(*<*)
theory Paper
imports "../Myhill" "LaTeXsugar"
begin
declare [[show_question_marks = false]]
consts
REL :: "(string \<times> string) \<Rightarrow> bool"
notation (latex output)
str_eq_rel ("\<approx>\<^bsub>_\<^esub>") and
Seq (infixr "\<cdot>" 100) and
Star ("_\<^bsup>\<star>\<^esup>") and
pow ("_\<^bsup>_\<^esup>" [100, 100] 100) and
Suc ("_+1" [100] 100) and
quotient ("_ \<^raw:\ensuremath{\!\sslash\!}> _" [90, 90] 90) and
REL ("\<approx>")
(*>*)
section {* Introduction *}
text {*
Regular languages are an important and well-understood subject in Computer
Science with many beautiful theorems and many useful algorithms. There is a
wide range of textbooks about this subject. Many of these textbooks, such as
\cite{Kozen97}, are aimed at students and contain very detailed
``pencil-and-paper'' proofs. It seems natural to exercise theorem provers by
formalising these theorems and by verifying formally the algorithms. There
is however a problem: the typical approach to regular languages is to start
with finite automata.
Therefore instead of defining a regular language as being one where there exists an
automata that regognises all of its strings, we define
\begin{definition}[A Regular Language]
A language @{text A} is regular, if there is a regular expression that matches all
strings of @{text "A"}.
\end{definition}
\noindent
{\bf Contributions:} A proof of the Myhil-Nerode Theorem based on regular expressions. The
finiteness part of this theorem is proved using tagging-functions (which to our knowledge
are novel in this context).
*}
section {* Preliminaries *}
text {*
Strings in Isabelle/HOL are lists of characters and the
\emph{empty string} is the empty list, written @{term "[]"}. \emph{Languages} are sets of
strings. The language containing all strings is written in Isabelle/HOL as @{term "UNIV::string set"}.
The notation for the quotient of a language @{text A} according to a relation @{term REL} is
@{term "A // REL"}. The concatenation of two languages is written @{term "A ;; B"}; a language
raised tow the power $n$ is written @{term "A \<up> n"}. Both concepts are defined as
\begin{center}
@{thm Seq_def[THEN eq_reflection, where A1="A" and B1="B"]}
\hspace{7mm}
@{thm pow.simps(1)[THEN eq_reflection, where A1="A"]}
\hspace{7mm}
@{thm pow.simps(2)[THEN eq_reflection, where A1="A" and n1="n"]}
\end{center}
\noindent
where @{text "@"} is the usual list-append operation. The Kleene-star of a language @{text A}
is defined as the union over all powers, namely @{thm Star_def}.
Regular expressions are defined as the following datatype
\begin{center}
@{text r} @{text "::="}
@{term NULL}\hspace{1.5mm}@{text"|"}\hspace{1.5mm}
@{term EMPTY}\hspace{1.5mm}@{text"|"}\hspace{1.5mm}
@{term "CHAR c"}\hspace{1.5mm}@{text"|"}\hspace{1.5mm}
@{term "SEQ r r"}\hspace{1.5mm}@{text"|"}\hspace{1.5mm}
@{term "ALT r r"}\hspace{1.5mm}@{text"|"}\hspace{1.5mm}
@{term "STAR r"}
\end{center}
Central to our proof will be the solution of equational systems
involving regular expressions. For this we will use the following ``reverse''
version of Arden's lemma.
\begin{lemma}[Reverse Arden's Lemma]\mbox{}\\
If @{thm (prem 1) ardens_revised} then
@{thm (lhs) ardens_revised} has the unique solution
@{thm (rhs) ardens_revised}.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
For the right-to-left direction we assume @{thm (rhs) ardens_revised} and show
that @{thm (lhs) ardens_revised} holds. From Lemma ??? we have @{term "A\<star> = {[]} \<union> A ;; A\<star>"},
which is equal to @{term "A\<star> = {[]} \<union> A\<star> ;; A"}. Adding @{text B} to both
sides gives @{term "B ;; A\<star> = B ;; ({[]} \<union> A\<star> ;; A)"}, whose right-hand side
is equal to @{term "(B ;; A\<star>) ;; A \<union> B"}. This completes this direction.
For the other direction we assume @{thm (lhs) ardens_revised}. By a simple induction
on @{text n}, we can establish the property
\begin{center}
@{text "(*)"}\hspace{5mm} @{thm (concl) ardens_helper}
\end{center}
\noindent
Using this property we can show that @{term "B ;; (A \<up> n) \<subseteq> X"} holds for
all @{text n}. From this we can infer @{term "B ;; A\<star> \<subseteq> X"} using Lemma ???.
For the inclusion in the other direction we assume a string @{text s}
with length @{text k} is element in @{text X}. Since @{thm (prem 1) ardens_revised}
we know that @{term "s \<notin> X ;; (A \<up> Suc k)"} since its length is only @{text k}
(the strings in @{term "X ;; (A \<up> Suc k)"} are all longer).
From @{text "(*)"} it follows then that
@{term s} must be element in @{term "(\<Union>m\<in>{0..k}. B ;; (A \<up> m))"}. This in turn
implies that @{term s} is in @{term "(\<Union>n. B ;; (A \<up> n))"}. Using Lemma ??? this
is equal to @{term "B ;; A\<star>"}, as we needed to show.\qed
\end{proof}
*}
section {* Finite Partitions Imply Regularity of a Language *}
text {*
\begin{theorem}
Given a language @{text A}.
@{thm[mode=IfThen] hard_direction[where Lang="A"]}
\end{theorem}
*}
section {* Regular Expressions Generate Finitely Many Partitions *}
text {*
\begin{theorem}
Given @{text "r"} is a regular expressions, then @{thm rexp_imp_finite}.
\end{theorem}
\begin{proof}
By induction on the structure of @{text r}. The cases for @{const NULL}, @{const EMPTY}
and @{const CHAR} are straightforward, because we can easily establish
\begin{center}
\begin{tabular}{l}
@{thm quot_null_eq}\\
@{thm quot_empty_subset}\\
@{thm quot_char_subset}
\end{tabular}
\end{center}
\end{proof}
*}
section {* Conclusion and Related Work *}
(*<*)
end
(*>*)