Paper/Paper.thy
author Cezary Kaliszyk <kaliszyk@in.tum.de>
Thu, 19 Aug 2010 14:28:54 +0900
changeset 2414 67e57fc3cd2a
parent 2381 fd85f4921654
child 2465 07ffa4e41659
permissions -rw-r--r--
TODO

(*<*)
theory Paper
imports "../Nominal/NewParser" "LaTeXsugar"
begin

consts
  fv :: "'a \<Rightarrow> 'b"
  abs_set :: "'a \<Rightarrow> 'b \<Rightarrow> 'c"
  alpha_bn :: "'a \<Rightarrow> 'a \<Rightarrow> bool"
  abs_set2 :: "'a \<Rightarrow> perm \<Rightarrow> 'b \<Rightarrow> 'c"
  Abs_dist :: "'a \<Rightarrow> 'b \<Rightarrow> 'c" 
  Abs_print :: "'a \<Rightarrow> 'b \<Rightarrow> 'c" 

definition
 "equal \<equiv> (op =)" 

notation (latex output)
  swap ("'(_ _')" [1000, 1000] 1000) and
  fresh ("_ # _" [51, 51] 50) and
  fresh_star ("_ #\<^sup>* _" [51, 51] 50) and
  supp ("supp _" [78] 73) and
  uminus ("-_" [78] 73) and
  If  ("if _ then _ else _" 10) and
  alpha_gen ("_ \<approx>\<^raw:\,\raisebox{-1pt}{\makebox[0mm][l]{$_{\textit{set}}$}}>\<^bsup>_, _, _\<^esup> _") and
  alpha_lst ("_ \<approx>\<^raw:\,\raisebox{-1pt}{\makebox[0mm][l]{$_{\textit{list}}$}}>\<^bsup>_, _, _\<^esup> _") and
  alpha_res ("_ \<approx>\<^raw:\,\raisebox{-1pt}{\makebox[0mm][l]{$_{\textit{res}}$}}>\<^bsup>_, _, _\<^esup> _") and
  abs_set ("_ \<approx>\<^raw:{$\,_{\textit{abs\_set}}$}> _") and
  abs_set2 ("_ \<approx>\<^raw:\raisebox{-1pt}{\makebox[0mm][l]{$\,_{\textit{list}}$}}>\<^bsup>_\<^esup>  _") and
  fv ("fa'(_')" [100] 100) and
  equal ("=") and
  alpha_abs ("_ \<approx>\<^raw:{$\,_{\textit{abs\_set}}$}> _") and 
  Abs ("[_]\<^bsub>set\<^esub>._" [20, 101] 999) and
  Abs_lst ("[_]\<^bsub>list\<^esub>._") and
  Abs_dist ("[_]\<^bsub>#list\<^esub>._") and
  Abs_res ("[_]\<^bsub>res\<^esub>._") and
  Abs_print ("_\<^bsub>set\<^esub>._") and
  Cons ("_::_" [78,77] 73) and
  supp_gen ("aux _" [1000] 10) and
  alpha_bn ("_ \<approx>bn _")

consts alpha_trm ::'a
consts fa_trm :: 'a
consts alpha_trm2 ::'a
consts fa_trm2 :: 'a
consts ast :: 'a
consts ast' :: 'a
notation (latex output) 
  alpha_trm ("\<approx>\<^bsub>trm\<^esub>") and
  fa_trm ("fa\<^bsub>trm\<^esub>") and
  alpha_trm2 ("'(\<approx>\<^bsub>assn\<^esub>, \<approx>\<^bsub>trm\<^esub>')") and
  fa_trm2 ("'(fa\<^bsub>assn\<^esub>, fa\<^bsub>trm\<^esub>')") and
  ast ("'(as, t')") and
  ast' ("'(as', t\<PRIME> ')")

(*>*)


section {* Introduction *}

text {*

  So far, Nominal Isabelle provided a mechanism for constructing
  $\alpha$-equated terms, for example lambda-terms

  \begin{center}
  @{text "t ::= x | t t | \<lambda>x. t"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  where free and bound variables have names.  For such $\alpha$-equated terms,
  Nominal Isabelle derives automatically a reasoning infrastructure that has
  been used successfully in formalisations of an equivalence checking
  algorithm for LF \cite{UrbanCheneyBerghofer08}, Typed
  Scheme~\cite{TobinHochstadtFelleisen08}, several calculi for concurrency
  \cite{BengtsonParow09} and a strong normalisation result for cut-elimination
  in classical logic \cite{UrbanZhu08}. It has also been used by Pollack for
  formalisations in the locally-nameless approach to binding
  \cite{SatoPollack10}.

  However, Nominal Isabelle has fared less well in a formalisation of
  the algorithm W \cite{UrbanNipkow09}, where types and type-schemes are,
  respectively, of the form
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{tysch}
  \begin{array}{l}
  @{text "T ::= x | T \<rightarrow> T"}\hspace{5mm}
  @{text "S ::= \<forall>{x\<^isub>1,\<dots>, x\<^isub>n}. T"}
  \end{array}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  and the @{text "\<forall>"}-quantification binds a finite (possibly empty) set of
  type-variables.  While it is possible to implement this kind of more general
  binders by iterating single binders, this leads to a rather clumsy
  formalisation of W. The need of iterating single binders is also one reason
  why Nominal Isabelle and similar theorem provers that only provide
  mechanisms for binding single variables have not fared extremely well with the
  more advanced tasks in the POPLmark challenge \cite{challenge05}, because
  also there one would like to bind multiple variables at once.

  Binding multiple variables has interesting properties that cannot be captured
  easily by iterating single binders. For example in the case of type-schemes we do not
  want to make a distinction about the order of the bound variables. Therefore
  we would like to regard the following two type-schemes as $\alpha$-equivalent
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{ex1}
  @{text "\<forall>{x, y}. x \<rightarrow> y  \<approx>\<^isub>\<alpha>  \<forall>{y, x}. x \<rightarrow> y"} 
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  but assuming that @{text x}, @{text y} and @{text z} are distinct variables,
  the following two should \emph{not} be $\alpha$-equivalent
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{ex2}
  @{text "\<forall>{x, y}. x \<rightarrow> y  \<notapprox>\<^isub>\<alpha>  \<forall>{z}. z \<rightarrow> z"} 
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  Moreover, we like to regard type-schemes as $\alpha$-equivalent, if they differ
  only on \emph{vacuous} binders, such as
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{ex3}
  @{text "\<forall>{x}. x \<rightarrow> y  \<approx>\<^isub>\<alpha>  \<forall>{x, z}. x \<rightarrow> y"}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  where @{text z} does not occur freely in the type.  In this paper we will
  give a general binding mechanism and associated notion of $\alpha$-equivalence
  that can be used to faithfully represent this kind of binding in Nominal
  Isabelle.  The difficulty of finding the right notion for $\alpha$-equivalence
  can be appreciated in this case by considering that the definition given by
  Leroy in \cite{Leroy92} is incorrect (it omits a side-condition). 

  However, the notion of $\alpha$-equivalence that is preserved by vacuous
  binders is not always wanted. For example in terms like
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{one}
  @{text "\<LET> x = 3 \<AND> y = 2 \<IN> x - y \<END>"}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  we might not care in which order the assignments @{text "x = 3"} and
  \mbox{@{text "y = 2"}} are given, but it would be unusual to regard
  \eqref{one} as $\alpha$-equivalent with
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "\<LET> x = 3 \<AND> y = 2 \<AND> z = loop \<IN> x - y \<END>"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  Therefore we will also provide a separate binding mechanism for cases in
  which the order of binders does not matter, but the ``cardinality'' of the
  binders has to agree.

  However, we found that this is still not sufficient for dealing with
  language constructs frequently occurring in programming language
  research. For example in @{text "\<LET>"}s containing patterns like
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{two}
  @{text "\<LET> (x, y) = (3, 2) \<IN> x - y \<END>"}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  we want to bind all variables from the pattern inside the body of the
  $\mathtt{let}$, but we also care about the order of these variables, since
  we do not want to regard \eqref{two} as $\alpha$-equivalent with
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "\<LET> (y, x) = (3, 2) \<IN> x - y \<END>"}
  \end{center}
  %
  \noindent
  As a result, we provide three general binding mechanisms each of which binds
  multiple variables at once, and let the user chose which one is intended
  when formalising a term-calculus.

  By providing these general binding mechanisms, however, we have to work
  around a problem that has been pointed out by Pottier \cite{Pottier06} and
  Cheney \cite{Cheney05}: in @{text "\<LET>"}-constructs of the form
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "\<LET> x\<^isub>1 = t\<^isub>1 \<AND> \<dots> \<AND> x\<^isub>n = t\<^isub>n \<IN> s \<END>"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  which bind all the @{text "x\<^isub>i"} in @{text s}, we might not care
  about the order in which the @{text "x\<^isub>i = t\<^isub>i"} are given,
  but we do care about the information that there are as many @{text
  "x\<^isub>i"} as there are @{text "t\<^isub>i"}. We lose this information if
  we represent the @{text "\<LET>"}-constructor by something like
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "\<LET> (\<lambda>x\<^isub>1\<dots>x\<^isub>n . s)  [t\<^isub>1,\<dots>,t\<^isub>n]"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  where the notation @{text "\<lambda>_ . _"} indicates that the list of @{text
  "x\<^isub>i"} becomes bound in @{text s}. In this representation the term
  \mbox{@{text "\<LET> (\<lambda>x . s)  [t\<^isub>1, t\<^isub>2]"}} is a perfectly legal
  instance, but the lengths of the two lists do not agree. To exclude such
  terms, additional predicates about well-formed terms are needed in order to
  ensure that the two lists are of equal length. This can result in very messy
  reasoning (see for example~\cite{BengtsonParow09}). To avoid this, we will
  allow type specifications for @{text "\<LET>"}s as follows
  %
  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{r@ {\hspace{2mm}}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l}
  @{text trm} & @{text "::="}  & @{text "\<dots>"}\\ 
              & @{text "|"}    & @{text "\<LET>  as::assn  s::trm"}\hspace{4mm} 
                                 \isacommand{bind} @{text "bn(as)"} \isacommand{in} @{text "s"}\\[1mm]
  @{text assn} & @{text "::="} & @{text "\<ANIL>"}\\
               & @{text "|"}   & @{text "\<ACONS>  name  trm  assn"}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  where @{text assn} is an auxiliary type representing a list of assignments
  and @{text bn} an auxiliary function identifying the variables to be bound
  by the @{text "\<LET>"}. This function can be defined by recursion over @{text
  assn} as follows

  \begin{center}
  @{text "bn(\<ANIL>) ="} @{term "{}"} \hspace{5mm} 
  @{text "bn(\<ACONS> x t as) = {x} \<union> bn(as)"} 
  \end{center}
  
  \noindent
  The scope of the binding is indicated by labels given to the types, for
  example @{text "s::trm"}, and a binding clause, in this case
  \isacommand{bind} @{text "bn(as)"} \isacommand{in} @{text "s"}. This binding
  clause states that all the names the function @{text
  "bn(as)"} returns should be bound in @{text s}.  This style of specifying terms and bindings is heavily
  inspired by the syntax of the Ott-tool \cite{ott-jfp}.

  However, we will not be able to cope with all specifications that are
  allowed by Ott. One reason is that Ott lets the user specify ``empty'' 
  types like

  \begin{center}
  @{text "t ::= t t | \<lambda>x. t"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  where no clause for variables is given. Arguably, such specifications make
  some sense in the context of Coq's type theory (which Ott supports), but not
  at all in a HOL-based environment where every datatype must have a non-empty
  set-theoretic model \cite{Berghofer99}.

  Another reason is that we establish the reasoning infrastructure
  for $\alpha$-\emph{equated} terms. In contrast, Ott produces  a reasoning 
  infrastructure in Isabelle/HOL for
  \emph{non}-$\alpha$-equated, or ``raw'', terms. While our $\alpha$-equated terms
  and the raw terms produced by Ott use names for bound variables,
  there is a key difference: working with $\alpha$-equated terms means, for example,  
  that the two type-schemes

  \begin{center}
  @{text "\<forall>{x}. x \<rightarrow> y  = \<forall>{x, z}. x \<rightarrow> y"} 
  \end{center}
  
  \noindent
  are not just $\alpha$-equal, but actually \emph{equal}! As a result, we can
  only support specifications that make sense on the level of $\alpha$-equated
  terms (offending specifications, which for example bind a variable according
  to a variable bound somewhere else, are not excluded by Ott, but we have
  to).  

  Our insistence on reasoning with $\alpha$-equated terms comes from the
  wealth of experience we gained with the older version of Nominal Isabelle:
  for non-trivial properties, reasoning with $\alpha$-equated terms is much
  easier than reasoning with raw terms. The fundamental reason for this is
  that the HOL-logic underlying Nominal Isabelle allows us to replace
  ``equals-by-equals''. In contrast, replacing
  ``$\alpha$-equals-by-$\alpha$-equals'' in a representation based on raw terms
  requires a lot of extra reasoning work.

  Although in informal settings a reasoning infrastructure for $\alpha$-equated
  terms is nearly always taken for granted, establishing it automatically in
  the Isabelle/HOL theorem prover is a rather non-trivial task. For every
  specification we will need to construct a type containing as elements the
  $\alpha$-equated terms. To do so, we use the standard HOL-technique of defining
  a new type by identifying a non-empty subset of an existing type.  The
  construction we perform in Isabelle/HOL can be illustrated by the following picture:

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tikzpicture}
  %\draw[step=2mm] (-4,-1) grid (4,1);
  
  \draw[very thick] (0.7,0.4) circle (4.25mm);
  \draw[rounded corners=1mm, very thick] ( 0.0,-0.8) rectangle ( 1.8, 0.9);
  \draw[rounded corners=1mm, very thick] (-1.95,0.85) rectangle (-2.85,-0.05);
  
  \draw (-2.0, 0.845) --  (0.7,0.845);
  \draw (-2.0,-0.045)  -- (0.7,-0.045);

  \draw ( 0.7, 0.4) node {\begin{tabular}{@ {}c@ {}}$\alpha$-\\[-1mm]clas.\end{tabular}};
  \draw (-2.4, 0.4) node {\begin{tabular}{@ {}c@ {}}$\alpha$-eq.\\[-1mm]terms\end{tabular}};
  \draw (1.8, 0.48) node[right=-0.1mm]
    {\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}}existing\\[-1mm] type\\ (sets of raw terms)\end{tabular}};
  \draw (0.9, -0.35) node {\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}}non-empty\\[-1mm]subset\end{tabular}};
  \draw (-3.25, 0.55) node {\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}}new\\[-1mm]type\end{tabular}};
  
  \draw[<->, very thick] (-1.8, 0.3) -- (-0.1,0.3);
  \draw (-0.95, 0.3) node[above=0mm] {isomorphism};

  \end{tikzpicture}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  We take as the starting point a definition of raw terms (defined as a
  datatype in Isabelle/HOL); then identify the $\alpha$-equivalence classes in
  the type of sets of raw terms according to our $\alpha$-equivalence relation,
  and finally define the new type as these $\alpha$-equivalence classes
  (non-emptiness is satisfied whenever the raw terms are definable as datatype
  in Isabelle/HOL and the property that our relation for $\alpha$-equivalence is
  indeed an equivalence relation).

