag-related, this in 
  turn means that the equivalence classes @{text X}
  and @{text Y} must be equal.
  \end{proof}

  \begin{lmm}\label{fintwo} 
  Given two equivalence relations @{text "R\<^isub>1"} and @{text "R\<^isub>2"}, whereby
  @{text "R\<^isub>1"} refines @{text "R\<^isub>2"}.
  If @{thm (prem 1) refined_partition_finite[where ?R1.0="R\<^isub>1" and ?R2.0="R\<^isub>2"]}
  then @{thm (concl) refined_partition_finite[where ?R1.0="R\<^isub>1" and ?R2.0="R\<^isub>2"]}.
  \end{lmm}

  \begin{proof}
  We prove this lemma again using \eqref{finiteimageD}. This time we set @{text f} to
  be @{text "X \<mapsto>"}~@{term "{R\<^isub>1 `` {x} | x. x \<in> X}"}. It is easy to see that 
  @{term "finite (f ` (UNIV // R\<^isub>2))"} because it is a subset of @{term "Pow (UNIV // R\<^isub>1)"},
  which must be finite by assumption. What remains to be shown is that @{text f} is injective
  on @{term "UNIV // R\<^isub>2"}. This is equivalent to showing that two equivalence 
  classes, say @{text "X"} and @{text Y}, in @{term "UNIV // R\<^isub>2"} are equal, provided
  @{text "f X = f Y"}. For @{text "X = Y"} to be equal, we have to find two elements
  @{text "x \<in> X"} and @{text "y \<in> Y"} such that they are @{text R\<^isub>2} related.
  We know there exists a @{text "x \<in> X"} with \mbox{@{term "X = R\<^isub>2 `` {x}"}}. 
  From the latter fact we can infer that @{term "R\<^isub>1 ``{x} \<in> f X"}
  and further @{term "R\<^isub>1 ``{x} \<in> f Y"}. This means we can obtain a @{text y}
  such that @{term "R\<^isub>1 `` {x} = R\<^isub>1 `` {y}"} holds. Consequently @{text x} and @{text y}
  are @{text "R\<^isub>1"}-related. Since by assumption @{text "R\<^isub>1"} refines @{text "R\<^isub>2"},
  they must also be @{text "R\<^isub>2"}-related, as we need to show.
  \end{proof}

  \noindent
  Chaining Lem.~\ref{finone} and \ref{fintwo} together, means in order to show
  that @{term "UNIV // \<approx>(lang r)"} is finite, we have to construct a tagging-function whose
  range can be shown to be finite and whose tagging-relation refines @{term "\<approx>(lang r)"}.
  Let us attempt the @{const PLUS}-case first. We take as tagging-function 
 
  \begin{center}
  @{thm tag_Plus_def[where A="A" and B="B", THEN meta_eq_app]}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  where @{text "A"} and @{text "B"} are some arbitrary languages. The reason for this choice 
  is that we need to establish that @{term "=(tag_Plus A B)="} refines @{term "\<approx>(A \<union> B)"}. 
  This amounts to showing @{term "x \<approx>A y"} or @{term "x \<approx>B y"} under the assumption
  @{term "x"}~@{term "=(tag_Plus A B)="}~@{term y}. As we shall see, this definition will 
  provide us with just the right assumptions in order to get the proof through.

 \begin{proof}[@{const "PLUS"}-Case]
  We can show in general, if @{term "finite (UNIV // \<approx>A)"} and @{term "finite
  (UNIV // \<approx>B)"} then @{term "finite ((UNIV // \<approx>A) \<times> (UNIV // \<approx>B))"}
  holds. The range of @{term "tag_Plus A B"} is a subset of this product
  set---so finite. For the refinement proof-obligation, we know that @{term
  "(\<approx>A `` {x}, \<approx>B `` {x}) = (\<approx>A `` {y}, \<approx>B `` {y})"} holds by assumption. Then
  clearly either @{term "x \<approx>A y"} or @{term "x \<approx>B y"}, as we needed to
  show. Finally we can discharge this case by setting @{text A} to @{term
  "lang r\<^isub>1"} and @{text B} to @{term "lang r\<^isub>2"}.
  \end{proof}

  \noindent
  The @{const TIMES}-case is slightly more complicated. We first prove the
  following lemma, which will aid the proof about refinement.

  \begin{lmm}\label{refinement}
  The relation @{text "\<^raw:$\threesim$>\<^bsub>tag\<^esub>"} refines @{term "\<approx>A"}, provided for
  all strings @{text x}, @{text y} and @{text z} we have \mbox{@{text "x \<^raw:$\threesim$>\<^bsub>tag\<^esub> y"}}
  and @{term "x @ z \<in> A"} imply @{text "y @ z \<in> A"}.
  \end{lmm}


  \noindent
  We therefore can analyse how the strings @{text "x @ z"} are in the language
  @{text A} and then construct an appropriate tagging-function to infer that
  @{term "y @ z"} are also in @{text A}.  For this we sill need the notion of
  the set of all possible \emph{partitions} of a string

  \begin{equation}
  @{thm Partitions_def}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  If we know that @{text "(x\<^isub>p, x\<^isub>s) \<in> Partitions x"}, we will
  refer to @{text "x\<^isub>p"} as the \emph{prefix} of the string @{text x},
  respectively to @{text "x\<^isub>s"} as the \emph{suffix}.


