Paper/Paper.thy
author Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
Fri, 02 Apr 2010 13:12:10 +0200
changeset 1770 26e44bcddb5b
parent 1769 6ca795b1cd76
child 1771 3e71af53cedb
permissions -rw-r--r--
first complete version (slightly less than 3h more to go)

(*<*)
theory Paper
imports "../Nominal/Test" "LaTeXsugar"
begin

consts
  fv :: "'a \<Rightarrow> 'b"
  abs_set :: "'a \<Rightarrow> 'b \<Rightarrow> 'c"
  alpha_bn :: "'a \<Rightarrow> 'a \<Rightarrow> bool"
  abs_set2 :: "'a \<Rightarrow> perm \<Rightarrow> 'b \<Rightarrow> 'c"
  alpha2 :: "'a \<Rightarrow> 'b \<Rightarrow> 'c \<Rightarrow> 'd \<Rightarrow> 'e \<Rightarrow> 'f" 

definition
 "equal \<equiv> (op =)" 

notation (latex output)
  swap ("'(_ _')" [1000, 1000] 1000) and
  fresh ("_ # _" [51, 51] 50) and
  fresh_star ("_ #\<^sup>* _" [51, 51] 50) and
  supp ("supp _" [78] 73) and
  uminus ("-_" [78] 73) and
  If  ("if _ then _ else _" 10) and
  alpha_gen ("_ \<approx>\<^raw:\raisebox{-1pt}{\makebox[0mm][l]{$\,_{\textit{set}}$}}>\<^bsup>_, _, _\<^esup> _") and
  alpha_lst ("_ \<approx>\<^raw:\raisebox{-1pt}{\makebox[0mm][l]{$\,_{\textit{list}}$}}>\<^bsup>_, _, _\<^esup> _") and
  alpha_res ("_ \<approx>\<^raw:\raisebox{-1pt}{\makebox[0mm][l]{$\,_{\textit{res}}$}}>\<^bsup>_, _, _\<^esup> _") and
  abs_set ("_ \<approx>\<^raw:{$\,_{\textit{abs\_set}}$}> _") and
  abs_set2 ("_ \<approx>\<^raw:\raisebox{-1pt}{\makebox[0mm][l]{$\,_{\textit{list}}$}}>\<^bsup>_\<^esup>  _") and
  alpha2 ("_ \<approx>\<^raw:\raisebox{-1pt}{\makebox[0mm][l]{$\,_{\textit{\#{}list}}$}}>\<^bsup>_, _, _\<^esup> _") and
  fv ("fv'(_')" [100] 100) and
  equal ("=") and
  alpha_abs ("_ \<approx>\<^raw:{$\,_{\textit{abs\_set}}$}> _") and 
  Abs ("[_]\<^raw:$\!$>\<^bsub>set\<^esub>._" [20, 101] 999) and
  Abs_lst ("[_]\<^raw:$\!$>\<^bsub>list\<^esub>._") and
  Abs_res ("[_]\<^raw:$\!$>\<^bsub>res\<^esub>._") and
  Cons ("_::_" [78,77] 73) and
  supp_gen ("aux _" [1000] 10) and
  alpha_bn ("_ \<approx>bn _")
(*>*)


section {* Introduction *}

text {*
%%%  @{text "(1, (2, 3))"}

  So far, Nominal Isabelle provides a mechanism for constructing
  alpha-equated terms, for example

  \begin{center}
  @{text "t ::= x | t t | \<lambda>x. t"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  where free and bound variables have names.  For such alpha-equated terms,  Nominal Isabelle
  derives automatically a reasoning infrastructure that has been used
  successfully in formalisations of an equivalence checking algorithm for LF
  \cite{UrbanCheneyBerghofer08}, Typed
  Scheme~\cite{TobinHochstadtFelleisen08}, several calculi for concurrency
  \cite{BengtsonParow09} and a strong normalisation result
  for cut-elimination in classical logic \cite{UrbanZhu08}. It has also been
  used by Pollack for formalisations in the locally-nameless approach to
  binding \cite{SatoPollack10}.