  The fact that we obtain an isomorphism between the new type and the
  non-empty subset shows that the new type is a faithful representation of
  $\alpha$-equated terms. That is not the case for example for terms using the
  locally nameless representation of binders \cite{McKinnaPollack99}: in this
  representation there are ``junk'' terms that need to be excluded by
  reasoning about a well-formedness predicate.

  The problem with introducing a new type in Isabelle/HOL is that in order to
  be useful, a reasoning infrastructure needs to be ``lifted'' from the
  underlying subset to the new type. This is usually a tricky and arduous
  task. To ease it, we re-implemented in Isabelle/HOL the quotient package
  described by Homeier \cite{Homeier05} for the HOL4 system. This package
  allows us to lift definitions and theorems involving raw terms to
  definitions and theorems involving $\alpha$-equated terms. For example if we
  define the free-variable function over raw lambda-terms

  \begin{center}
  @{text "fv(x) = {x}"}\hspace{10mm}
  @{text "fv(t\<^isub>1 t\<^isub>2) = fv(t\<^isub>1) \<union> fv(t\<^isub>2)"}\\[1mm]
  @{text "fv(\<lambda>x.t) = fv(t) - {x}"}
  \end{center}
  
  \noindent
  then with the help of the quotient package we can obtain a function @{text "fv\<^sup>\<alpha>"}
  operating on quotients, or $\alpha$-equivalence classes of lambda-terms. This
  lifted function is characterised by the equations

  \begin{center}
  @{text "fv\<^sup>\<alpha>(x) = {x}"}\hspace{10mm}
  @{text "fv\<^sup>\<alpha>(t\<^isub>1 t\<^isub>2) = fv\<^sup>\<alpha>(t\<^isub>1) \<union> fv\<^sup>\<alpha>(t\<^isub>2)"}\\[1mm]
  @{text "fv\<^sup>\<alpha>(\<lambda>x.t) = fv\<^sup>\<alpha>(t) - {x}"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  (Note that this means also the term-constructors for variables, applications
  and lambda are lifted to the quotient level.)  This construction, of course,
  only works if $\alpha$-equivalence is indeed an equivalence relation, and the
  ``raw'' definitions and theorems are respectful w.r.t.~$\alpha$-equivalence.
  For example, we will not be able to lift a bound-variable function. Although
  this function can be defined for raw terms, it does not respect
  $\alpha$-equivalence and therefore cannot be lifted. To sum up, every lifting
  of theorems to the quotient level needs proofs of some respectfulness
  properties (see \cite{Homeier05}). In the paper we show that we are able to
  automate these proofs and as a result can automatically establish a reasoning 
  infrastructure for $\alpha$-equated terms.

  The examples we have in mind where our reasoning infrastructure will be
  helpful includes the term language of System @{text "F\<^isub>C"}, also
  known as Core-Haskell (see Figure~\ref{corehas}). This term language
  involves patterns that have lists of type-, coercion- and term-variables,
  all of which are bound in @{text "\<CASE>"}-expressions. One
  feature is that we do not know in advance how many variables need to
  be bound. Another is that each bound variable comes with a kind or type
  annotation. Representing such binders with single binders and reasoning
  about them in a theorem prover would be a major pain.  \medskip

  \noindent
  {\bf Contributions:}  We provide three new definitions for when terms
  involving general binders are $\alpha$-equivalent. These definitions are
  inspired by earlier work of Pitts \cite{Pitts04}. By means of automatic
  proofs, we establish a reasoning infrastructure for $\alpha$-equated
  terms, including properties about support, freshness and equality
  conditions for $\alpha$-equated terms. We are also able to derive strong 
  induction principles that have the variable convention already built in.
  The method behind our specification of general binders is taken 
  from the Ott-tool, but we introduce crucial restrictions, and also extensions, so 
  that our specifications make sense for reasoning about $\alpha$-equated terms. 


  \begin{figure}
  \begin{boxedminipage}{\linewidth}
  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{r@ {\hspace{1mm}}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l}
  \multicolumn{3}{@ {}l}{Type Kinds}\\
  @{text "\<kappa>"} & @{text "::="} & @{text "\<star> | \<kappa>\<^isub>1 \<rightarrow> \<kappa>\<^isub>2"}\smallskip\\
  \multicolumn{3}{@ {}l}{Coercion Kinds}\\
  @{text "\<iota>"} & @{text "::="} & @{text "\<sigma>\<^isub>1 \<sim> \<sigma>\<^isub>2"}\smallskip\\
  \multicolumn{3}{@ {}l}{Types}\\
  @{text "\<sigma>"} & @{text "::="} & @{text "a | T | \<sigma>\<^isub>1 \<sigma>\<^isub>2 | S\<^isub>n"}$\;\overline{@{text "\<sigma>"}}$@{text "\<^sup>n"} 
  @{text "| \<forall>a:\<kappa>. \<sigma> | \<iota> \<Rightarrow> \<sigma>"}\smallskip\\
  \multicolumn{3}{@ {}l}{Coercion Types}\\
  @{text "\<gamma>"} & @{text "::="} & @{text "c | C | \<gamma>\<^isub>1 \<gamma>\<^isub>2 | S\<^isub>n"}$\;\overline{@{text "\<gamma>"}}$@{text "\<^sup>n"}
  @{text "| \<forall>c:\<iota>. \<gamma> | \<iota> \<Rightarrow> \<gamma> "}\\
  & @{text "|"} & @{text "refl \<sigma> | sym \<gamma> | \<gamma>\<^isub>1 \<circ> \<gamma>\<^isub>2 | \<gamma> @ \<sigma> | left \<gamma> | right \<gamma>"}\\
  & @{text "|"} & @{text "\<gamma>\<^isub>1 \<sim> \<gamma>\<^isub>2 | rightc \<gamma> | leftc \<gamma> | \<gamma>\<^isub>1 \<triangleright> \<gamma>\<^isub>2"}\smallskip\\
  \multicolumn{3}{@ {}l}{Terms}\\
  @{text "e"} & @{text "::="} & @{text "x | K | \<Lambda>a:\<kappa>. e | \<Lambda>c:\<iota>. e | e \<sigma> | e \<gamma>"}\\
  & @{text "|"} & @{text "\<lambda>x:\<sigma>. e | e\<^isub>1 e\<^isub>2 | \<LET> x:\<sigma> = e\<^isub>1 \<IN> e\<^isub>2"}\\
  & @{text "|"} & @{text "\<CASE> e\<^isub>1 \<OF>"}$\;\overline{@{text "p \<rightarrow> e\<^isub>2"}}$ @{text "| e \<triangleright> \<gamma>"}\smallskip\\
  \multicolumn{3}{@ {}l}{Patterns}\\
  @{text "p"} & @{text "::="} & @{text "K"}$\;\overline{@{text "a:\<kappa>"}}\;\overline{@{text "c:\<iota>"}}\;\overline{@{text "x:\<sigma>"}}$\smallskip\\
  \multicolumn{3}{@ {}l}{Constants}\\
  & @{text C} & coercion constants\\
  & @{text T} & value type constructors\\
  & @{text "S\<^isub>n"} & n-ary type functions (which need to be fully applied)\\
  & @{text K} & data constructors\smallskip\\
  \multicolumn{3}{@ {}l}{Variables}\\
  & @{text a} & type variables\\
  & @{text c} & coercion variables\\
  & @{text x} & term variables\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}
  \end{boxedminipage}
  \caption{The System @{text "F\<^isub>C"}
  \cite{CoreHaskell}, also often referred to as \emph{Core-Haskell}. In this
  version of @{text "F\<^isub>C"} we made a modification by separating the
  grammars for type kinds and coercion kinds, as well as for types and coercion
  types. For this paper the interesting term-constructor is @{text "\<CASE>"},
  which binds multiple type-, coercion- and term-variables.\label{corehas}}
  \end{figure}
*}

section {* A Short Review of the Nominal Logic Work *}

text {*
  At its core, Nominal Isabelle is an adaption of the nominal logic work by
  Pitts \cite{Pitts03}. This adaptation for Isabelle/HOL is described in
  \cite{HuffmanUrban10} (including proofs). We shall briefly review this work
  to aid the description of what follows. 

  Two central notions in the nominal logic work are sorted atoms and
  sort-respecting permutations of atoms. We will use the letters @{text "a,
  b, c, \<dots>"} to stand for atoms and @{text "p, q, \<dots>"} to stand for
  permutations. The purpose of atoms is to represent variables, be they bound or free. 
  The sorts of atoms can be used to represent different kinds of
  variables, such as the term-, coercion- and type-variables in Core-Haskell.
  It is assumed that there is an infinite supply of atoms for each
  sort. However, in the interest of brevity, we shall restrict ourselves 
  in what follows to only one sort of atoms.

  Permutations are bijective functions from atoms to atoms that are 
  the identity everywhere except on a finite number of atoms. There is a 
  two-place permutation operation written
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "_ \<bullet> _  ::  perm \<Rightarrow> \<beta> \<Rightarrow> \<beta>"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent 
  in which the generic type @{text "\<beta>"} stands for the type of the object 
  over which the permutation 
  acts. In Nominal Isabelle, the identity permutation is written as @{term "0::perm"},
  the composition of two permutations @{term p} and @{term q} as \mbox{@{term "p + q"}}, 
  and the inverse permutation of @{term p} as @{text "- p"}. The permutation
  operation is defined by induction over the type-hierarchy \cite{HuffmanUrban10};
  for example permutations acting on products, lists, sets, functions and booleans is
  given by:
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{permute}
  \mbox{\begin{tabular}{@ {}cc@ {}}
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}}
  @{thm permute_prod.simps[no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]}\\[2mm]
  @{thm permute_list.simps(1)[no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]}\\
  @{thm permute_list.simps(2)[no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]}\\
  \end{tabular} &
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}}
  @{thm permute_set_eq[no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]}\\
  @{text "p \<bullet> f \<equiv> \<lambda>x. p \<bullet> (f (- p \<bullet> x))"}\\
  @{thm permute_bool_def[no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]}\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{tabular}}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  Concrete permutations in Nominal Isabelle are built up from swappings, 
  written as \mbox{@{text "(a b)"}}, which are permutations that behave 
  as follows:
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "(a b) = \<lambda>c. if a = c then b else if b = c then a else c"}
  \end{center}

  The most original aspect of the nominal logic work of Pitts is a general
  definition for the notion of the ``set of free variables of an object @{text
  "x"}''.  This notion, written @{term "supp x"}, is general in the sense that
  it applies not only to lambda-terms ($\alpha$-equated or not), but also to lists,
  products, sets and even functions. The definition depends only on the
  permutation operation and on the notion of equality defined for the type of
  @{text x}, namely:
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{suppdef}
  @{thm supp_def[no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  There is also the derived notion for when an atom @{text a} is \emph{fresh}
  for an @{text x}, defined as
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{thm fresh_def[no_vars]}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  We use for sets of atoms the abbreviation 
  @{thm (lhs) fresh_star_def[no_vars]}, defined as 
  @{thm (rhs) fresh_star_def[no_vars]}.
  A striking consequence of these definitions is that we can prove
  without knowing anything about the structure of @{term x} that
  swapping two fresh atoms, say @{text a} and @{text b}, leaves 
  @{text x} unchanged:

  \begin{property}\label{swapfreshfresh}
  @{thm[mode=IfThen] swap_fresh_fresh[no_vars]}
  \end{property}

  While often the support of an object can be relatively easily 
  described, for example for atoms, products, lists, function applications, 
  booleans and permutations as follows
  %
  \begin{eqnarray}
  @{term "supp a"} & = & @{term "{a}"}\\
  @{term "supp (x, y)"} & = & @{term "supp x \<union> supp y"}\\
  @{term "supp []"} & = & @{term "{}"}\\
  @{term "supp (x#xs)"} & = & @{term "supp x \<union> supp xs"}\\
  @{text "supp (f x)"} & @{text "\<subseteq>"} & @{term "supp f \<union> supp x"}\label{suppfun}\\
  @{term "supp b"} & = & @{term "{}"}\\
  @{term "supp p"} & = & @{term "{a. p \<bullet> a \<noteq> a}"}
  \end{eqnarray}
  
  \noindent 
  in some cases it can be difficult to characterise the support precisely, and
  only an approximation can be established (see \eqref{suppfun} above). Reasoning about
  such approximations can be simplified with the notion \emph{supports}, defined 
  as follows:

  \begin{defn}
  A set @{text S} \emph{supports} @{text x} if for all atoms @{text a} and @{text b}
  not in @{text S} we have @{term "(a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> x = x"}.
  \end{defn}

  \noindent
  The main point of @{text supports} is that we can establish the following 
  two properties.

  \begin{property}\label{supportsprop}
  Given a set @{text "as"} of atoms.
  {\it (i)} @{thm[mode=IfThen] supp_is_subset[where S="as", no_vars]}
  {\it (ii)} @{thm supp_supports[no_vars]}.
  \end{property}

  Another important notion in the nominal logic work is \emph{equivariance}.
  For a function @{text f}, say of type @{text "\<alpha> \<Rightarrow> \<beta>"}, to be equivariant 
  it is required that every permutation leaves @{text f} unchanged, that is
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{equivariancedef}
  @{term "\<forall>p. p \<bullet> f = f"}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent or equivalently that a permutation applied to the application
  @{text "f x"} can be moved to the argument @{text x}. That means for equivariant
  functions @{text f}, we have for all permutations @{text p}:
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{equivariance}
  @{text "p \<bullet> f = f"} \;\;\;\textit{if and only if}\;\;\;
  @{text "p \<bullet> (f x) = f (p \<bullet> x)"}
  \end{equation}
 
  \noindent
  From property \eqref{equivariancedef} and the definition of @{text supp}, we 
  can easily deduce that equivariant functions have empty support. There is
  also a similar notion for equivariant relations, say @{text R}, namely the property
  that
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "x R y"} \;\;\textit{implies}\;\; @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R (p \<bullet> y)"}
  \end{center}

  Finally, the nominal logic work provides us with general means for renaming 
  binders. While in the older version of Nominal Isabelle, we used extensively 
  Property~\ref{swapfreshfresh} to rename single binders, this property 
  proved too unwieldy for dealing with multiple binders. For such binders the 
  following generalisations turned out to be easier to use.

  \begin{property}\label{supppermeq}
  @{thm[mode=IfThen] supp_perm_eq[no_vars]}
  \end{property}

  \begin{property}\label{avoiding}
  For a finite set @{text as} and a finitely supported @{text x} with
  @{term "as \<sharp>* x"} and also a finitely supported @{text c}, there
  exists a permutation @{text p} such that @{term "(p \<bullet> as) \<sharp>* c"} and
  @{term "supp x \<sharp>* p"}.
  \end{property}

  \noindent
  The idea behind the second property is that given a finite set @{text as}
  of binders (being bound, or fresh, in @{text x} is ensured by the
  assumption @{term "as \<sharp>* x"}), then there exists a permutation @{text p} such that
  the renamed binders @{term "p \<bullet> as"} avoid @{text c} (which can be arbitrarily chosen
  as long as it is finitely supported) and also @{text "p"} does not affect anything
  in the support of @{text x} (that is @{term "supp x \<sharp>* p"}). The last 
  fact and Property~\ref{supppermeq} allow us to ``rename'' just the binders 
  @{text as} in @{text x}, because @{term "p \<bullet> x = x"}.