  Now assuming  @{term "x @ z \<in> A \<cdot> B"} there are only two possible ways of how to `split' 
  this string to be in @{term "A \<cdot> B"}:
  %
  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{c}
  \scalebox{1}{
  \begin{tikzpicture}
    \node[draw,minimum height=3.8ex] (x) { $\hspace{4.8em}@{text x}\hspace{4.8em}$ };
    \node[draw,minimum height=3.8ex, right=-0.03em of x] (za) { $\hspace{0.6em}@{text "z\<^isub>p"}\hspace{0.6em}$ };
    \node[draw,minimum height=3.8ex, right=-0.03em of za] (zza) { $\hspace{2.6em}@{text "z\<^isub>s"}\hspace{2.6em}$  };

    \draw[decoration={brace,transform={yscale=3}},decorate]
           (x.north west) -- ($(za.north west)+(0em,0em)$)
               node[midway, above=0.5em]{@{text x}};

    \draw[decoration={brace,transform={yscale=3}},decorate]
           ($(za.north west)+(0em,0ex)$) -- ($(zza.north east)+(0em,0ex)$)
               node[midway, above=0.5em]{@{text z}};

    \draw[decoration={brace,transform={yscale=3}},decorate]
           ($(x.north west)+(0em,3ex)$) -- ($(zza.north east)+(0em,3ex)$)
               node[midway, above=0.8em]{@{term "x @ z \<in> A \<cdot> B"}};

    \draw[decoration={brace,transform={yscale=3}},decorate]
           ($(za.south east)+(0em,0ex)$) -- ($(x.south west)+(0em,0ex)$)
               node[midway, below=0.5em]{@{text "x @ z\<^isub>p \<in> A"}};

    \draw[decoration={brace,transform={yscale=3}},decorate]
           ($(zza.south east)+(0em,0ex)$) -- ($(za.south east)+(0em,0ex)$)
               node[midway, below=0.5em]{@{text "z\<^isub>s \<in> B"}};
  \end{tikzpicture}}
  \\[2mm]
  \scalebox{1}{
  \begin{tikzpicture}
    \node[draw,minimum height=3.8ex] (xa) { $\hspace{3em}@{text "x\<^isub>p"}\hspace{3em}$ };
    \node[draw,minimum height=3.8ex, right=-0.03em of xa] (xxa) { $\hspace{0.2em}@{text "x\<^isub>s"}\hspace{0.2em}$ };
    \node[draw,minimum height=3.8ex, right=-0.03em of xxa] (z) { $\hspace{5em}@{text z}\hspace{5em}$ };

    \draw[decoration={brace,transform={yscale=3}},decorate]
           (xa.north west) -- ($(xxa.north east)+(0em,0em)$)
               node[midway, above=0.5em]{@{text x}};

    \draw[decoration={brace,transform={yscale=3}},decorate]
           (z.north west) -- ($(z.north east)+(0em,0em)$)
               node[midway, above=0.5em]{@{text z}};

    \draw[decoration={brace,transform={yscale=3}},decorate]
           ($(xa.north west)+(0em,3ex)$) -- ($(z.north east)+(0em,3ex)$)
               node[midway, above=0.8em]{@{term "x @ z \<in> A \<cdot> B"}};

    \draw[decoration={brace,transform={yscale=3}},decorate]
           ($(z.south east)+(0em,0ex)$) -- ($(xxa.south west)+(0em,0ex)$)
               node[midway, below=0.5em]{@{term "x\<^isub>s @ z \<in> B"}};

    \draw[decoration={brace,transform={yscale=3}},decorate]
           ($(xa.south east)+(0em,0ex)$) -- ($(xa.south west)+(0em,0ex)$)
               node[midway, below=0.5em]{@{term "x\<^isub>p \<in> A"}};
  \end{tikzpicture}}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}
  %
  \noindent
  Either @{text x} and a prefix of @{text "z"} is in @{text A} and the rest in @{text B} 
  (first picture) or there is a prefix of @{text x} in @{text A} and the rest is in @{text B} 
  (second picture). In both cases we have to show that @{term "y @ z \<in> A \<cdot> B"}. The first case
  we will only go through if we know that  @{term "x \<approx>A y"} holds @{text "(*)"}. Because then 
  we can infer from @{term "x @ z\<^isub>p \<in> A"} that @{term "y @ z\<^isub>p \<in> A"} holds for all @{text "z\<^isub>p"}.
  In the second case we only know that @{text "x\<^isub>p"} and @{text "x\<^isub>s"} is one possible partition
  of the string @{text x}. We have to know that both @{text "x\<^isub>p"} and the
  corresponding partition @{text "y\<^isub>p"} are in @{text "A"}, and that @{text "x\<^isub>s"} is `@{text B}-related' 
  to @{text "y\<^isub>s"} @{text "(**)"}. From the latter fact we can infer that @{text "y\<^isub>s @ z \<in> B"}.
  This will solve the second case.
  Taking the two requirements, @{text "(*)"} and @{text "(**)"}, together we define the
  tagging-function in the @{const Times}-case as:

  \begin{center}
  @{thm (lhs) tag_Times_def[where ?A="A" and ?B="B"]}~@{text "\<equiv>"}~
  @{text "(\<lbrakk>x\<rbrakk>\<^bsub>\<approx>A\<^esub>, {\<lbrakk>x\<^isub>s\<rbrakk>\<^bsub>\<approx>B\<^esub> | x\<^isub>p \<in> A \<and> (x\<^isub>p, x\<^isub>s) \<in> Partitions x})"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  We have to make the assumption for all suffixes @{text "x\<^isub>s"}, since we do 
  not know anything about how the string @{term x} is partitioned.
  With this definition in place, let us prove the @{const "Times"}-case.