  However, Nominal Isabelle has fared less well in a formalisation of
  the algorithm W \cite{UrbanNipkow09}, where types and type-schemes are,
  respectively, of the form
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{tysch}
  \begin{array}{l}
  @{text "T ::= x | T \<rightarrow> T"}\hspace{5mm}
  @{text "S ::= \<forall>{x\<^isub>1,\<dots>, x\<^isub>n}. T"}
  \end{array}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  and the @{text "\<forall>"}-quantification binds a finite (possibly empty) set of
  type-variables.  While it is possible to implement this kind of more general
  binders by iterating single binders, this leads to a rather clumsy
  formalisation of W. The need of iterating single binders is also one reason
  why Nominal Isabelle and similar theorem provers that only provide
  mechanisms for binding single variables have not fared extremely well with the
  more advanced tasks in the POPLmark challenge \cite{challenge05}, because
  also there one would like to bind multiple variables at once.

  Binding multiple variables has interesting properties that cannot be captured
  easily by iterating single binders. For example in case of type-schemes we do not
  want to make a distinction about the order of the bound variables. Therefore
  we would like to regard the following two type-schemes as alpha-equivalent
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{ex1}
  @{text "\<forall>{x, y}. x \<rightarrow> y  \<approx>\<^isub>\<alpha>  \<forall>{y, x}. y \<rightarrow> x"} 
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  but assuming that @{text x}, @{text y} and @{text z} are distinct variables,
  the following two should \emph{not} be alpha-equivalent
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{ex2}
  @{text "\<forall>{x, y}. x \<rightarrow> y  \<notapprox>\<^isub>\<alpha>  \<forall>{z}. z \<rightarrow> z"} 
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  Moreover, we like to regard type-schemes as alpha-equivalent, if they differ
  only on \emph{vacuous} binders, such as
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{ex3}
  @{text "\<forall>{x}. x \<rightarrow> y  \<approx>\<^isub>\<alpha>  \<forall>{x, z}. x \<rightarrow> y"}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  where @{text z} does not occur freely in the type.  In this paper we will
  give a general binding mechanism and associated notion of alpha-equivalence
  that can be used to faithfully represent this kind of binding in Nominal
  Isabelle.  The difficulty of finding the right notion for alpha-equivalence
  can be appreciated in this case by considering that the definition given by
  Leroy in \cite{Leroy92} is incorrect (it omits a side-condition).

  However, the notion of alpha-equivalence that is preserved by vacuous
  binders is not always wanted. For example in terms like
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{one}
  @{text "\<LET> x = 3 \<AND> y = 2 \<IN> x - y \<END>"}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  we might not care in which order the assignments $x = 3$ and $y = 2$ are
  given, but it would be unusual to regard \eqref{one} as alpha-equivalent 
  with
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "\<LET> x = 3 \<AND> y = 2 \<AND> z = loop \<IN> x - y \<END>"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  Therefore we will also provide a separate binding mechanism for cases in
  which the order of binders does not matter, but the ``cardinality'' of the
  binders has to agree.

  However, we found that this is still not sufficient for dealing with
  language constructs frequently occurring in programming language
  research. For example in @{text "\<LET>"}s containing patterns like
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{two}
  @{text "\<LET> (x, y) = (3, 2) \<IN> x - y \<END>"}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  we want to bind all variables from the pattern inside the body of the
  $\mathtt{let}$, but we also care about the order of these variables, since
  we do not want to regard \eqref{two} as alpha-equivalent with
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "\<LET> (y, x) = (3, 2) \<IN> x - y \<END>"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  As a result, we provide three general binding mechanisms each of which binds
  multiple variables at once, and let the user chose which one is intended
  when formalising a term-calculus.