  Most properties given in this section are described in detail in \cite{HuffmanUrban10}
  and of course all are formalised in Isabelle/HOL. In the next sections we will make 
  extensive use of these properties in order to define $\alpha$-equivalence in 
  the presence of multiple binders.
*}


section {* General Bindings\label{sec:binders} *}

text {*
  In Nominal Isabelle, the user is expected to write down a specification of a
  term-calculus and then a reasoning infrastructure is automatically derived
  from this specification (remember that Nominal Isabelle is a definitional
  extension of Isabelle/HOL, which does not introduce any new axioms).

  In order to keep our work with deriving the reasoning infrastructure
  manageable, we will wherever possible state definitions and perform proofs
  on the ``user-level'' of Isabelle/HOL, as opposed to write custom ML-code that
  generates them anew for each specification. To that end, we will consider
  first pairs @{text "(as, x)"} of type @{text "(atom set) \<times> \<beta>"}.  These pairs
  are intended to represent the abstraction, or binding, of the set of atoms @{text
  "as"} in the body @{text "x"}.

  The first question we have to answer is when two pairs @{text "(as, x)"} and
  @{text "(bs, y)"} are $\alpha$-equivalent? (For the moment we are interested in
  the notion of $\alpha$-equivalence that is \emph{not} preserved by adding
  vacuous binders.) To answer this question, we identify four conditions: {\it (i)}
  given a free-atom function @{text "fa"} of type \mbox{@{text "\<beta> \<Rightarrow> atom
  set"}}, then @{text x} and @{text y} need to have the same set of free
  atoms; moreover there must be a permutation @{text p} such that {\it
  (ii)} @{text p} leaves the free atoms of @{text x} and @{text y} unchanged, but
  {\it (iii)} ``moves'' their bound names so that we obtain modulo a relation,
  say \mbox{@{text "_ R _"}}, two equivalent terms. We also require that {\it (iv)}
  @{text p} makes the sets of abstracted atoms @{text as} and @{text bs} equal. The
  requirements {\it (i)} to {\it (iv)} can be stated formally as follows:
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{alphaset}
  \begin{array}{@ {\hspace{10mm}}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l@ {\hspace{4mm}}r}
  \multicolumn{3}{l}{@{term "(as, x) \<approx>gen R fa p (bs, y)"}\hspace{2mm}@{text "\<equiv>"}}\\[1mm]
              & @{term "fa(x) - as = fa(y) - bs"} & \mbox{\it (i)}\\
  @{text "\<and>"} & @{term "(fa(x) - as) \<sharp>* p"} & \mbox{\it (ii)}\\
  @{text "\<and>"} & @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"} & \mbox{\it (iii)}\\
  @{text "\<and>"} & @{term "(p \<bullet> as) = bs"} & \mbox{\it (iv)}\\ 
  \end{array}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  Note that this relation depends on the permutation @{text
  "p"}; $\alpha$-equivalence between two pairs is then the relation where we
  existentially quantify over this @{text "p"}. Also note that the relation is
  dependent on a free-atom function @{text "fa"} and a relation @{text
  "R"}. The reason for this extra generality is that we will use
  $\approx_{\,\textit{set}}$ for both ``raw'' terms and $\alpha$-equated terms. In
  the latter case, @{text R} will be replaced by equality @{text "="} and we
  will prove that @{text "fa"} is equal to @{text "supp"}.

  The definition in \eqref{alphaset} does not make any distinction between the
  order of abstracted atoms. If we want this, then we can define $\alpha$-equivalence 
  for pairs of the form \mbox{@{text "(as, x)"}} with type @{text "(atom list) \<times> \<beta>"} 
  as follows
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{alphalist}
  \begin{array}{@ {\hspace{10mm}}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l@ {\hspace{4mm}}r}
  \multicolumn{2}{l}{@{term "(as, x) \<approx>lst R fa p (bs, y)"}\hspace{2mm}@{text "\<equiv>"}}\\[1mm]
             & @{term "fa(x) - (set as) = fa(y) - (set bs)"} & \mbox{\it (i)}\\
  \wedge     & @{term "(fa(x) - set as) \<sharp>* p"} & \mbox{\it (ii)}\\
  \wedge     & @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"} & \mbox{\it (iii)}\\
  \wedge     & @{term "(p \<bullet> as) = bs"} & \mbox{\it (iv)}\\ 
  \end{array}
  \end{equation}
  
  \noindent
  where @{term set} is the function that coerces a list of atoms into a set of atoms.
  Now the last clause ensures that the order of the binders matters (since @{text as}
  and @{text bs} are lists of atoms).

  If we do not want to make any difference between the order of binders \emph{and}
  also allow vacuous binders, then we keep sets of binders, but drop the fourth 
  condition in \eqref{alphaset}:
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{alphares}
  \begin{array}{@ {\hspace{10mm}}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l@ {\hspace{4mm}}r}
  \multicolumn{2}{l}{@{term "(as, x) \<approx>res R fa p (bs, y)"}\hspace{2mm}@{text "\<equiv>"}}\\[1mm]
             & @{term "fa(x) - as = fa(y) - bs"} & \mbox{\it (i)}\\
  \wedge     & @{term "(fa(x) - as) \<sharp>* p"} & \mbox{\it (ii)}\\
  \wedge     & @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"} & \mbox{\it (iii)}\\
  \end{array}
  \end{equation}

  It might be useful to consider first some examples about how these definitions
  of $\alpha$-equivalence pan out in practice.  For this consider the case of
  abstracting a set of atoms over types (as in type-schemes). We set
  @{text R} to be the usual equality @{text "="} and for @{text "fa(T)"} we
  define

  \begin{center}
  @{text "fa(x) = {x}"}  \hspace{5mm} @{text "fa(T\<^isub>1 \<rightarrow> T\<^isub>2) = fa(T\<^isub>1) \<union> fa(T\<^isub>2)"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  Now recall the examples shown in \eqref{ex1}, \eqref{ex2} and
  \eqref{ex3}. It can be easily checked that @{text "({x, y}, x \<rightarrow> y)"} and
  @{text "({y, x}, y \<rightarrow> x)"} are $\alpha$-equivalent according to
  $\approx_{\,\textit{set}}$ and $\approx_{\,\textit{res}}$ by taking @{text p} to
  be the swapping @{term "(x \<rightleftharpoons> y)"}. In case of @{text "x \<noteq> y"}, then @{text
  "([x, y], x \<rightarrow> y)"} $\not\approx_{\,\textit{list}}$ @{text "([y, x], x \<rightarrow> y)"}
  since there is no permutation that makes the lists @{text "[x, y]"} and
  @{text "[y, x]"} equal, and also leaves the type \mbox{@{text "x \<rightarrow> y"}}
  unchanged. Another example is @{text "({x}, x)"} $\approx_{\,\textit{res}}$
  @{text "({x, y}, x)"} which holds by taking @{text p} to be the identity
  permutation.  However, if @{text "x \<noteq> y"}, then @{text "({x}, x)"}
  $\not\approx_{\,\textit{set}}$ @{text "({x, y}, x)"} since there is no
  permutation that makes the sets @{text "{x}"} and @{text "{x, y}"} equal
  (similarly for $\approx_{\,\textit{list}}$).  It can also relatively easily be
  shown that all three notions of $\alpha$-equivalence coincide, if we only
  abstract a single atom.

  In the rest of this section we are going to introduce three abstraction 
  types. For this we define 
  %
  \begin{equation}
  @{term "abs_set (as, x) (bs, x) \<equiv> \<exists>p. alpha_gen (as, x) equal supp p (bs, x)"}
  \end{equation}
  
  \noindent
  (similarly for $\approx_{\,\textit{abs\_res}}$ 
  and $\approx_{\,\textit{abs\_list}}$). We can show that these relations are equivalence 
  relations and equivariant.

  \begin{lemma}\label{alphaeq} 
  The relations $\approx_{\,\textit{abs\_set}}$, $\approx_{\,\textit{abs\_list}}$
  and $\approx_{\,\textit{abs\_res}}$ are equivalence relations, and if @{term
  "abs_set (as, x) (bs, y)"} then also @{term "abs_set (p \<bullet> as, p \<bullet> x) (p \<bullet>
  bs, p \<bullet> y)"} (similarly for the other two relations).
  \end{lemma}

  \begin{proof}
  Reflexivity is by taking @{text "p"} to be @{text "0"}. For symmetry we have
  a permutation @{text p} and for the proof obligation take @{term "-p"}. In case 
  of transitivity, we have two permutations @{text p} and @{text q}, and for the
  proof obligation use @{text "q + p"}. All conditions are then by simple
  calculations. 
  \end{proof}

  \noindent
  This lemma allows us to use our quotient package for introducing 
  new types @{text "\<beta> abs_set"}, @{text "\<beta> abs_res"} and @{text "\<beta> abs_list"}
  representing $\alpha$-equivalence classes of pairs of type 
  @{text "(atom set) \<times> \<beta>"} (in the first two cases) and of type @{text "(atom list) \<times> \<beta>"}
  (in the third case). 
  The elements in these types will be, respectively, written as:

  \begin{center}
  @{term "Abs as x"} \hspace{5mm} 
  @{term "Abs_res as x"} \hspace{5mm}
  @{term "Abs_lst as x"} 
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  indicating that a set (or list) of atoms @{text as} is abstracted in @{text x}. We will
  call the types \emph{abstraction types} and their elements
  \emph{abstractions}. The important property we need to derive is the support of 
  abstractions, namely:

  \begin{thm}[Support of Abstractions]\label{suppabs} 
  Assuming @{text x} has finite support, then\\[-6mm] 
  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{l@ {\hspace{2mm}}c@ {\hspace{2mm}}l}
  @{thm (lhs) supp_abs(1)[no_vars]} & $=$ & @{thm (rhs) supp_abs(1)[no_vars]}\\
  @{thm (lhs) supp_abs(2)[no_vars]} & $=$ & @{thm (rhs) supp_abs(2)[no_vars]}\\
  @{thm (lhs) supp_abs(3)[where bs="as", no_vars]} & $=$ & @{thm (rhs) supp_abs(3)[where bs="as", no_vars]}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}
  \end{thm}

  \noindent
  Below we will show the first equation. The others 
  follow by similar arguments. By definition of the abstraction type @{text "abs_set"} 
  we have 
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{abseqiff}
  @{thm (lhs) abs_eq_iff(1)[where bs="as" and cs="bs", no_vars]} \;\;\text{if and only if}\;\; 
  @{thm (rhs) abs_eq_iff(1)[where bs="as" and cs="bs", no_vars]}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  and also
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{absperm}
  @{thm permute_Abs[no_vars]}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  The second fact derives from the definition of permutations acting on pairs 
  \eqref{permute} and $\alpha$-equivalence being equivariant 
  (see Lemma~\ref{alphaeq}). With these two facts at our disposal, we can show 
  the following lemma about swapping two atoms in an abstraction.
  
  \begin{lemma}
  @{thm[mode=IfThen] abs_swap1(1)[where bs="as", no_vars]}
  \end{lemma}

  \begin{proof}
  This lemma is straightforward using \eqref{abseqiff} and observing that
  the assumptions give us @{term "(a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> (supp x - as) = (supp x - as)"}.
  Moreover @{text supp} and set difference are equivariant (see \cite{HuffmanUrban10}).
  \end{proof}

  \noindent
  Assuming that @{text "x"} has finite support, this lemma together 
  with \eqref{absperm} allows us to show
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{halfone}
  @{thm abs_supports(1)[no_vars]}
  \end{equation}
  
  \noindent
  which by Property~\ref{supportsprop} gives us ``one half'' of
  Theorem~\ref{suppabs}. The ``other half'' is a bit more involved. To establish 
  it, we use a trick from \cite{Pitts04} and first define an auxiliary 
  function @{text aux}, taking an abstraction as argument:
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{thm supp_gen.simps[THEN eq_reflection, no_vars]}
  \end{center}
  
  \noindent
  Using the second equation in \eqref{equivariance}, we can show that 
  @{text "aux"} is equivariant (since @{term "p \<bullet> (supp x - as) =
  (supp (p \<bullet> x)) - (p \<bullet> as)"}) and therefore has empty support. 
  This in turn means
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{term "supp (supp_gen (Abs as x)) \<subseteq> supp (Abs as x)"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  using \eqref{suppfun}. Assuming @{term "supp x - as"} is a finite set,
  we further obtain
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{halftwo}
  @{thm (concl) supp_abs_subset1(1)[no_vars]}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  since for finite sets of atoms, @{text "bs"}, we have 
  @{thm (concl) supp_finite_atom_set[where S="bs", no_vars]}.
  Finally, taking \eqref{halfone} and \eqref{halftwo} together establishes 
  Theorem~\ref{suppabs}. 