  \begin{proof}[@{const TIMES}-Case]
  If @{term "finite (UNIV // \<approx>A)"} and @{term "finite (UNIV // \<approx>B)"}
  then @{term "finite ((UNIV // \<approx>A) \<times> (Pow (UNIV // \<approx>B)))"} holds. The range of
  @{term "tag_Times A B"} is a subset of this product set, and therefore finite.
  For the refinement of @{term "\<approx>(A \<cdot> B)"} and @{text "\<^raw:$\threesim$>\<^bsub>\<times>tag A B\<^esub>"}, 
  we have by Lemma \ref{refinement} 

  \begin{center}
   @{term "tag_Times A B x = tag_Times A B y"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  and @{term "x @ z \<in> A \<cdot> B"}, and have to establish @{term "y @ z \<in> A \<cdot>
  B"}. As shown in the pictures above, there are two cases to be
  considered. First, there exists a @{text "z\<^isub>p"} and @{text
  "z\<^isub>s"} such that @{term "x @ z\<^isub>p \<in> A"} and @{text "z\<^isub>s
  \<in> B"}.  By the assumption about @{term "tag_Times A B"} we have @{term "\<approx>A
  `` {x} = \<approx>A `` {y}"} and thus @{term "x \<approx>A y"}. Hence by the Myhill-Nerode
  relation @{term "y @ z\<^isub>p \<in> A"} holds. Using @{text "z\<^isub>s \<in> B"},
  we can conclude in this case with @{term "y @ z \<in> A \<cdot> B"} (recall @{text
  "z\<^isub>p @ z\<^isub>s = z"}).

  Second there exists a partition @{text "x\<^isub>p"} and @{text "x\<^isub>s"} with 
  @{text "x\<^isub>p \<in> A"} and @{text "x\<^isub>s @ z \<in> B"}. We therefore have
  
  \begin{center}
  @{text "\<lbrakk>x\<^isub>s\<rbrakk>\<^bsub>\<approx>B\<^esub> \<in> {\<lbrakk>x\<^isub>s\<rbrakk>\<^bsub>\<approx>B\<^esub> | x\<^isub>p \<in> A \<and> (x\<^isub>p, x\<^isub>s) \<in> Partitions x}"}
  \end{center}
  
  \noindent
  and by the assumption about @{term "tag_Times A B"} also 
  
  \begin{center}
  @{text "\<lbrakk>x\<^isub>s\<rbrakk>\<^bsub>\<approx>B\<^esub> \<in> {\<lbrakk>y\<^isub>s\<rbrakk>\<^bsub>\<approx>B\<^esub> | y\<^isub>p \<in> A \<and> (y\<^isub>p, y\<^isub>s) \<in> Partitions y}"}
  \end{center}
  
  \noindent
  This means there must be a partition @{text "y\<^isub>p"} and @{text "y\<^isub>s"}
  such that @{term "y\<^isub>p \<in> A"} and @{term "\<approx>B `` {x\<^isub>s} = \<approx>B ``
  {y\<^isub>s}"}. Unfolding the Myhill-Nerode relation and together with the
  facts that @{text "x\<^isub>p \<in> A"} and \mbox{@{text "x\<^isub>s @ z \<in> B"}}, we
  obtain @{term "y\<^isub>p \<in> A"} and @{text "y\<^isub>s @ z \<in> B"}, as needed in
  this case.  We again can complete the @{const TIMES}-case by setting @{text
  A} to @{term "lang r\<^isub>1"} and @{text B} to @{term "lang r\<^isub>2"}.
  \end{proof}

  \noindent
  The case for @{const Star} is similar to @{const TIMES}, but poses a few
  extra challenges.  To deal with them, we define first the notion of a \emph{string
  prefix} and a \emph{strict string prefix}:

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{l}
  @{text "x \<le> y \<equiv> \<exists>z. y = x @ z"}\\
  @{text "x < y \<equiv> x \<le> y \<and> x \<noteq> y"}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  When analysing the case of @{text "x @ z"} being an element in @{term "A\<star>"}
  and @{text x} is not the empty string, we have the following picture:

  \begin{center}
  \scalebox{1}{
  \begin{tikzpicture}
    \node[draw,minimum height=3.8ex] (xa) { $\hspace{4em}@{text "x\<^bsub>pmax\<^esub>"}\hspace{4em}$ };
    \node[draw,minimum height=3.8ex, right=-0.03em of xa] (xxa) { $\hspace{0.5em}@{text "x\<^bsub>s\<^esub>"}\hspace{0.5em}$ };
    \node[draw,minimum height=3.8ex, right=-0.03em of xxa] (za) { $\hspace{2em}@{text "z\<^isub>a"}\hspace{2em}$ };
    \node[draw,minimum height=3.8ex, right=-0.03em of za] (zb) { $\hspace{7em}@{text "z\<^isub>b"}\hspace{7em}$ };

    \draw[decoration={brace,transform={yscale=3}},decorate]
           (xa.north west) -- ($(xxa.north east)+(0em,0em)$)
               node[midway, above=0.5em]{@{text x}};

    \draw[decoration={brace,transform={yscale=3}},decorate]
           (za.north west) -- ($(zb.north east)+(0em,0em)$)
               node[midway, above=0.5em]{@{text z}};