  The method of first considering abstractions of the
  form @{term "Abs as x"} etc is motivated by the fact that 
  we can conveniently establish  at the Isabelle/HOL level
  properties about them.  It would be
  laborious to write custom ML-code that derives automatically such properties 
  for every term-constructor that binds some atoms. Also the generality of
  the definitions for $\alpha$-equivalence will help us in the next section.
*}

section {* Specifying General Bindings\label{sec:spec} *}

text {*
  Our choice of syntax for specifications is influenced by the existing
  datatype package of Isabelle/HOL \cite{Berghofer99} and by the syntax of the
  Ott-tool \cite{ott-jfp}. For us a specification of a term-calculus is a
  collection of (possibly mutual recursive) type declarations, say @{text
  "ty\<AL>\<^isub>1, \<dots>, ty\<AL>\<^isub>n"}, and an associated collection of
  binding functions, say @{text "bn\<AL>\<^isub>1, \<dots>, bn\<AL>\<^isub>m"}. The
  syntax in Nominal Isabelle for such specifications is roughly as follows:
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{scheme}
  \mbox{\begin{tabular}{@ {\hspace{-5mm}}p{1.8cm}l}
  type \mbox{declaration part} &
  $\begin{cases}
  \mbox{\begin{tabular}{l}
  \isacommand{nominal\_datatype} @{text "ty\<AL>\<^isub>1 = \<dots>"}\\
  \isacommand{and} @{text "ty\<AL>\<^isub>2 = \<dots>"}\\
  $\ldots$\\ 
  \isacommand{and} @{text "ty\<AL>\<^isub>n = \<dots>"}\\ 
  \end{tabular}}
  \end{cases}$\\
  binding \mbox{function part} &
  $\begin{cases}
  \mbox{\begin{tabular}{l}
  \isacommand{binder} @{text "bn\<AL>\<^isub>1"} \isacommand{and} \ldots \isacommand{and} @{text "bn\<AL>\<^isub>m"}\\
  \isacommand{where}\\
  $\ldots$\\
  \end{tabular}}
  \end{cases}$\\
  \end{tabular}}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  Every type declaration @{text ty}$^\alpha_{1..n}$ consists of a collection of 
  term-constructors, each of which comes with a list of labelled 
  types that stand for the types of the arguments of the term-constructor.
  For example a term-constructor @{text "C\<^sup>\<alpha>"} might be specified with

  \begin{center}
  @{text "C\<^sup>\<alpha> label\<^isub>1::ty"}$'_1$ @{text "\<dots> label\<^isub>l::ty"}$'_l\;\;$  @{text "binding_clauses"} 
  \end{center}
  
  \noindent
  whereby some of the @{text ty}$'_{1..l}$ (or their components) can be contained
  in the collection of @{text ty}$^\alpha_{1..n}$ declared in
  \eqref{scheme}. 
  In this case we will call the corresponding argument a
  \emph{recursive argument} of @{text "C\<^sup>\<alpha>"}. 
  %The types of such recursive 
  %arguments need to satisfy a  ``positivity''
  %restriction, which ensures that the type has a set-theoretic semantics 
  %\cite{Berghofer99}.  
  The labels
  annotated on the types are optional. Their purpose is to be used in the
  (possibly empty) list of \emph{binding clauses}, which indicate the binders
  and their scope in a term-constructor.  They come in three \emph{modes}:

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{l}
  \isacommand{bind}\; {\it binders}\; \isacommand{in}\; {\it bodies}\\
  \isacommand{bind\_set}\; {\it binders}\; \isacommand{in}\; {\it bodies}\\
  \isacommand{bind\_res}\; {\it binders}\; \isacommand{in}\; {\it bodies}\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  The first mode is for binding lists of atoms (the order of binders matters);
  the second is for sets of binders (the order does not matter, but the
  cardinality does) and the last is for sets of binders (with vacuous binders
  preserving $\alpha$-equivalence). As indicated, the labels in the ``\isacommand{in}-part'' of a binding
  clause will be called \emph{bodies}; the
  ``\isacommand{bind}-part'' will be called \emph{binders}. In contrast to
  Ott, we allow multiple labels in binders and bodies. For example we allow
  binding clauses of the form:

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}ll@ {}}
  @{text "Foo\<^isub>1 x::name y::name t::trm s::trm"} &  
      \isacommand{bind} @{text "x y"} \isacommand{in} @{text "t s"}\\
  @{text "Foo\<^isub>2 x::name y::name t::trm s::trm"} &  
      \isacommand{bind} @{text "x y"} \isacommand{in} @{text "t"}, 
      \isacommand{bind} @{text "x y"} \isacommand{in} @{text "s"}\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  Similarly for the other binding modes. 
  %Interestingly, in case of \isacommand{bind\_set}
  %and \isacommand{bind\_res} the binding clauses above will make a difference to the semantics
  %of the specifications (the corresponding $\alpha$-equivalence will differ). We will 
  %show this later with an example.
  
  There are also some restrictions we need to impose on our binding clauses in comparison to
  the ones of Ott. The
  main idea behind these restrictions is that we obtain a sensible notion of
  $\alpha$-equivalence where it is ensured that within a given scope an 
  atom occurrence cannot be both bound and free at the same time.  The first
  restriction is that a body can only occur in
  \emph{one} binding clause of a term constructor (this ensures that the bound
  atoms of a body cannot be free at the same time by specifying an
  alternative binder for the same body). For binders we distinguish between
  \emph{shallow} and \emph{deep} binders.  Shallow binders are just
  labels. The restriction we need to impose on them is that in case of
  \isacommand{bind\_set} and \isacommand{bind\_res} the labels must either
  refer to atom types or to sets of atom types; in case of \isacommand{bind}
  the labels must refer to atom types or lists of atom types. Two examples for
  the use of shallow binders are the specification of lambda-terms, where a
  single name is bound, and type-schemes, where a finite set of names is
  bound:


  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}cc@ {}}
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {\hspace{-1mm}}}
  \isacommand{nominal\_datatype} @{text lam} $=$\\
  \hspace{5mm}\phantom{$\mid$}~@{text "Var name"}\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{text "App lam lam"}\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{text "Lam x::name t::lam"}\\
  \hspace{21mm}\isacommand{bind} @{text x} \isacommand{in} @{text t}\\
  \end{tabular} &
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}}
  \isacommand{nominal\_datatype}~@{text ty} $=$\\
  \hspace{5mm}\phantom{$\mid$}~@{text "TVar name"}\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{text "TFun ty ty"}\\
  \isacommand{and}~@{text "tsc = All xs::(name fset) T::ty"}\\
  \hspace{24mm}\isacommand{bind\_res} @{text xs} \isacommand{in} @{text T}\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  In these specifications @{text "name"} refers to an atom type, and @{text
  "fset"} to the type of finite sets.
  Note that for @{text lam} it does not matter which binding mode we use. The
  reason is that we bind only a single @{text name}. However, having
  \isacommand{bind\_set} or \isacommand{bind} in the second case makes a
  difference to the semantics of the specification (which we will define in the next section).


  A \emph{deep} binder uses an auxiliary binding function that ``picks'' out
  the atoms in one argument of the term-constructor, which can be bound in
  other arguments and also in the same argument (we will call such binders
  \emph{recursive}, see below). The binding functions are
  expected to return either a set of atoms (for \isacommand{bind\_set} and
  \isacommand{bind\_res}) or a list of atoms (for \isacommand{bind}). They can
  be defined by recursion over the corresponding type; the equations
  must be given in the binding function part of the scheme shown in
  \eqref{scheme}. For example a term-calculus containing @{text "Let"}s with
  tuple patterns might be specified as:
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{letpat}
  \mbox{%
  \begin{tabular}{l}
  \isacommand{nominal\_datatype} @{text trm} =\\
  \hspace{5mm}\phantom{$\mid$}~@{term "Var name"}\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{term "App trm trm"}\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{text "Lam x::name t::trm"} 
     \;\;\isacommand{bind} @{text x} \isacommand{in} @{text t}\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{text "Let p::pat trm t::trm"} 
     \;\;\isacommand{bind} @{text "bn(p)"} \isacommand{in} @{text t}\\
  \isacommand{and} @{text pat} =\\
  \hspace{5mm}\phantom{$\mid$}~@{text PNil}\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{text "PVar name"}\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{text "PTup pat pat"}\\ 
  \isacommand{binder}~@{text "bn::pat \<Rightarrow> atom list"}\\
  \isacommand{where}~@{text "bn(PNil) = []"}\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{text "bn(PVar x) = [atom x]"}\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{text "bn(PTup p\<^isub>1 p\<^isub>2) = bn(p\<^isub>1) @ bn(p\<^isub>2)"}\smallskip\\ 
  \end{tabular}}
  \end{equation}
  
  \noindent
  In this specification the function @{text "bn"} determines which atoms of
  the pattern @{text p} are bound in the argument @{text "t"}. Note that in the
  second-last @{text bn}-clause the function @{text "atom"} coerces a name
  into the generic atom type of Nominal Isabelle \cite{HuffmanUrban10}. This
  allows us to treat binders of different atom type uniformly.

  As said above, for deep binders we allow binding clauses such as
  %
  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{ll}
  @{text "Bar p::pat t::trm"} &  
     \isacommand{bind} @{text "bn(p)"} \isacommand{in} @{text "p t"}\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  where the argument of the deep binder also occurs in the body. We call such
  binders \emph{recursive}.  To see the purpose of such recursive binders,
  compare ``plain'' @{text "Let"}s and @{text "Let_rec"}s in the following
  specification:
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{letrecs}
  \mbox{%
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}}
  \isacommand{nominal\_datatype}~@{text "trm ="}\\
  \hspace{5mm}\phantom{$\mid$}\ldots\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{text "Let as::assn t::trm"} 
     \;\;\isacommand{bind} @{text "bn(as)"} \isacommand{in} @{text t}\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{text "Let_rec as::assn t::trm"}
     \;\;\isacommand{bind} @{text "bn(as)"} \isacommand{in} @{text "as t"}\\
  \isacommand{and} @{text "ass"} =\\
  \hspace{5mm}\phantom{$\mid$}~@{text "ANil"}\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{text "ACons name trm assn"}\\
  \isacommand{binder} @{text "bn::assn \<Rightarrow> atom list"}\\
  \isacommand{where}~@{text "bn(ANil) = []"}\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{text "bn(ACons a t as) = [atom a] @ bn(as)"}\\
  \end{tabular}}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  The difference is that with @{text Let} we only want to bind the atoms @{text
  "bn(as)"} in the term @{text t}, but with @{text "Let_rec"} we also want to bind the atoms
  inside the assignment. This difference has consequences for the associated
  notions of free-atoms and $\alpha$-equivalence.
  
  To make sure that atoms bound by deep binders cannot be free at the
  same time, we cannot have more than one binding function for a deep binder. 
  Consequently we exclude specifications such as

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {\hspace{2mm}}l@ {}}
  @{text "Baz\<^isub>1 p::pat t::trm"} & 
     \isacommand{bind} @{text "bn\<^isub>1(p) bn\<^isub>2(p)"} \isacommand{in} @{text t}\\
  @{text "Baz\<^isub>2 p::pat t\<^isub>1::trm t\<^isub>2::trm"} & 
     \isacommand{bind} @{text "bn\<^isub>1(p)"} \isacommand{in} @{text "t\<^isub>1"},
     \isacommand{bind} @{text "bn\<^isub>2(p)"} \isacommand{in} @{text "t\<^isub>2"}\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  Otherwise it is possible that @{text "bn\<^isub>1"} and @{text "bn\<^isub>2"}  pick 
  out different atoms to become bound, respectively be free, in @{text "p"}.
  (Since the Ott-tool does not derive a reasoning infrastructure for 
  $\alpha$-equated terms, it can permit such specifications.)
  
  We also need to restrict the form of the binding functions in order 
  to ensure the @{text "bn"}-functions can be defined for $\alpha$-equated 
  terms. The main restriction is that we cannot return an atom in a binding function that is also
  bound in the corresponding term-constructor. That means in \eqref{letpat} 
  that the term-constructors @{text PVar} and @{text PTup} may
  not have a binding clause (all arguments are used to define @{text "bn"}).
  In contrast, in case of \eqref{letrecs} the term-constructor @{text ACons}
  may have a binding clause involving the argument @{text t} (the only one that
  is \emph{not} used in the definition of the binding function). This restriction
  is sufficient for having the binding function over $\alpha$-equated terms.

  In the version of
  Nominal Isabelle described here, we also adopted the restriction from the
  Ott-tool that binding functions can only return: the empty set or empty list
  (as in case @{text PNil}), a singleton set or singleton list containing an
  atom (case @{text PVar}), or unions of atom sets or appended atom lists
  (case @{text PTup}). This restriction will simplify some automatic definitions and proofs
  later on.
  
  In order to simplify our definitions of free atoms and $\alpha$-equivalence, 
  we shall assume specifications 
  of term-calculi are implicitly \emph{completed}. By this we mean that  
  for every argument of a term-constructor that is \emph{not} 
  already part of a binding clause given by the user, we add implicitly a special \emph{empty} binding
  clause, written \isacommand{bind}~@{term "{}"}~\isacommand{in}~@{text "labels"}. In case
  of the lambda-calculus, the completion produces

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {\hspace{-1mm}}}
  \isacommand{nominal\_datatype} @{text lam} =\\
  \hspace{5mm}\phantom{$\mid$}~@{text "Var x::name"}
    \;\;\isacommand{bind}~@{term "{}"}~\isacommand{in}~@{text "x"}\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{text "App t\<^isub>1::lam t\<^isub>2::lam"}
    \;\;\isacommand{bind}~@{term "{}"}~\isacommand{in}~@{text "t\<^isub>1 t\<^isub>2"}\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{text "Lam x::name t::lam"}
    \;\;\isacommand{bind}~@{text x} \isacommand{in} @{text t}\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent 
  The point of completion is that we can make definitions over the binding
  clauses and be sure to have captured all arguments of a term constructor. 
*}

section {* Alpha-Equivalence and Free Atoms\label{sec:alpha} *}

text {*
  Having dealt with all syntax matters, the problem now is how we can turn
  specifications into actual type definitions in Isabelle/HOL and then
  establish a reasoning infrastructure for them. As
  Pottier and Cheney pointed out \cite{Pottier06,Cheney05}, just 
  re-arranging the arguments of
  term-constructors so that binders and their bodies are next to each other will 
  result in inadequate representations in cases like @{text "Let x\<^isub>1 = t\<^isub>1\<dots>x\<^isub>n = t\<^isub>n in s"}. 
  Therefore we will first
  extract ``raw'' datatype definitions from the specification and then define 
  explicitly an $\alpha$-equivalence relation over them. We subsequently
  quotient the datatypes according to our $\alpha$-equivalence.


  The ``raw'' datatype definition can be obtained by stripping off the 
  binding clauses and the labels from the types. We also have to invent
  new names for the types @{text "ty\<^sup>\<alpha>"} and term-constructors @{text "C\<^sup>\<alpha>"}
  given by the user. In our implementation we just use the affix ``@{text "_raw"}''.
  But for the purpose of this paper, we use the superscript @{text "_\<^sup>\<alpha>"} to indicate 
  that a notion is defined over $\alpha$-equivalence classes and leave it out 
  for the corresponding notion defined on the ``raw'' level. So for example 
  we have
  
  \begin{center}
  @{text "ty\<^sup>\<alpha> \<mapsto> ty"} \hspace{2mm}and\hspace{2mm} @{text "C\<^sup>\<alpha> \<mapsto> C"}
  \end{center}
  
  \noindent
  where @{term ty} is the type used in the quotient construction for 
  @{text "ty\<^sup>\<alpha>"} and @{text "C"} is the term-constructor on the ``raw'' type @{text "ty"}. 

  The resulting datatype definition is legal in Isabelle/HOL provided the datatypes are 
  non-empty and the types in the constructors only occur in positive 
  position (see \cite{Berghofer99} for an in-depth description of the datatype package
  in Isabelle/HOL). We subsequently define each of the user-specified binding 
  functions @{term "bn"}$_{1..m}$ by recursion over the corresponding 
  raw datatype. We can also easily define permutation operations by 
  recursion so that for each term constructor @{text "C"} we have that
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{ceqvt}
  @{text "p \<bullet> (C z\<^isub>1 \<dots> z\<^isub>n) = C (p \<bullet> z\<^isub>1) \<dots> (p \<bullet> z\<^isub>n)"}
  \end{equation}

  The first non-trivial step we have to perform is the generation of
  free-atom functions from the specification. For the 
  \emph{raw} types @{text "ty"}$_{1..n}$ we define the free-atom functions
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{fvars}
  @{text "fa_ty\<^isub>1, \<dots>, fa_ty\<^isub>n"}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  by mutual recursion.
  We define these functions together with auxiliary free-atom functions for
  the binding functions. Given raw binding functions @{text "bn"}$_{1..m}$ 
  we define
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "fa_bn\<^isub>1, \<dots>, fa_bn\<^isub>m"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  The reason for this setup is that in a deep binder not all atoms have to be
  bound, as we saw in the example with ``plain'' @{text Let}s. We need therefore a function
  that calculates those free atoms in a deep binder.

  While the idea behind these free-atom functions is clear (they just
  collect all atoms that are not bound), because of our rather complicated
  binding mechanisms their definitions are somewhat involved.  Given
  a term-constructor @{text "C"} of type @{text ty} and some associated
  binding clauses @{text "bc\<^isub>1\<dots>bc\<^isub>k"}, the result of @{text
  "fa_ty (C z\<^isub>1 \<dots> z\<^isub>n)"} will be the union @{text
  "fa(bc\<^isub>1) \<union> \<dots> \<union> fa(bc\<^isub>k)"} where we will define below what @{text "fa"} for a binding
  clause means. We only show the details for the mode \isacommand{bind\_set} (the other modes are similar). 
  Suppose the binding clause @{text bc\<^isub>i} is of the form 
  %
  \begin{center}
  \mbox{\isacommand{bind\_set} @{text "b\<^isub>1\<dots>b\<^isub>p"} \isacommand{in} @{text "d\<^isub>1\<dots>d\<^isub>q"}}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  in which the body-labels @{text "d"}$_{1..q}$ refer to types @{text ty}$_{1..q}$,
  and the binders @{text b}$_{1..p}$
  either refer to labels of atom types (in case of shallow binders) or to binding 
  functions taking a single label as argument (in case of deep binders). Assuming 
  @{text "D"} stands for the set of free atoms of the bodies, @{text B} for the 
  set of binding atoms in the binders and @{text "B'"} for the set of free atoms in 
  non-recursive deep binders,
  then the free atoms of the binding clause @{text bc\<^isub>i} are
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{fadef}
  \mbox{@{text "fa(bc\<^isub>i) \<equiv> (D - B) \<union> B'"}}.
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  The set @{text D} is formally defined as
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "D \<equiv> fa_ty\<^isub>1 d\<^isub>1 \<union> ... \<union> fa_ty\<^isub>q d\<^isub>q"}
  \end{center} 

  \noindent
  where in case @{text "d\<^isub>i"} refers to one of the raw types @{text "ty"}$_{1..n}$ from the 
  specification, the function @{text "fa_ty\<^isub>i"} is the corresponding free-atom function 
  we are defining by recursion 
  (see \eqref{fvars}); otherwise we set @{text "fa_ty\<^isub>i d\<^isub>i = supp d\<^isub>i"}.
  
  In order to formally define the set @{text B} we use the following auxiliary @{text "bn"}-functions
  for atom types to which shallow binders may refer
  %
  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{r@ {\hspace{2mm}}c@ {\hspace{2mm}}l}
  @{text "bn_atom a"} & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{text "{atom a}"}\\
  @{text "bn_atom_set as"} & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{text "atoms as"}\\
  @{text "bn_atom_list as"} & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{text "atoms (set as)"}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent 
  Like the function @{text atom}, the function @{text "atoms"} coerces 
  a set of atoms to a set of the generic atom type. It is defined as 
  @{text "atoms as \<equiv> {atom a | a \<in> as}"}. 
  The set @{text B} is then formally defined as
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "B \<equiv> bn_ty\<^isub>1 b\<^isub>1 \<union> ... \<union> bn_ty\<^isub>p b\<^isub>p"}
  \end{center} 

  \noindent 
  where we use the auxiliary binding functions for shallow binders. 
  The set @{text "B'"} collects all free atoms in non-recursive deep
  binders. Let us assume these binders in @{text "bc\<^isub>i"} are
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "bn\<^isub>1 l\<^isub>1, \<dots>, bn\<^isub>r l\<^isub>r"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  with @{text "l"}$_{1..r}$ $\subseteq$ @{text "b"}$_{1..p}$ and none of the 
  @{text "l"}$_{1..r}$ being among the bodies @{text
  "d"}$_{1..q}$. The set @{text "B'"} is defined as
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "B' \<equiv> fa_bn\<^isub>1 l\<^isub>1 \<union> ... \<union> fa_bn\<^isub>r l\<^isub>r"}
  \end{center} 

  \noindent
  This completes the definition of the free-atom functions @{text "fa_ty"}$_{1..n}$.

  Note that for non-recursive deep binders, we have to add in \eqref{fadef}
  the set of atoms that are left unbound by the binding functions @{text
  "bn"}$_{1..m}$. We used for the definition of
  this set the functions @{text "fa_bn"}$_{1..m}$, which are also defined by mutual
  recursion. Assume the user specified a @{text bn}-clause of the form
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "bn (C z\<^isub>1 \<dots> z\<^isub>s) = rhs"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  where the @{text "z"}$_{1..s}$ are of types @{text "ty"}$_{1..s}$. For each of
  the arguments we calculate the free atoms as follows:
  %
  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{c@ {\hspace{2mm}}p{7cm}}
  $\bullet$ & @{term "fa_ty\<^isub>i z\<^isub>i"} provided @{text "z\<^isub>i"} does not occur in @{text "rhs"} 
  (that means nothing is bound in @{text "z\<^isub>i"} by the binding function),\\
  $\bullet$ & @{term "fa_bn\<^isub>i z\<^isub>i"} provided @{text "z\<^isub>i"} occurs in  @{text "rhs"}
  with the recursive call @{text "bn\<^isub>i z\<^isub>i"}, and\\
  $\bullet$ & @{term "{}"} provided @{text "z\<^isub>i"} occurs in  @{text "rhs"},
  but without a recursive call.
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  For defining @{text "fa_bn (C z\<^isub>1 \<dots> z\<^isub>n)"} we just union up all these sets.
 
  To see how these definitions work in practice, let us reconsider the
  term-constructors @{text "Let"} and @{text "Let_rec"} shown in
  \eqref{letrecs} together with the term-constructors for assignments @{text
  "ANil"} and @{text "ACons"}. Since there is a binding function defined for
  assignments, we have three free-atom functions, namely @{text
  "fa\<^bsub>trm\<^esub>"}, @{text "fa\<^bsub>assn\<^esub>"} and @{text
  "fa\<^bsub>bn\<^esub>"} as follows:
  %
  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {\hspace{1mm}}c@ {\hspace{1mm}}l@ {}}
  @{text "fa\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> (Let as t)"} & @{text "="} & @{text "(fa\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> t - set (bn as)) \<union> fa\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> as"}\\
  @{text "fa\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> (Let_rec as t)"} & @{text "="} & @{text "(fa\<^bsub>assn\<^esub> as \<union> fa\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> t) - set (bn as)"}\\[1mm]

  @{text "fa\<^bsub>assn\<^esub> (ANil)"} & @{text "="} & @{term "{}"}\\
  @{text "fa\<^bsub>assn\<^esub> (ACons a t as)"} & @{text "="} & @{text "(supp a) \<union> (fa\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> t) \<union> (fa\<^bsub>assn\<^esub> as)"}\\[1mm]

  @{text "fa\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> (ANil)"} & @{text "="} & @{term "{}"}\\
  @{text "fa\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> (ACons a t as)"} & @{text "="} & @{text "(fa\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> t) \<union> (fa\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> as)"}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  Recall that @{text ANil} and @{text "ACons"} have no
  binding clause in the specification. The corresponding free-atom
  function @{text "fa\<^bsub>assn\<^esub>"} therefore returns all free atoms
  occurring in an assignment (in case of @{text "ACons"}, they are given in
  terms of @{text supp}, @{text "fa\<^bsub>trm\<^esub>"} and @{text "fa\<^bsub>assn\<^esub>"}). 
  The binding only takes place in @{text Let} and
  @{text "Let_rec"}. In case of @{text "Let"}, the binding clause specifies
  that all atoms given by @{text "set (bn as)"} have to be bound in @{text
  t}. Therefore we have to subtract @{text "set (bn as)"} from @{text
  "fa\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> t"}. However, we also need to add all atoms that are
  free in @{text "as"}. This is
  in contrast with @{text "Let_rec"} where we have a recursive
  binder to bind all occurrences of the atoms in @{text
  "set (bn as)"} also inside @{text "as"}. Therefore we have to subtract
  @{text "set (bn as)"} from both @{text "fa\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> t"} and @{text "fa\<^bsub>assn\<^esub> as"}. 
  Like the function @{text "bn"}, the function @{text "fa\<^bsub>bn\<^esub>"} traverses the 
  list of assignments, but instead returns the free atoms, which means in this 
  example the free atoms in the argument @{text "t"}.  

  An interesting point in this
  example is that a ``naked'' assignment (@{text "ANil"} or @{text "ACons"}) does not bind any
  atoms, even if the binding function is specified over assignments. 
  Only in the context of a @{text Let} or @{text "Let_rec"}, where the binding clauses are given, will
  some atoms actually become bound.  This is a phenomenon that has also been pointed
  out in \cite{ott-jfp}. For us this observation is crucial, because we would 
  not be able to lift the @{text "bn"}-functions to $\alpha$-equated terms if they act on 
  atoms that are bound. In that case, these functions would \emph{not} respect
  $\alpha$-equivalence.

  Next we define the $\alpha$-equivalence relations for the raw types @{text
  "ty"}$_{1..n}$ from the specification. We write them as
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "\<approx>ty\<^isub>1, \<dots>, \<approx>ty\<^isub>n"}. 
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  Like with the free-atom functions, we also need to
  define auxiliary $\alpha$-equivalence relations 
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "\<approx>bn\<^isub>1, \<dots>, \<approx>bn\<^isub>m"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  for the binding functions @{text "bn"}$_{1..m}$, 
  To simplify our definitions we will use the following abbreviations for
  \emph{compound equivalence relations} and \emph{compound free-atom functions} acting on tuples
  %
  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{r@ {\hspace{2mm}}c@ {\hspace{2mm}}l}
  @{text "(x\<^isub>1,.., x\<^isub>n) (R\<^isub>1,.., R\<^isub>n) (x\<PRIME>\<^isub>1,.., x\<PRIME>\<^isub>n)"} & @{text "\<equiv>"} & \\
  \multicolumn{3}{r}{@{text "x\<^isub>1 R\<^isub>1 x\<PRIME>\<^isub>1 \<and> .. \<and> x\<^isub>n R\<^isub>n x\<PRIME>\<^isub>n"}}\\
  @{text "(fa\<^isub>1,.., fa\<^isub>n) (x\<^isub>1,.., x\<^isub>n)"} & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{text "fa\<^isub>1 x\<^isub>1 \<union> .. \<union> fa\<^isub>n x\<^isub>n"}\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}


  The $\alpha$-equivalence relations are defined as inductive predicates
  having a single clause for each term-constructor. Assuming a
  term-constructor @{text C} is of type @{text ty} and has the binding clauses
  @{term "bc"}$_{1..k}$, then the $\alpha$-equivalence clause has the form
  %
  \begin{center}
  \mbox{\infer{@{text "C z\<^isub>1 \<dots> z\<^isub>n  \<approx>ty  C z\<PRIME>\<^isub>1 \<dots> z\<PRIME>\<^isub>n"}}
  {@{text "prems(bc\<^isub>1) \<dots> prems(bc\<^isub>k)"}}} 
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  The task below is to specify what the premises of a binding clause are. As a
  special instance, we first treat the case where @{text "bc\<^isub>i"} is the
  empty binding clause of the form
  %
  \begin{center}
  \mbox{\isacommand{bind\_set} @{term "{}"} \isacommand{in} @{text "d\<^isub>1\<dots>d\<^isub>q"}.}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  In this binding clause no atom is bound and we only have to $\alpha$-relate the bodies. For this
  we build first the tuples @{text "D \<equiv> (d\<^isub>1,\<dots>, d\<^isub>q)"} and @{text "D' \<equiv> (d\<PRIME>\<^isub>1,\<dots>, d\<PRIME>\<^isub>q)"}  
  whereby the labels @{text "d"}$_{1..q}$ refer to arguments @{text "z"}$_{1..n}$ and
  respectively @{text "d\<PRIME>"}$_{1..q}$ to @{text "z\<PRIME>"}$_{1..n}$. In order to relate
  two such tuples we define the compound $\alpha$-equivalence relation @{text "R"} as follows
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{rempty}
  \mbox{@{text "R \<equiv> (R\<^isub>1,\<dots>, R\<^isub>q)"}}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  with @{text "R\<^isub>i"} being @{text "\<approx>ty\<^isub>i"} if the corresponding labels @{text "d\<^isub>i"} and 
  @{text "d\<PRIME>\<^isub>i"} refer
  to a recursive argument of @{text C} with type @{text "ty\<^isub>i"}; otherwise
  we take @{text "R\<^isub>i"} to be the equality @{text "="}. This lets us define
  the premise for an empty binding clause succinctly as @{text "prems(bc\<^isub>i) \<equiv> D R D'"},
  which can be unfolded to the series of premises
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "d\<^isub>1 R\<^isub>1 d\<PRIME>\<^isub>1  \<dots> d\<^isub>q R\<^isub>q d\<PRIME>\<^isub>q"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  We will use the unfolded version in the examples below.