    \draw[decoration={brace,transform={yscale=3}},decorate]
           ($(xa.north west)+(0em,3ex)$) -- ($(zb.north east)+(0em,3ex)$)
               node[midway, above=0.8em]{@{term "x @ z \<in> A\<star>"}};

    \draw[decoration={brace,transform={yscale=3}},decorate]
           ($(za.south east)+(0em,0ex)$) -- ($(xxa.south west)+(0em,0ex)$)
               node[midway, below=0.5em]{@{term "x\<^isub>s @ z\<^isub>a \<in> A"}};

    \draw[decoration={brace,transform={yscale=3}},decorate]
           ($(xa.south east)+(0em,0ex)$) -- ($(xa.south west)+(0em,0ex)$)
               node[midway, below=0.5em]{@{text "x\<^bsub>pmax\<^esub> \<in> A\<^isup>\<star>"}};

    \draw[decoration={brace,transform={yscale=3}},decorate]
           ($(zb.south east)+(0em,0ex)$) -- ($(zb.south west)+(0em,0ex)$)
               node[midway, below=0.5em]{@{term "z\<^isub>b \<in> A\<star>"}};

    \draw[decoration={brace,transform={yscale=3}},decorate]
           ($(zb.south east)+(0em,-4ex)$) -- ($(xxa.south west)+(0em,-4ex)$)
               node[midway, below=0.5em]{@{term "x\<^isub>s @ z \<in> A\<star>"}};
  \end{tikzpicture}}
  \end{center}
  %
  \noindent
  We can find a strict prefix @{text "x\<^isub>p"} of @{text x} such that @{term "x\<^isub>p \<in> A\<star>"},
  @{text "x\<^isub>p < x"} and the rest @{term "x\<^isub>s @ z \<in> A\<star>"}. For example the empty string 
  @{text "[]"} would do (recall @{term "x \<noteq> []"}).
  There are potentially many such prefixes, but there can only be finitely many of them (the 
  string @{text x} is finite). Let us therefore choose the longest one and call it 
  @{text "x\<^bsub>pmax\<^esub>"}. Now for the rest of the string @{text "x\<^isub>s @ z"} we
  know it is in @{term "A\<star>"} and cannot be the empty string. By Prop.~\ref{langprops}@{text "(iv)"}, 
  we can separate
  this string into two parts, say @{text "a"} and @{text "b"}, such that @{text "a \<noteq> []"}, @{text "a \<in> A"}
  and @{term "b \<in> A\<star>"}. Now @{text a} must be strictly longer than @{text "x\<^isub>s"},
  otherwise @{text "x\<^bsub>pmax\<^esub>"} is not the longest prefix. That means @{text a}
  `overlaps' with @{text z}, splitting it into two components @{text "z\<^isub>a"} and
   @{text "z\<^isub>b"}. For this we know that @{text "x\<^isub>s @ z\<^isub>a \<in> A"} and
  @{term "z\<^isub>b \<in> A\<star>"}. To cut a story short, we have divided @{term "x @ z \<in> A\<star>"}
  such that we have a string @{text a} with @{text "a \<in> A"} that lies just on the
  `border' of @{text x} and @{text z}. This string is @{text "x\<^isub>s @ z\<^isub>a"}.

  In order to show that @{term "x @ z \<in> A\<star>"} implies @{term "y @ z \<in> A\<star>"}, we use
  the following tagging-function:
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{thm (lhs) tag_Star_def[where ?A="A", THEN meta_eq_app]}~@{text "\<equiv>"}~
  @{text "{\<lbrakk>x\<^isub>s\<rbrakk>\<^bsub>\<approx>A\<^esub> | x\<^isub>p < x \<and> x\<^isub>p \<in> A\<^isup>\<star> \<and> (x\<^isub>s, x\<^isub>p) \<in> Partitions x}"}
  \end{center}

  \begin{proof}[@{const Star}-Case]
  If @{term "finite (UNIV // \<approx>A)"} 
  then @{term "finite (Pow (UNIV // \<approx>A))"} holds. The range of
  @{term "tag_Star A"} is a subset of this set, and therefore finite.
  Again we have to show under the assumption @{term "x"}~@{term "=(tag_Star A)="}~@{term y}
  that @{term "x @ z \<in> A\<star>"} implies @{term "y @ z \<in> A\<star>"}.

  We first need to consider the case that @{text x} is the empty string.
  From the assumption about strict prefixes in @{text "\<^raw:$\threesim$>\<^bsub>\<star>tag A\<^esub>"}, we 
  can infer @{text y} is the empty string and
  then clearly have @{term "y @ z \<in> A\<star>"}. In case @{text x} is not the empty
  string, we can divide the string @{text "x @ z"} as shown in the picture 
  above. By the tagging-function and the facts @{text "x\<^bsub>pmax\<^esub> \<in> A\<^isup>\<star>"} and @{text "x\<^bsub>pmax\<^esub> < x"}, 
  we have

  \begin{center}
  @{text "\<lbrakk>x\<^isub>s\<rbrakk>\<^bsub>\<approx>A\<^esub> \<in> {\<lbrakk>x\<^isub>s\<rbrakk>\<^bsub>\<approx>A\<^esub> | x\<^bsub>pmax\<^esub> < x \<and> x\<^bsub>pmax\<^esub> \<in> A\<^isup>\<star> \<and> (x\<^bsub>pmax\<^esub>, x\<^isub>s) \<in> Partitions x}"}
  \end{center}
  
  \noindent
  which by assumption is equal to
  
  \begin{center}
  @{text "\<lbrakk>x\<^isub>s\<rbrakk>\<^bsub>\<approx>A\<^esub> \<in> {\<lbrakk>y\<^isub>s\<rbrakk>\<^bsub>\<approx>A\<^esub> | y\<^bsub>p\<^esub> < y \<and> y\<^bsub>p\<^esub> \<in> A\<^isup>\<star> \<and> (y\<^bsub>p\<^esub>, y\<^isub>s) \<in> Partitions y}"}
  \end{center}
  
  \noindent 
  From this we know there exist partitions @{text "y\<^isub>p"} and @{text
  "y\<^isub>s"} with @{term "y\<^isub>p \<in> A\<star>"} and also @{term "x\<^isub>s \<approx>A
  y\<^isub>s"}. Unfolding the Myhill-Nerode relation we know @{term
  "y\<^isub>s @ z\<^isub>a \<in> A"}. We also know that @{term "z\<^isub>b \<in> A\<star>"}.
  Therefore @{term "y\<^isub>p @ (y\<^isub>s @ z\<^isub>a) @ z\<^isub>b \<in>
  A\<star>"}, which means @{term "y @ z \<in> A\<star>"}. As the last step we have to set
  @{text "A"} to @{term "lang r"} and thus complete the proof.
  \end{proof}
*}

section {* Second Part proved using Partial Derivatives *}

text {*
  \noindent
  As we have seen in the previous section, in order to establish
  the second direction of the Myhill-Nerode theorem, we need to find 
  a more refined relation than @{term "\<approx>(lang r)"} for which we can
  show that there are only finitely many equivalence classes. So far we 
  showed this by induction on @{text "r"}. However, there is also 
  an indirect method to come up with such a refined relation based on
  derivatives of regular expressions \cite{Brzozowski64}. 

  Assume the following two definitions for a \emph{left-quotient} of a language,
  which we write as @{term "Der c A"} and @{term "Ders s A"} where @{text c}
  is a character and @{text s} a string:

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{r@ {\hspace{1mm}}c@ {\hspace{2mm}}l}
  @{thm (lhs) Der_def}  & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) Der_def}\\
  @{thm (lhs) Ders_def} & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) Ders_def}\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  In order to aid readability, we shall also make use of the following abbreviation:

  \begin{center}
  @{abbrev "Derss s A"}
  \end{center}
  

  \noindent
  Clearly we have the following relation between the Myhill-Nerode relation
  (Def.~\ref{myhillneroderel}) and left-quotients

  \begin{equation}\label{mhders}
  @{term "x \<approx>A y"} \hspace{4mm}\text{if and only if}\hspace{4mm} @{term "Ders x A = Ders y A"}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  It is straightforward to establish the following properties for left-quotients:
  
  \begin{equation}
  \mbox{\begin{tabular}{l@ {\hspace{1mm}}c@ {\hspace{2mm}}l}
  @{thm (lhs) Der_simps(1)} & $=$ & @{thm (rhs) Der_simps(1)}\\
  @{thm (lhs) Der_simps(2)} & $=$ & @{thm (rhs) Der_simps(2)}\\
  @{thm (lhs) Der_simps(3)} & $=$ & @{thm (rhs) Der_simps(3)}\\
  @{thm (lhs) Der_simps(4)} & $=$ & @{thm (rhs) Der_simps(4)}\\
  @{thm (lhs) Der_conc}  & $=$ & @{thm (rhs) Der_conc}\\
  @{thm (lhs) Der_star}  & $=$ & @{thm (rhs) Der_star}\\
  @{thm (lhs) Ders_simps(1)} & $=$ & @{thm (rhs) Ders_simps(1)}\\
  @{thm (lhs) Ders_simps(2)} & $=$ & @{thm (rhs) Ders_simps(2)}\\
  %@{thm (lhs) Ders_simps(3)[where ?s1.0="s\<^isub>1" and ?s2.0="s\<^isub>2"]}  & $=$ 
  %   & @{thm (rhs) Ders_simps(3)[where ?s1.0="s\<^isub>1" and ?s2.0="s\<^isub>2"]}\\
  \end{tabular}}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  where @{text "\<Delta>"} is a function that tests whether the empty string
  is in the language and returns @{term "{[]}"} or @{term "{}"}, respectively.
  The only interesting case above is the last one where we use Prop.~\ref{langprops}
  in order to infer that @{term "Der c (A\<star>) = Der c (A \<cdot> A\<star>)"}. We can 
  then complete the proof by observing that @{term "Delta A \<cdot> Der c (A\<star>) \<subseteq> (Der c A) \<cdot> A\<star>"}.
  
  Brzozowski observed that the left-quotients for languages of regular
  expressions can be calculated directly via the notion of \emph{derivatives
  of a regular expression} \cite{Brzozowski64}, which we define in Isabelle/HOL as 
  follows:

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {\hspace{1mm}}c@ {\hspace{1.5mm}}l@ {}}
  @{thm (lhs) der.simps(1)}  & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) der.simps(1)}\\
  @{thm (lhs) der.simps(2)}  & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) der.simps(2)}\\
  @{thm (lhs) der.simps(3)[where c'="d"]}  & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) der.simps(3)[where c'="d"]}\\
  @{thm (lhs) der.simps(4)[where ?r1.0="r\<^isub>1" and ?r2.0="r\<^isub>2"]}  
     & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) der.simps(4)[where ?r1.0="r\<^isub>1" and ?r2.0="r\<^isub>2"]}\\
  @{thm (lhs) der.simps(5)[where ?r1.0="r\<^isub>1" and ?r2.0="r\<^isub>2"]}  
     & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{text "if"}~@{term "nullable r\<^isub>1"}~@{text "then"}~%
       @{term "Plus (Times (der c r\<^isub>1) r\<^isub>2) (der c r\<^isub>2)"}\\
     &             & \phantom{@{text "if"}~@{term "nullable r\<^isub>1"}~}@{text "else"}~%  
                    @{term "Times (der c r\<^isub>1) r\<^isub>2"}\\ 
  @{thm (lhs) der.simps(6)}  & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) der.simps(6)}\smallskip\\
  @{thm (lhs) ders.simps(1)}  & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) ders.simps(1)}\\
  @{thm (lhs) ders.simps(2)}  & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) ders.simps(2)}\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  The last two clauses extend derivatives for characters to strings (list of
  characters). The list-cons operator is written \mbox{@{text "_ :: _"}}. The
  function @{term "nullable r"} needed in the @{const Times}-case tests
  whether a regular expression can recognise the empty string:

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{c@ {\hspace{10mm}}c}
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {\hspace{1mm}}c@ {\hspace{1.5mm}}l@ {}}
  @{thm (lhs) nullable.simps(1)}  & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) nullable.simps(1)}\\
  @{thm (lhs) nullable.simps(2)}  & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) nullable.simps(2)}\\
  @{thm (lhs) nullable.simps(3)}  & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) nullable.simps(3)}\\
  \end{tabular} &
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {\hspace{1mm}}c@ {\hspace{1.5mm}}l@ {}}
  @{thm (lhs) nullable.simps(4)[where ?r1.0="r\<^isub>1" and ?r2.0="r\<^isub>2"]}  
     & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) nullable.simps(4)[where ?r1.0="r\<^isub>1" and ?r2.0="r\<^isub>2"]}\\
  @{thm (lhs) nullable.simps(5)[where ?r1.0="r\<^isub>1" and ?r2.0="r\<^isub>2"]}  
     & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) nullable.simps(5)[where ?r1.0="r\<^isub>1" and ?r2.0="r\<^isub>2"]}\\
  @{thm (lhs) nullable.simps(6)}  & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) nullable.simps(6)}\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  By induction on the regular expression @{text r}, respectively the string @{text s}, 
  one can easily show that left-quotients and derivatives relate as follows 
  \cite{Sakarovitch09}:

  \begin{equation}\label{Dersders}
  \mbox{\begin{tabular}{c}
  @{thm Der_der}\\
  @{thm Ders_ders}
  \end{tabular}}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  The importance in the context of the Myhill-Nerode theorem is that 
  we can use \eqref{mhders} and \eqref{Dersders} in order to 
  establish that @{term "x \<approx>(lang r) y"} is equivalent to
  @{term "lang (ders x r) = lang (ders y r)"}. From this we obtain

  \begin{equation}
  @{term "x \<approx>(lang r) y"}\hspace{4mm}\mbox{provided}\hspace{4mm}@{term "ders x r = ders y r"}
  \end{equation}


  \noindent
  which means the right-hand side (seen as relation) refines the
  Myhill-Nerode relation.  Consequently, we can use 
  @{text "\<^raw:$\threesim$>\<^bsub>(\<lambda>x. ders x r)\<^esub>"} as a potential tagging-relation
  for the regular expression @{text r}. However, in
  order to be useful in the Myhill-Nerode theorem, we also have to show that
  for the corresponding language there are only finitely many derivatives---ensuring
  that there are only finitely many equivalence classes. Unfortunately, this
  is not true in general. Sakarovitch gives an example where a regular
  expression  has infinitely many derivatives w.r.t.~a language
  \cite[Page~141]{Sakarovitch09}. What Brzozowski \cite{Brzozowski64} proved
  is that for every language there \emph{are} only finitely `dissimilar'
  derivatives for a regular expression. Two regular expressions are said to be
  \emph{similar} provided they can be identified using the using the @{text
  "ACI"}-identities:

  \begin{equation}\label{ACI}
  \mbox{\begin{tabular}{cl}
  (@{text A}) & @{term "Plus (Plus r\<^isub>1 r\<^isub>2) r\<^isub>3"} $\equiv$ @{term "Plus r\<^isub>1 (Plus r\<^isub>2 r\<^isub>3)"}\\
  (@{text C}) & @{term "Plus r\<^isub>1 r\<^isub>2"} $\equiv$ @{term "Plus r\<^isub>2 r\<^isub>1"}\\
  (@{text I}) & @{term "Plus r r"} $\equiv$ @{term "r"}\\
  \end{tabular}}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  Carrying this idea through, we must not consider the set of all derivatives,
  but the ones modulo @{text "ACI"}.  In principle, this can be formally
  defined, but it is very painful in a theorem prover (since there is no
  direct characterisation of the set of dissimlar derivatives).