  Now suppose the binding clause @{text "bc\<^isub>i"} is of the general form 
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{nonempty}
  \mbox{\isacommand{bind\_set} @{text "b\<^isub>1\<dots>b\<^isub>p"} \isacommand{in} @{text "d\<^isub>1\<dots>d\<^isub>q"}.}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  In this case we define a premise @{text P} using the relation
  $\approx_{\,\textit{set}}$ given in Section~\ref{sec:binders} (similarly
  $\approx_{\,\textit{res}}$ and $\approx_{\,\textit{list}}$ for the other
  binding modes). This premise defines $\alpha$-equivalence of two abstractions
  involving multiple binders. As above, we first build the tuples @{text "D"} and
  @{text "D'"} for the bodies @{text "d"}$_{1..q}$, and the corresponding
  compound $\alpha$-relation @{text "R"} (shown in \eqref{rempty}). 
  For $\approx_{\,\textit{set}}$  we also need
  a compound free-atom function for the bodies defined as
  %
  \begin{center}
  \mbox{@{text "fa \<equiv> (fa_ty\<^isub>1,\<dots>, fa_ty\<^isub>q)"}}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  with the assumption that the @{text "d"}$_{1..q}$ refer to arguments of types @{text "ty"}$_{1..q}$.
  The last ingredient we need are the sets of atoms bound in the bodies.
  For this we take

  \begin{center}
  @{text "B \<equiv> bn_ty\<^isub>1 b\<^isub>1 \<union> \<dots> \<union> bn_ty\<^isub>p b\<^isub>p"}\;.\\
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  Similarly for @{text "B'"} using the labels @{text "b\<PRIME>"}$_{1..p}$. This 
  lets us formally define the premise @{text P} for a non-empty binding clause as:
  %
  \begin{center}
  \mbox{@{term "P \<equiv> \<exists>p. (B, D) \<approx>gen R fa p (B', D')"}}\;.
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  This premise accounts for $\alpha$-equivalence of the bodies of the binding
  clause. 
  However, in case the binders have non-recursive deep binders, this premise
  is not enough:
  we also have to ``propagate'' $\alpha$-equivalence inside the structure of
  these binders. An example is @{text "Let"} where we have to make sure the
  right-hand sides of assignments are $\alpha$-equivalent. For this we use 
  relations @{text "\<approx>bn"}$_{1..m}$ (which we will formally define shortly).
  Let us assume the non-recursive deep binders in @{text "bc\<^isub>i"} are
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "bn\<^isub>1 l\<^isub>1, \<dots>, bn\<^isub>r l\<^isub>r"}.
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  The tuple @{text L} is then @{text "(l\<^isub>1,\<dots>,l\<^isub>r)"} (similarly @{text "L'"})
  and the compound equivalence relation @{text "R'"} is @{text "(\<approx>bn\<^isub>1,\<dots>,\<approx>bn\<^isub>r)"}. 
  All premises for @{text "bc\<^isub>i"} are then given by
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "prems(bc\<^isub>i) \<equiv> P  \<and>   L R' L'"}
  \end{center} 

  \noindent 
  The auxiliary $\alpha$-equivalence relations @{text "\<approx>bn"}$_{1..m}$ 
  in @{text "R'"} are defined as follows: assuming a @{text bn}-clause is of the form
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "bn (C z\<^isub>1 \<dots> z\<^isub>s) = rhs"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  where the @{text "z"}$_{1..s}$ are of types @{text "ty"}$_{1..s}$,
  then the corresponding $\alpha$-equivalence clause for @{text "\<approx>bn"} has the form
  %
  \begin{center}
  \mbox{\infer{@{text "C z\<^isub>1 \<dots> z\<^isub>s \<approx>bn C z\<PRIME>\<^isub>1 \<dots> z\<PRIME>\<^isub>s"}}
  {@{text "z\<^isub>1 R\<^isub>1 z\<PRIME>\<^isub>1 \<dots> z\<^isub>s R\<^isub>s z\<PRIME>\<^isub>s"}}}
  \end{center}
  
  \noindent
  In this clause the relations @{text "R"}$_{1..s}$ are given by 

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{c@ {\hspace{2mm}}p{7cm}}
  $\bullet$ & @{text "z\<^isub>i \<approx>ty z\<PRIME>\<^isub>i"} provided @{text "z\<^isub>i"} does not occur in @{text rhs} and 
  is a recursive argument of @{text C},\\
  $\bullet$ & @{text "z\<^isub>i = z\<PRIME>\<^isub>i"} provided @{text "z\<^isub>i"} does not occur in @{text rhs}
  and is a non-recursive argument of @{text C},\\
  $\bullet$ & @{text "z\<^isub>i \<approx>bn\<^isub>i z\<PRIME>\<^isub>i"} provided @{text "z\<^isub>i"} occurs in @{text rhs}
  with the recursive call @{text "bn\<^isub>i x\<^isub>i"} and\\
  $\bullet$ & @{text True} provided @{text "z\<^isub>i"} occurs in @{text rhs} but without a
  recursive call.
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  This completes the definition of $\alpha$-equivalence. As a sanity check, we can show
  that the premises of empty binding clauses are a special case of the clauses for 
  non-empty ones (we just have to unfold the definition of $\approx_{\,\textit{set}}$ and take @{text "0"}
  for the existentially quantified permutation).

  Again let us take a look at a concrete example for these definitions. For \eqref{letrecs}
  we have three relations $\approx_{\textit{trm}}$, $\approx_{\textit{assn}}$ and
  $\approx_{\textit{bn}}$ with the following clauses:

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}c @ {}}
  \infer{@{text "Let as t \<approx>\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> Let as' t'"}}
  {@{term "\<exists>p. (bn as, t) \<approx>lst alpha_trm fa_trm p (bn as', t')"} & @{text "as \<approx>\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> as'"}}\smallskip\\
  \makebox[0mm]{\infer{@{text "Let_rec as t \<approx>\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> Let_rec as' t'"}}
  {@{term "\<exists>p. (bn as, ast) \<approx>lst alpha_trm2 fa_trm2 p (bn as', ast')"}}}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}c @ {}}
  \infer{@{text "ANil \<approx>\<^bsub>assn\<^esub> ANil"}}{}\smallskip\\
  \infer{@{text "ACons a t as \<approx>\<^bsub>assn\<^esub> ACons a' t' as"}}
  {@{text "a = a'"} & @{text "t \<approx>\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> t'"} & @{text "as \<approx>\<^bsub>assn\<^esub> as'"}}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}c @ {}}
  \infer{@{text "ANil \<approx>\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> ANil"}}{}\smallskip\\
  \infer{@{text "ACons a t as \<approx>\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> ACons a' t' as"}}
  {@{text "t \<approx>\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> t'"} & @{text "as \<approx>\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> as'"}}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  Note the difference between  $\approx_{\textit{assn}}$ and
  $\approx_{\textit{bn}}$: the latter only ``tracks'' $\alpha$-equivalence of 
  the components in an assignment that are \emph{not} bound. This is needed in the 
  in the clause for @{text "Let"} (which is has
  a non-recursive binder). The underlying reason is that the terms inside an assignment are not meant 
  to be ``under'' the binder. Such a premise is \emph{not} needed in @{text "Let_rec"}, 
  because there all components of an assignment are ``under'' the binder. 
*}

section {* Establishing the Reasoning Infrastructure *}

text {*
  Having made all necessary definitions for raw terms, we can start
  with establishing the reasoning infrastructure for the $\alpha$-equated types
  @{text "ty\<AL>"}$_{1..n}$, that is the types the user originally specified. We sketch
  in this section the proofs we need for establishing this infrastructure. One
  main point of our work is that we have completely automated these proofs in Isabelle/HOL.

  First we establish that the
  $\alpha$-equivalence relations defined in the previous section are 
  equivalence relations.

  \begin{lemma}\label{equiv} 
  Given the raw types @{text "ty"}$_{1..n}$ and binding functions
  @{text "bn"}$_{1..m}$, the relations @{text "\<approx>ty"}$_{1..n}$ and 
  @{text "\<approx>bn"}$_{1..m}$ are equivalence relations and equivariant.
  \end{lemma}

  \begin{proof} 
  The proof is by mutual induction over the definitions. The non-trivial
  cases involve premises built up by $\approx_{\textit{set}}$, 
  $\approx_{\textit{res}}$ and $\approx_{\textit{list}}$. They 
  can be dealt with as in Lemma~\ref{alphaeq}.
  \end{proof}

  \noindent 
  We can feed this lemma into our quotient package and obtain new types @{text
  "ty"}$^\alpha_{1..n}$ representing $\alpha$-equated terms of types @{text "ty"}$_{1..n}$. 
  We also obtain definitions for the term-constructors @{text
  "C"}$^\alpha_{1..k}$ from the raw term-constructors @{text
  "C"}$_{1..k}$, and similar definitions for the free-atom functions @{text
  "fa_ty"}$^\alpha_{1..n}$ and @{text "fa_bn"}$^\alpha_{1..m}$ as well as the binding functions @{text
  "bn"}$^\alpha_{1..m}$. However, these definitions are not really useful to the 
  user, since they are given in terms of the isomorphisms we obtained by 
  creating new types in Isabelle/HOL (recall the picture shown in the 
  Introduction).

  The first useful property for the user is the fact that distinct 
  term-constructors are not 
  equal, that is
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{distinctalpha}
  \mbox{@{text "C"}$^\alpha$~@{text "x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>r"}~@{text "\<noteq>"}~% 
  @{text "D"}$^\alpha$~@{text "y\<^isub>1 \<dots> y\<^isub>s"}} 
  \end{equation}
  
  \noindent
  whenever @{text "C"}$^\alpha$~@{text "\<noteq>"}~@{text "D"}$^\alpha$.
  In order to derive this fact, we use the definition of $\alpha$-equivalence
  and establish that
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{distinctraw}
  \mbox{@{text "C x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>r"}\;$\not\approx$@{text ty}\;@{text "D y\<^isub>1 \<dots> y\<^isub>s"}}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  holds for the corresponding raw term-constructors.
  In order to deduce \eqref{distinctalpha} from \eqref{distinctraw}, our quotient
  package needs to know that the raw term-constructors @{text "C"} and @{text "D"} 
  are \emph{respectful} w.r.t.~the $\alpha$-equivalence relations (see \cite{Homeier05}).
  Assuming, for example, @{text "C"} is of type @{text "ty"} with argument types
  @{text "ty"}$_{1..r}$, respectfulness amounts to showing that
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "C x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>r \<approx>ty C x\<PRIME>\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<PRIME>\<^isub>r"}
  \end{center}  

  \noindent
  holds under the assumptions that we have \mbox{@{text
  "x\<^isub>i \<approx>ty\<^isub>i x\<PRIME>\<^isub>i"}} whenever @{text "x\<^isub>i"}
  and @{text "x\<PRIME>\<^isub>i"} are recursive arguments of @{text C} and
  @{text "x\<^isub>i = x\<PRIME>\<^isub>i"} whenever they are non-recursive arguments. We can prove this
  implication by applying the corresponding rule in our $\alpha$-equivalence
  definition and by establishing the following auxiliary facts 
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{fnresp}
  \mbox{%
  \begin{tabular}{l}
  @{text "x \<approx>ty\<^isub>i x\<PRIME>"}~~implies~@{text "fa_ty\<^isub>i x = fa_ty\<^isub>i x\<PRIME>"}\\
  @{text "x \<approx>ty\<^isub>j x\<PRIME>"}~~implies~@{text "fa_bn\<^isub>j x = fa_bn\<^isub>j x\<PRIME>"}\\
  @{text "x \<approx>ty\<^isub>j x\<PRIME>"}~~implies~@{text "bn\<^isub>j x = bn\<^isub>j x\<PRIME>"}\\
  @{text "x \<approx>ty\<^isub>j x\<PRIME>"}~~implies~@{text "x \<approx>bn\<^isub>j x\<PRIME>"}\\
  \end{tabular}}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  They can be established by induction on @{text "\<approx>ty"}$_{1..n}$. Whereas the first,
  second and last implication are true by how we stated our definitions, the 
  third \emph{only} holds because of our restriction
  imposed on the form of the binding functions---namely \emph{not} returning 
  any bound atoms. In Ott, in contrast, the user may 
  define @{text "bn"}$_{1..m}$ so that they return bound
  atoms and in this case the third implication is \emph{not} true. A 
  result is that the lifing of the corresponding binding functions in Ott to $\alpha$-equated
  terms is impossible.

  Having established respectfulness for the raw term-constructors, the 
  quotient package is able to automatically deduce \eqref{distinctalpha} from 
  \eqref{distinctraw}. Having the facts \eqref{fnresp} at our disposal, we can 
  also lift properties that characterise when two raw terms of the form
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "C x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>r \<approx>ty C x\<PRIME>\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<PRIME>\<^isub>r"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  are $\alpha$-equivalent. This gives us conditions when the corresponding
  $\alpha$-equated terms are \emph{equal}, namely
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "C\<^sup>\<alpha> x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>r = C\<^sup>\<alpha> x\<PRIME>\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<PRIME>\<^isub>r"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  We call these conditions as \emph{quasi-injectivity}. They correspond to
  the premises in our $\alpha$-equivalence relations.