  Fortunately, there is a much simpler approach using \emph{partial
  derivatives}. They were introduced by Antimirov \cite{Antimirov95} and can be defined
  in Isabelle/HOL as follows:

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {\hspace{1mm}}c@ {\hspace{1.5mm}}l@ {}}
  @{thm (lhs) pder.simps(1)}  & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) pder.simps(1)}\\
  @{thm (lhs) pder.simps(2)}  & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) pder.simps(2)}\\
  @{thm (lhs) pder.simps(3)[where c'="d"]}  & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) pder.simps(3)[where c'="d"]}\\
  @{thm (lhs) pder.simps(4)[where ?r1.0="r\<^isub>1" and ?r2.0="r\<^isub>2"]}  
     & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) pder.simps(4)[where ?r1.0="r\<^isub>1" and ?r2.0="r\<^isub>2"]}\\
  @{thm (lhs) pder.simps(5)[where ?r1.0="r\<^isub>1" and ?r2.0="r\<^isub>2"]}  
     & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{text "if"}~@{term "nullable r\<^isub>1"}~@{text "then"}~%
       @{term "(Timess (pder c r\<^isub>1) r\<^isub>2) \<union> (pder c r\<^isub>2)"}\\
     & & \phantom{@{text "if"}~@{term "nullable r\<^isub>1"}~}@{text "else"}~%  
                    @{term "Timess (pder c r\<^isub>1) r\<^isub>2"}\\ 
  @{thm (lhs) pder.simps(6)}  & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) pder.simps(6)}\smallskip\\
  @{thm (lhs) pders.simps(1)}  & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) pders.simps(1)}\\
  @{thm (lhs) pders.simps(2)}  & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{text "\<Union> (pders s) ` (pder c r)"}\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  Again the last two clauses extend partial derivatives from characters to strings. 
  Unlike `simple' derivatives, the functions for partial derivatives return sets of regular
  expressions. In the @{const Times} and @{const Star} cases we therefore use the
  auxiliary definition

  \begin{center}
  @{text "TIMESS rs r \<equiv> {TIMES r' r | r' \<in> rs}"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  in order to `sequence' a regular expression with a set of regular
  expressions. Note that in the last clause we first build the set of partial
  derivatives w.r.t~the character @{text c}, then build the image of this set under the
  function @{term "pders s"} and finally `union up' all resulting sets. It will be
  convenient to introduce the following abbreviation

  \begin{center}
  @{abbrev "pderss s A"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  which simplifies the last clause of @{const "pders"} to

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {\hspace{1mm}}c@ {\hspace{1.5mm}}l@ {}}
  @{thm (lhs) pders.simps(2)}  & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) pders.simps(2)}\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  Partial derivatives can be seen as having the @{text "ACI"}-identities already built in: 
  taking the partial derivatives of the
  regular expressions in \eqref{ACI} gives us in each case
  equal sets.  Antimirov \cite{Antimirov95} showed a similar result to
  \eqref{Dersders} for partial derivatives:

  \begin{equation}
  \mbox{\begin{tabular}{lc}
  @{text "(i)"}  & @{thm Der_pder}\\
  @{text "(ii)"} & @{thm Ders_pders}
  \end{tabular}}
  \end{equation} 

  \begin{proof}
  The first fact is by a simple induction on @{text r}. For the second we slightly
  modify Antimirov's proof by performing an induction on @{text s} where we
  genaralise over all @{text r}. That means in the @{text "cons"}-case the 
  induction hypothesis is

  \begin{center}
  @{text "(IH)"}\hspace{3mm}@{term "\<forall>r. Ders s (lang r) = \<Union> lang ` (pders s r)"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  With this we can establish

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{r@ {\hspace{1.5mm}}c@ {\hspace{1.5mm}}ll}
  @{term "Ders (c # s) (lang r)"} 
    & @{text "="} & @{term "Ders s (Der c (lang r))"} & by def.\\
    & @{text "="} & @{term "Ders s (\<Union> lang ` (pder c r))"} & by @{text "(i)"}\\
    & @{text "="} & @{term "\<Union> (Ders s) ` (lang ` (pder c r))"} & by def.~of @{text "Ders"}\\
    & @{text "="} & @{term "\<Union> lang ` (\<Union> pders s ` (pder c r))"} & by IH\\
    & @{text "="} & @{term "\<Union> lang ` (pders (c # s) r)"} & by def.\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}
  
  \noindent
  In order to apply the induction hypothesis in the fourth step, we need the generalisation
  over all regular expressions @{text r}. The case for the empty string is routine and omitted.
  \end{proof}

  Antimirov also proved that for every language and regular expression there are only finitely
  many partial derivatives.
*}

section {* Closure Properties *}

text {*
  \noindent
  The real beauty of regular languages is that they are closed
  under almost all set operations. Closure under union, concatenation and Kleene-star
  are trivial to establish given our definition of regularity (Def.~\ref{regular}).
  More interesting is the closure under complement, because
  it seems difficult to construct a regular expression for the complement
  language by direct means. However the existence of such a regular expression
  can now be easily proved using the Myhill-Nerode theorem since 
  
  \begin{center}
  @{term "s\<^isub>1 \<approx>A s\<^isub>2"} if and only if @{term "s\<^isub>1 \<approx>(-A) s\<^isub>2"}
  \end{center}
  
  \noindent
  holds for any strings @{text "s\<^isub>1"} and @{text
  "s\<^isub>2"}. Therefore @{text A} and the complement language @{term "-A"}
  give rise to the same partitions.

  Once closure under complement is established, closure under intersection
  and set difference is also easy, because

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{c}
  @{term "A \<inter> B = - (- A \<union> - B)"}\\
  @{term "A - B = - (- A \<union> B)"}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  Closure of regular languages under reversal, which means 

  \begin{center}
  @{text "A\<^bsup>-1\<^esup> \<equiv> {s\<^bsup>-1\<^esup> | s \<in> A}"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent 
  can be shown with the help of the following operation defined on regular
  expressions

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{r@ {\hspace{1mm}}c@ {\hspace{1mm}}l}
  @{thm (lhs) Rev.simps(1)} & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) Rev.simps(1)}\\
  @{thm (lhs) Rev.simps(2)} & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) Rev.simps(2)}\\
  @{thm (lhs) Rev.simps(3)} & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) Rev.simps(3)}\\
  @{thm (lhs) Rev.simps(4)[where ?r1.0="r\<^isub>1" and ?r2.0="r\<^isub>2"]} & @{text "\<equiv>"} & 
      @{thm (rhs) Rev.simps(4)[where ?r1.0="r\<^isub>1" and ?r2.0="r\<^isub>2"]}\\
  @{thm (lhs) Rev.simps(5)[where ?r1.0="r\<^isub>1" and ?r2.0="r\<^isub>2"]} & @{text "\<equiv>"} & 
      @{thm (rhs) Rev.simps(5)[where ?r1.0="r\<^isub>1" and ?r2.0="r\<^isub>2"]}\\
  @{thm (lhs) Rev.simps(6)} & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) Rev.simps(6)}\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}


  In connection with left-quotient, the perhaps surprising fact is that
  regular languages are closed under any left-quotient.

  
*}


section {* Conclusion and Related Work *}

text {*
  \noindent
  In this paper we took the view that a regular language is one where there
  exists a regular expression that matches all of its strings. Regular
  expressions can conveniently be defined as a datatype in HOL-based theorem
  provers. For us it was therefore interesting to find out how far we can push
  this point of view. We have established in Isabelle/HOL both directions 
  of the Myhill-Nerode theorem.
  %
  \begin{thrm}[The Myhill-Nerode Theorem]\mbox{}\\
  A language @{text A} is regular if and only if @{thm (rhs) Myhill_Nerode}.
  \end{thrm}
  
  \noindent
  Having formalised this theorem means we pushed our point of view quite
  far. Using this theorem we can obviously prove when a language is \emph{not}
  regular---by establishing that it has infinitely many equivalence classes
  generated by the Myhill-Nerode relation (this is usually the purpose of the
  pumping lemma \cite{Kozen97}).  We can also use it to establish the standard
  textbook results about closure properties of regular languages. Interesting
  is the case of closure under complement, because it seems difficult to
  construct a regular expression for the complement language by direct
  means. However the existence of such a regular expression can be easily
  proved using the Myhill-Nerode theorem.  Proving the existence of such a
  regular expression via automata using the standard method would be quite
  involved. It includes the steps: regular expression @{text "\<Rightarrow>"}
  non-deterministic automaton @{text "\<Rightarrow>"} deterministic automaton @{text "\<Rightarrow>"}
  complement automaton @{text "\<Rightarrow>"} regular expression.


  While regular expressions are convenient in formalisations, they have some
  limitations. One is that there seems to be no method of calculating a
  minimal regular expression (for example in terms of length) for a regular
  language, like there is
  for automata. On the other hand, efficient regular expression matching,
  without using automata, poses no problem \cite{OwensReppyTuron09}.
  For an implementation of a simple regular expression matcher,
  whose correctness has been formally established, we refer the reader to
  Owens and Slind \cite{OwensSlind08}.


  Our formalisation consists of 780 lines of Isabelle/Isar code for the first
  direction and 460 for the second, plus around 300 lines of standard material
  about regular languages. While this might be seen large, it should be seen
  in the context of the work done by Constable at al \cite{Constable00} who
  formalised the Myhill-Nerode theorem in Nuprl using automata. They write
  that their four-member team needed something on the magnitude of 18 months
  for their formalisation. The estimate for our formalisation is that we
  needed approximately 3 months and this included the time to find our proof
  arguments. Unlike Constable et al, who were able to follow the proofs from
  \cite{HopcroftUllman69}, we had to find our own arguments.  So for us the
  formalisation was not the bottleneck. It is hard to gauge the size of a
  formalisation in Nurpl, but from what is shown in the Nuprl Math Library
  about their development it seems substantially larger than ours. The code of
  ours can be found in the Mercurial Repository at
  \mbox{\url{http://www4.in.tum.de/~urbanc/regexp.html}}.



  Our proof of the first direction is very much inspired by \emph{Brzozowski's
  algebraic method} used to convert a finite automaton to a regular
  expression \cite{Brzozowski64}. The close connection can be seen by considering the equivalence
  classes as the states of the minimal automaton for the regular language.
  However there are some subtle differences. Since we identify equivalence
  classes with the states of the automaton, then the most natural choice is to
  characterise each state with the set of strings starting from the initial
  state leading up to that state. Usually, however, the states are characterised as the
  strings starting from that state leading to the terminal states.  The first
  choice has consequences about how the initial equational system is set up. We have
  the $\lambda$-term on our `initial state', while Brzozowski has it on the
  terminal states. This means we also need to reverse the direction of Arden's
  Lemma.

  This is also where our method shines, because we can completely
  side-step the standard argument \cite{Kozen97} where automata need
  to be composed, which as stated in the Introduction is not so easy
  to formalise in a HOL-based theorem prover. However, it is also the
  direction where we had to spend most of the `conceptual' time, as
  our proof-argument based on tagging-functions is new for
  establishing the Myhill-Nerode theorem. All standard proofs of this
  direction proceed by arguments over automata.\medskip

  We expect that the development of Krauss \& Nipkow gets easier by
  using partial derivatives.\medskip
  
  \noindent
  {\bf Acknowledgements:}
  We are grateful for the comments we received from Larry
  Paulson.

*}


(*<*)
end
(*>*)