  Next we can lift the permutation 
  operations defined in \eqref{ceqvt}. In order to make this 
  lifting to go through, we have to show that the permutation operations are respectful. 
  This amounts to showing that the 
  $\alpha$-equivalence relations are equivariant, which we already established 
  in Lemma~\ref{equiv}. As a result we can add the equations
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{calphaeqvt}
  @{text "p \<bullet> (C\<^sup>\<alpha> x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>r) = C\<^sup>\<alpha> (p \<bullet> x\<^isub>1) \<dots> (p \<bullet> x\<^isub>r)"}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  to our infrastructure. In a similar fashion we can lift the defining equations
  of the free-atom functions @{text "fn_ty\<AL>"}$_{1..n}$ and
  @{text "fa_bn\<AL>"}$_{1..m}$ as well as of the binding functions @{text
  "bn\<AL>"}$_{1..m}$ and the size functions @{text "size_ty\<AL>"}$_{1..n}$.
  The latter are defined automatically for the raw types @{text "ty"}$_{1..n}$
  by the datatype package of Isabelle/HOL.

  Finally we can add to our infrastructure a structural induction principle 
  for the types @{text "ty\<AL>"}$_{i..n}$ whose 
  conclusion of the form
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{weakinduct}
  \mbox{@{text "P\<^isub>1 x\<^isub>1 \<and> \<dots> \<and> P\<^isub>n x\<^isub>n "}}
  \end{equation} 

  \noindent
  whereby the @{text P}$_{1..n}$ are predicates and the @{text x}$_{1..n}$ 
  have types @{text "ty\<AL>"}$_{1..n}$. This induction principle has for each
  term constructor @{text "C"}$^\alpha$ a premise of the form
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{weakprem}
  \mbox{@{text "\<forall>x\<^isub>1\<dots>x\<^isub>r. P\<^isub>i x\<^isub>i \<and> \<dots> \<and> P\<^isub>j x\<^isub>j \<Rightarrow> P (C\<^sup>\<alpha> x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>r)"}} 
  \end{equation}

  \noindent 
  in which the @{text "x"}$_{i..j}$ @{text "\<subseteq>"} @{text "x"}$_{1..r}$ are 
  the recursive arguments of @{text "C\<AL>"}. 

  By working now completely on the $\alpha$-equated level, we
  can first show that the free-atom functions and binding functions are
  equivariant, namely
  %
  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{rcl}
  @{text "p \<bullet> (fa_ty\<AL>\<^isub>i  x)"} & $=$ & @{text "fa_ty\<AL>\<^isub>i (p \<bullet> x)"}\\
  @{text "p \<bullet> (fa_bn\<AL>\<^isub>j  x)"} & $=$ & @{text "fa_bn\<AL>\<^isub>j (p \<bullet> x)"}\\
  @{text "p \<bullet> (bn\<AL>\<^isub>j  x)"}    & $=$ & @{text "bn\<AL>\<^isub>j (p \<bullet> x)"}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  These properties can be established using the induction principle
  in \eqref{weakinduct}.
  Having these equivariant properties established, we can
  show for every term-constructor @{text "C\<^sup>\<alpha>"} that 

  \begin{center}
  @{text "(supp x\<^isub>1 \<union> \<dots> \<union> supp x\<^isub>r) supports (C\<^sup>\<alpha> x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>r)"}
  \end{center}
 
  \noindent
  holds. This together with Property~\ref{supportsprop} allows us to prove
  that every @{text x} of type @{text "ty\<AL>"}$_{1..n}$ is finitely supported, 
  namely @{text "finite (supp x)"}. This can be again shown by induction 
  over @{text "ty\<AL>"}$_{1..n}$. Lastly, we can show that the support of 
  elements in  @{text "ty\<AL>"}$_{1..n}$ is the same as @{text "fa_ty\<AL>"}$_{1..n}$.
  This fact is important in a nominal setting, but also provides evidence 
  that our notions of free-atoms and $\alpha$-equivalence are correct.

  \begin{lemma} 
  For every @{text "x"} of type @{text "ty\<AL>"}$_{1..n}$, we have
  @{text "supp x = fa_ty\<AL>\<^isub>i x"}.
  \end{lemma}

  \begin{proof}
  The proof is by induction. In each case
  we unfold the definition of @{text "supp"}, move the swapping inside the 
  term-constructors and then use the quasi-injectivity lemmas in order to complete the
  proof. For the abstraction cases we use the facts derived in Theorem~\ref{suppabs}.
  \end{proof}

  \noindent
  To sum up this section, we can established automatically a reasoning infrastructure
  for the types @{text "ty\<AL>"}$_{1..n}$ 
  by first lifting definitions from the raw level to the quotient level and
  then by establishing facts about these lifted definitions. All necessary proofs
  are generated automatically by custom ML-code. This code can deal with 
  specifications such as the one shown in Figure~\ref{nominalcorehas} for Core-Haskell.  

  \begin{figure}[t!]
  \begin{boxedminipage}{\linewidth}
  \small
  \begin{tabular}{l}
  \isacommand{atom\_decl}~@{text "var cvar tvar"}\\[1mm]
  \isacommand{nominal\_datatype}~@{text "tkind ="}\\
  \phantom{$|$}~@{text "KStar"}~$|$~@{text "KFun tkind tkind"}\\ 
  \isacommand{and}~@{text "ckind ="}\\
  \phantom{$|$}~@{text "CKSim ty ty"}\\
  \isacommand{and}~@{text "ty ="}\\
  \phantom{$|$}~@{text "TVar tvar"}~$|$~@{text "T string"}~$|$~@{text "TApp ty ty"}\\
  $|$~@{text "TFun string ty_list"}~%
  $|$~@{text "TAll tv::tvar tkind ty::ty"}  \isacommand{bind}~@{text "tv"}~\isacommand{in}~@{text ty}\\
  $|$~@{text "TArr ckind ty"}\\
  \isacommand{and}~@{text "ty_lst ="}\\
  \phantom{$|$}~@{text "TNil"}~$|$~@{text "TCons ty ty_lst"}\\
  \isacommand{and}~@{text "cty ="}\\
  \phantom{$|$}~@{text "CVar cvar"}~%
  $|$~@{text "C string"}~$|$~@{text "CApp cty cty"}~$|$~@{text "CFun string co_lst"}\\
  $|$~@{text "CAll cv::cvar ckind cty::cty"}  \isacommand{bind}~@{text "cv"}~\isacommand{in}~@{text cty}\\
  $|$~@{text "CArr ckind cty"}~$|$~@{text "CRefl ty"}~$|$~@{text "CSym cty"}~$|$~@{text "CCirc cty cty"}\\
  $|$~@{text "CAt cty ty"}~$|$~@{text "CLeft cty"}~$|$~@{text "CRight cty"}~$|$~@{text "CSim cty cty"}\\
  $|$~@{text "CRightc cty"}~$|$~@{text "CLeftc cty"}~$|$~@{text "Coerce cty cty"}\\
  \isacommand{and}~@{text "co_lst ="}\\
  \phantom{$|$}@{text "CNil"}~$|$~@{text "CCons cty co_lst"}\\
  \isacommand{and}~@{text "trm ="}\\
  \phantom{$|$}~@{text "Var var"}~$|$~@{text "K string"}\\
  $|$~@{text "LAM_ty tv::tvar tkind t::trm"}  \isacommand{bind}~@{text "tv"}~\isacommand{in}~@{text t}\\
  $|$~@{text "LAM_cty cv::cvar ckind t::trm"}   \isacommand{bind}~@{text "cv"}~\isacommand{in}~@{text t}\\
  $|$~@{text "App_ty trm ty"}~$|$~@{text "App_cty trm cty"}~$|$~@{text "App trm trm"}\\
  $|$~@{text "Lam v::var ty t::trm"}  \isacommand{bind}~@{text "v"}~\isacommand{in}~@{text t}\\
  $|$~@{text "Let x::var ty trm t::trm"}  \isacommand{bind}~@{text x}~\isacommand{in}~@{text t}\\
  $|$~@{text "Case trm assoc_lst"}~$|$~@{text "Cast trm co"}\\
  \isacommand{and}~@{text "assoc_lst ="}\\
  \phantom{$|$}~@{text ANil}~%
  $|$~@{text "ACons p::pat t::trm assoc_lst"}  \isacommand{bind}~@{text "bv p"}~\isacommand{in}~@{text t}\\
  \isacommand{and}~@{text "pat ="}\\
  \phantom{$|$}~@{text "Kpat string tvtk_lst tvck_lst vt_lst"}\\
  \isacommand{and}~@{text "vt_lst ="}\\
  \phantom{$|$}~@{text VTNil}~$|$~@{text "VTCons var ty vt_lst"}\\
  \isacommand{and}~@{text "tvtk_lst ="}\\
  \phantom{$|$}~@{text TVTKNil}~$|$~@{text "TVTKCons tvar tkind tvtk_lst"}\\
  \isacommand{and}~@{text "tvck_lst ="}\\ 
  \phantom{$|$}~@{text TVCKNil}~$|$ @{text "TVCKCons cvar ckind tvck_lst"}\\
  \isacommand{binder}\\
  @{text "bv :: pat \<Rightarrow> atom list"}~\isacommand{and}~%
  @{text "bv1 :: vt_lst \<Rightarrow> atom list"}~\isacommand{and}\\
  @{text "bv2 :: tvtk_lst \<Rightarrow> atom list"}~\isacommand{and}~%
  @{text "bv3 :: tvck_lst \<Rightarrow> atom list"}\\
  \isacommand{where}\\
  \phantom{$|$}~@{text "bv (K s tvts tvcs vs) = (bv3 tvts) @ (bv2 tvcs) @ (bv1 vs)"}\\
  $|$~@{text "bv1 VTNil = []"}\\
  $|$~@{text "bv1 (VTCons x ty tl) = (atom x)::(bv1 tl)"}\\
  $|$~@{text "bv2 TVTKNil = []"}\\
  $|$~@{text "bv2 (TVTKCons a ty tl) = (atom a)::(bv2 tl)"}\\
  $|$~@{text "bv3 TVCKNil = []"}\\
  $|$~@{text "bv3 (TVCKCons c cty tl) = (atom c)::(bv3 tl)"}\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{boxedminipage}
  \caption{The nominal datatype declaration for Core-Haskell. For the moment we
  do not support nested types; therefore we explicitly have to unfold the 
  lists @{text "co_lst"}, @{text "assoc_lst"} and so on. This will be improved
  in a future version of Nominal Isabelle. Apart from that, the 
  declaration follows closely the original in Figure~\ref{corehas}. The
  point of our work is that having made such a declaration in Nominal Isabelle,
  one obtains automatically a reasoning infrastructure for Core-Haskell.
  \label{nominalcorehas}}
  \end{figure}
*}


section {* Strong Induction Principles *}

text {*
  In the previous section we were able to provide induction principles that 
  allow us to perform structural inductions over $\alpha$-equated terms. 
  We call such induction principles \emph{weak}, because in case of the 
  term-constructor @{text "C\<^sup>\<alpha> x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>r"},
  the induction hypothesis requires us to establish the implications \eqref{weakprem}.
  The problem with these implications is that in general they are difficult to establish.
  The reason is that we cannot make any assumption about the binders that might be in @{text "C\<^sup>\<alpha>"} 
  (for example we cannot assume the variable convention for them).

  In \cite{UrbanTasson05} we introduced a method for automatically
  strengthening weak induction principles for terms containing single
  binders. These stronger induction principles allow the user to make additional
  assumptions about binders. 
  These additional assumptions amount to a formal
  version of the informal variable convention for binders. A natural question is
  whether we can also strengthen the weak induction principles involving
  the general binders presented here. We will indeed be able to so, but for this we need an 
  additional notion for permuting deep binders. 

  Given a binding function @{text "bn"} we define an auxiliary permutation 
  operation @{text "_ \<bullet>\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> _"} which permutes only bound arguments in a deep binder.
  Assuming a clause of @{text bn} is given as 
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "bn (C x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>r) = rhs"}, 
  \end{center}

  \noindent 
  then we define 
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "p \<bullet>\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> (C x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>r) \<equiv> C y\<^isub>1 \<dots> y\<^isub>r"} 
  \end{center}
  
  \noindent
  with @{text "y\<^isub>i"} determined as follows:
  %
  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{c@ {\hspace{2mm}}p{7cm}}
  $\bullet$ & @{text "y\<^isub>i \<equiv> x\<^isub>i"} provided @{text "x\<^isub>i"} does not occur in @{text "rhs"}\\
  $\bullet$ & @{text "y\<^isub>i \<equiv> p \<bullet>\<^bsub>bn'\<^esub> x\<^isub>i"} provided @{text "bn' x\<^isub>i"} is in @{text "rhs"}\\
  $\bullet$ & @{text "y\<^isub>i \<equiv> p \<bullet> x\<^isub>i"} otherwise
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}
  
  \noindent
  Using again the quotient package  we can lift the @{text "_ \<bullet>\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> _"} function to 
  $\alpha$-equated terms. We can then prove the following two facts

  \begin{lemma}\label{permutebn} 
  Given a binding function @{text "bn\<^sup>\<alpha>"} then for all @{text p}
  {\it (i)} @{text "p \<bullet> (bn\<^sup>\<alpha> x) = bn\<^sup>\<alpha> (p \<bullet>\<AL>\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> x)"} and {\it (ii)}
    @{text "fa_bn\<^isup>\<alpha> x = fa_bn\<^isup>\<alpha> (p \<bullet>\<AL>\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> x)"}.
  \end{lemma}

  \begin{proof} 
  By induction on @{text x}. The equations follow by simple unfolding 
  of the definitions. 
  \end{proof}

  \noindent
  The first property states that a permutation applied to a binding function is
  equivalent to first permuting the binders and then calculating the bound
  atoms. The second amounts to the fact that permuting the binders has no 
  effect on the free-atom function. The main point of this permutation
  function, however, is that if we have a permutation that is fresh 
  for the support of an object @{text x}, then we can use this permutation 
  to rename the binders in @{text x}, without ``changing'' @{text x}. In case of the 
  @{text "Let"} term-constructor from the example shown 
  in \eqref{letpat} this means for a permutation @{text "r"}
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{renaming}
  \begin{array}{l}
  \mbox{if @{term "supp (Abs_lst (bn p) t\<^isub>2)  \<sharp>* r"}}\\ 
  \qquad\mbox{then @{text "Let p t\<^isub>1 t\<^isub>2 = Let (r \<bullet>\<AL>\<^bsub>bn_pat\<^esub> p) t\<^isub>1 (r \<bullet> t\<^isub>2)"}}
  \end{array}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  This fact will be crucial when establishing the strong induction principles below.

 
  In our running example about @{text "Let"}, the strong induction
  principle means that instead 
  of establishing the implication 
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "\<forall>p t\<^isub>1 t\<^isub>2. P\<^bsub>pat\<^esub> p \<and> P\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> t\<^isub>1 \<and> P\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> t\<^isub>2 \<Rightarrow> P\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> (Let p t\<^isub>1 t\<^isub>2)"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  it is sufficient to establish the following implication
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{strong}
  \mbox{\begin{tabular}{l}
  @{text "\<forall>p t\<^isub>1 t\<^isub>2 c."}\\
  \hspace{5mm}@{text "set (bn p) #\<^sup>* c \<and>"}\\
  \hspace{5mm}@{text "(\<forall>d. P\<^bsub>pat\<^esub> d p) \<and> (\<forall>d. P\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> d t\<^isub>1) \<and> (\<forall>d. P\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> d t\<^isub>2)"}\\
  \hspace{15mm}@{text "\<Rightarrow> P\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> c (Let p t\<^isub>1 t\<^isub>2)"}
  \end{tabular}}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent 
  While this implication contains an additional argument, namely @{text c}, and 
  also additional universal quantifications, it is usually easier to establish.
  The reason is that we have the freshness 
  assumption @{text "set (bn\<^sup>\<alpha> p) #\<^sup>* c"}, whereby @{text c} can be arbitrarily 
  chosen by the user as long as it has finite support.

  Let us now show how we derive the strong induction principles from the
  weak ones. In case of the @{text "Let"}-example we derive by the weak 
  induction the following two properties
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{hyps}
  @{text "\<forall>q c. P\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> c (q \<bullet> t)"} \hspace{4mm} 
  @{text "\<forall>q\<^isub>1 q\<^isub>2 c. P\<^bsub>pat\<^esub> (q\<^isub>1 \<bullet>\<AL>\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> (q\<^isub>2 \<bullet> p))"}
  \end{equation} 

  \noindent
  For the @{text Let} term-constructor  we therefore have to establish @{text "P\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> c (q \<bullet> Let p t\<^isub>1 t\<^isub>2)"} 
  assuming \eqref{hyps} as induction hypotheses (the first for @{text t\<^isub>1} and @{text t\<^isub>2}). 
  By Property~\ref{avoiding} we
  obtain a permutation @{text "r"} such that 
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{rprops}
  @{term "(r \<bullet> set (bn (q \<bullet> p))) \<sharp>* c "}\hspace{4mm}
  @{term "supp (Abs_lst (bn (q \<bullet> p)) (q \<bullet> t\<^isub>2)) \<sharp>* r"}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  hold. The latter fact and \eqref{renaming} give us
  %
  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{l}
  @{text "Let (q \<bullet> p) (q \<bullet> t\<^isub>1) (q \<bullet> t\<^isub>2) ="} \\
  \hspace{15mm}@{text "Let (r \<bullet>\<AL>\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> (q \<bullet> p)) (q \<bullet> t\<^isub>1) (r \<bullet> (q \<bullet> t\<^isub>2))"}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  So instead of proving @{text "P\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> c (q \<bullet> Let p t\<^isub>1 t\<^isub>2)"}, we can equally
  establish @{text "P\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> c (Let (r \<bullet>\<AL>\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> (q \<bullet> p)) (q \<bullet> t\<^isub>1) (r \<bullet> (q \<bullet> t\<^isub>2)))"}.
  To do so, we will use the implication \eqref{strong} of the strong induction
  principle, which requires us to discharge
  the following four proof obligations:
  %
  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{rl}
  {\it (i)} &   @{text "set (bn (r \<bullet>\<AL>\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> (q \<bullet> p))) #\<^sup>* c"}\\
  {\it (ii)} &  @{text "\<forall>d. P\<^bsub>pat\<^esub> d (r \<bullet>\<AL>\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> (q \<bullet> p))"}\\
  {\it (iii)} & @{text "\<forall>d. P\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> d (q \<bullet> t\<^isub>1)"}\\
  {\it (iv)} & @{text "\<forall>d. P\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> d (r \<bullet> (q \<bullet> t\<^isub>2))"}\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  The first follows from \eqref{rprops} and Lemma~\ref{permutebn}.{\it (i)}; the 
  others from the induction hypotheses in \eqref{hyps} (in the fourth case
  we have to use the fact that @{term "(r \<bullet> (q \<bullet> t\<^isub>2)) = (r + q) \<bullet> t\<^isub>2"}).

  Taking now the identity permutation @{text 0} for the permutations in \eqref{hyps},
  we can establish our original goals, namely @{text "P\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> c t"} and \mbox{@{text "P\<^bsub>pat\<^esub> c p"}}.
  This completes the proof showing that the weak induction principles imply 
  the strong induction principles. 
*}


section {* Related Work *}

text {*
  To our knowledge the earliest usage of general binders in a theorem prover
  is described in \cite{NaraschewskiNipkow99} about a formalisation of the
  algorithm W. This formalisation implements binding in type-schemes using a
  de-Bruijn indices representation. Since type-schemes in W contain only a single
  place where variables are bound, different indices do not refer to different binders (as in the usual
  de-Bruijn representation), but to different bound variables. A similar idea
  has been recently explored for general binders in the locally nameless
  approach to binding \cite{chargueraud09}.  There, de-Bruijn indices consist
  of two numbers, one referring to the place where a variable is bound and the
  other to which variable is bound. The reasoning infrastructure for both
  representations of bindings comes for free in theorem provers like Isabelle/HOL or
  Coq, since the corresponding term-calculi can be implemented as ``normal''
  datatypes.  However, in both approaches it seems difficult to achieve our
  fine-grained control over the ``semantics'' of bindings (i.e.~whether the
  order of binders should matter, or vacuous binders should be taken into
  account). To do so, one would require additional predicates that filter out
  unwanted terms. Our guess is that such predicates result in rather
  intricate formal reasoning.

  Another representation technique for binding is higher-order abstract syntax
  (HOAS), which for example is implemented in the Twelf system. This representation
  technique supports very elegantly many aspects of \emph{single} binding, and
  impressive work has been done that uses HOAS for mechanising the metatheory
  of SML~\cite{LeeCraryHarper07}. We are, however, not aware how multiple
  binders of SML are represented in this work. Judging from the submitted
  Twelf-solution for the POPLmark challenge, HOAS cannot easily deal with
  binding constructs where the number of bound variables is not fixed. For
  example in the second part of this challenge, @{text "Let"}s involve
  patterns that bind multiple variables at once. In such situations, HOAS
  representations have to resort to the iterated-single-binders-approach with
  all the unwanted consequences when reasoning about the resulting terms.

  Two formalisations involving general binders have been 
  performed in older
  versions of Nominal Isabelle (one about Psi-calculi and one about algorithm W 
  \cite{BengtsonParow09, UrbanNipkow09}).  Both
  use the approach based on iterated single binders. Our experience with
  the latter formalisation has been disappointing. The major pain arose from
  the need to ``unbind'' variables. This can be done in one step with our
  general binders described in this paper, but needs a cumbersome
  iteration with single binders. The resulting formal reasoning turned out to
  be rather unpleasant. The hope is that the extension presented in this paper
  is a substantial improvement.
 
  The most closely related work to the one presented here is the Ott-tool
  \cite{ott-jfp} and the C$\alpha$ml language \cite{Pottier06}. Ott is a nifty
  front-end for creating \LaTeX{} documents from specifications of
  term-calculi involving general binders. For a subset of the specifications
  Ott can also generate theorem prover code using a raw representation of
  terms, and in Coq also a locally nameless representation. The developers of
  this tool have also put forward (on paper) a definition for
  $\alpha$-equivalence of terms that can be specified in Ott.  This definition is
  rather different from ours, not using any nominal techniques.  To our
  knowledge there is also no concrete mathematical result concerning this
  notion of $\alpha$-equivalence.  A definition for the notion of free variables
  is work in progress in Ott.

  Although we were heavily inspired by the syntax in Ott,
  its definition of $\alpha$-equivalence is unsuitable for our extension of
  Nominal Isabelle. First, it is far too complicated to be a basis for
  automated proofs implemented on the ML-level of Isabelle/HOL. Second, it
  covers cases of binders depending on other binders, which just do not make
  sense for our $\alpha$-equated terms. Third, it allows empty types that have no
  meaning in a HOL-based theorem prover. We also had to generalise slightly Ott's 
  binding clauses. In Ott you specify binding clauses with a single body; we 
  allow more than one. We have to do this, because this makes a difference 
  for our notion of $\alpha$-equivalence in case of \isacommand{bind\_set} and 
  \isacommand{bind\_res}. Consider the examples

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {\hspace{2mm}}l@ {}}
  @{text "Foo\<^isub>1 xs::name fset t::trm s::trm"} &  
      \isacommand{bind\_set} @{text "xs"} \isacommand{in} @{text "t s"}\\
  @{text "Foo\<^isub>2 xs::name fset t::trm s::trm"} &  
      \isacommand{bind\_set} @{text "xs"} \isacommand{in} @{text "t"}, 
      \isacommand{bind\_set} @{text "xs"} \isacommand{in} @{text "s"}\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  In the first term-constructor we have a single
  body that happens to be ``spread'' over two arguments; in the second term-constructor we have
  two independent bodies in which the same variables are bound. As a result we 
  have

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{r@ {\hspace{1.5mm}}c@ {\hspace{1.5mm}}l}
  @{text "Foo\<^isub>1 {a, b} (a, b) (a, b)"} & $\not=$ & 
  @{text "Foo\<^isub>1 {a, b} (a, b) (b, a)"}\\
  @{text "Foo\<^isub>2 {a, b} (a, b) (a, b)"} & $=$ & 
  @{text "Foo\<^isub>2 {a, b} (a, b) (b, a)"}\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  and therefore need the extra generality to be able to distinguish between 
  both specifications.
  Because of how we set up our definitions, we also had to impose some restrictions
  (like a single binding function for a deep binder) that are not present in Ott. Our
  expectation is that we can still cover many interesting term-calculi from
  programming language research, for example Core-Haskell. 

  Pottier presents in \cite{Pottier06} a language, called C$\alpha$ml, for 
  representing terms with general binders inside OCaml. This language is
  implemented as a front-end that can be translated to OCaml with the help of
  a library. He presents a type-system in which the scope of general binders
  can be specified using special markers, written @{text "inner"} and 
  @{text "outer"}. It seems our and his specifications can be
  inter-translated as long as ours use the binding mode 
  \isacommand{bind} only.
  However, we have not proved this. Pottier gives a definition for 
  $\alpha$-equivalence, which also uses a permutation operation (like ours).
  Still, this definition is rather different from ours and he only proves that
  it defines an equivalence relation. A complete
  reasoning infrastructure is well beyond the purposes of his language. 
  
  In a slightly different domain (programming with dependent types), the 
  paper \cite{Altenkirch10} presents a calculus with a notion of 
  $\alpha$-equivalence related to our binding mode \isacommand{bind\_res}.
  The definition in \cite{Altenkirch10} is similar to the one by Pottier, except that it
  has a more operational flavour and calculates a partial (renaming) map. 
  In this way, the definition can deal with vacuous binders. However, to our
  best knowledge, no concrete mathematical result concerning this
  definition of $\alpha$-equivalence has been proved.    
*}

section {* Conclusion *}

text {*
  We have presented an extension of Nominal Isabelle for dealing with
  general binders, that is term-constructors having multiple bound 
  variables. For this extension we introduced new definitions of 
  $\alpha$-equivalence and automated all necessary proofs in Isabelle/HOL.
  To specify general binders we used the specifications from Ott, but extended them 
  in some places and restricted
  them in others so that they make sense in the context of $\alpha$-equated terms.
  We have tried out the extension with terms from Core-Haskell, type-schemes 
  and the lambda-calculus, and our code
  will eventually become part of the next Isabelle distribution.\footnote{For the moment
  it can be downloaded from the Mercurial repository linked at
  \href{http://isabelle.in.tum.de/nominal/download}
  {http://isabelle.in.tum.de/nominal/download}.}

  We have left out a discussion about how functions can be defined over
  $\alpha$-equated terms involving general binders. In earlier versions of Nominal
  Isabelle \cite{UrbanBerghofer06} this turned out to be a thorny issue.  We
  hope to do better this time by using the function package that has recently
  been implemented in Isabelle/HOL and also by restricting function
  definitions to equivariant functions (for such functions it is possible to
  provide more automation).

  There are some restrictions we imposed in this paper that we would like to lift in
  future work. One is the exclusion of nested datatype definitions. Nested
  datatype definitions allow one to specify, for instance, the function kinds
  in Core-Haskell as @{text "TFun string (ty list)"} instead of the unfolded
  version @{text "TFun string ty_list"} (see Figure~\ref{nominalcorehas}). To
  achieve this, we need a slightly more clever implementation than we have at the moment. 

  A more interesting line of investigation is whether we can go beyond the 
  simple-minded form of binding functions that we adopted from Ott. At the moment, binding
  functions can only return the empty set, a singleton atom set or unions
  of atom sets (similarly for lists). It remains to be seen whether 
  properties like
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "fa_ty x  =  bn x \<union> fa_bn x"}.
  \end{center}
  
  \noindent
  allow us to support more interesting binding functions. 

  We have also not yet played with other binding modes. For example we can
  imagine that there is need for a binding mode 
  where instead of lists, we abstract lists of distinct elements.
  Once we feel confident about such binding modes, our implementation 
  can be easily extended to accommodate them.

  \medskip
  \noindent
  {\bf Acknowledgements:} We are very grateful to Andrew Pitts for  
  many discussions about Nominal Isabelle. We also thank Peter Sewell for 
  making the informal notes \cite{SewellBestiary} available to us and 
  also for patiently explaining some of the finer points of the work on the Ott-tool.
  Stephanie Weirich suggested to separate the subgrammars
  of kinds and types in our Core-Haskell example.  

*}

(*<*)
end
(*>*)