  By providing these general binding mechanisms, however, we have to work
  around a problem that has been pointed out by Pottier \cite{Pottier06} and
  Cheney \cite{Cheney05}: in @{text "\<LET>"}-constructs of the form
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "\<LET> x\<^isub>1 = t\<^isub>1 \<AND> \<dots> \<AND> x\<^isub>n = t\<^isub>n \<IN> s \<END>"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  which bind all the @{text "x\<^isub>i"} in @{text s}, we might not care
  about the order in which the @{text "x\<^isub>i = t\<^isub>i"} are given,
  but we do care about the information that there are as many @{text
  "x\<^isub>i"} as there are @{text "t\<^isub>i"}. We lose this information if
  we represent the @{text "\<LET>"}-constructor by something like
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "\<LET> [x\<^isub>1,\<dots>,x\<^isub>n].s [t\<^isub>1,\<dots>,t\<^isub>n]"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  where the notation @{text "[_]._"} indicates that the list of @{text "x\<^isub>i"}
  becomes bound in @{text s}. In this representation the term 
  \mbox{@{text "\<LET> [x].s [t\<^isub>1, t\<^isub>2]"}} is a perfectly legal
  instance, but the lengths of two lists do not agree. To exclude such terms, 
  additional predicates about well-formed
  terms are needed in order to ensure that the two lists are of equal
  length. This can result into very messy reasoning (see for
  example~\cite{BengtsonParow09}). To avoid this, we will allow type
  specifications for $\mathtt{let}$s as follows
  %
  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{r@ {\hspace{2mm}}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l}
  @{text trm} & @{text "::="}  & @{text "\<dots>"}\\ 
              & @{text "|"}    & @{text "\<LET> as::assn s::trm"}\hspace{4mm} 
                                 \isacommand{bind} @{text "bn(as)"} \isacommand{in} @{text "s"}\\[1mm]
  @{text assn} & @{text "::="} & @{text "\<ANIL>"}\\
               & @{text "|"}   & @{text "\<ACONS> name trm assn"}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  where @{text assn} is an auxiliary type representing a list of assignments
  and @{text bn} an auxiliary function identifying the variables to be bound
  by the @{text "\<LET>"}. This function can be defined by recursion over @{text
  assn} as follows

  \begin{center}
  @{text "bn(\<ANIL>) ="} @{term "{}"} \hspace{5mm} 
  @{text "bn(\<ACONS> x t as) = {x} \<union> bn(as)"} 
  \end{center}
  
  \noindent
  The scope of the binding is indicated by labels given to the types, for
  example @{text "s::trm"}, and a binding clause, in this case
  \isacommand{bind} @{text "bn(as)"} \isacommand{in} @{text "s"}. This binding
  clause states to bind in @{text s} all the names the function call @{text
  "bn(as)"} returns.  This style of specifying terms and bindings is heavily
  inspired by the syntax of the Ott-tool \cite{ott-jfp}.

  However, we will not be able to cope with all specifications that are
  allowed by Ott. One reason is that Ott lets the user to specify ``empty'' 
  types like

  \begin{center}
  @{text "t ::= t t | \<lambda>x. t"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  where no clause for variables is given. Arguably, such specifications make
  some sense in the context of Coq's type theory (which Ott supports), but not
  at all in a HOL-based environment where every datatype must have a non-empty
  set-theoretic model \cite{Berghofer99}.

  Another reason is that we establish the reasoning infrastructure
  for alpha-\emph{equated} terms. In contrast, Ott produces  a reasoning 
  infrastructure in Isabelle/HOL for
  \emph{non}-alpha-equated, or ``raw'', terms. While our alpha-equated terms
  and the raw terms produced by Ott use names for bound variables,
  there is a key difference: working with alpha-equated terms means, for example,  
  that the two type-schemes

  \begin{center}
  @{text "\<forall>{x}. x \<rightarrow> y  = \<forall>{x, z}. x \<rightarrow> y"} 
  \end{center}
  
  \noindent
  are not just alpha-equal, but actually \emph{equal}! As a result, we can
  only support specifications that make sense on the level of alpha-equated
  terms (offending specifications, which for example bind a variable according
  to a variable bound somewhere else, are not excluded by Ott, but we have
  to).  

  Our insistence on reasoning with alpha-equated terms comes from the
  wealth of experience we gained with the older version of Nominal Isabelle:
  for non-trivial properties, reasoning about alpha-equated terms is much
  easier than reasoning with raw terms. The fundamental reason for this is
  that the HOL-logic underlying Nominal Isabelle allows us to replace
  ``equals-by-equals''. In contrast, replacing
  ``alpha-equals-by-alpha-equals'' in a representation based on raw terms
  requires a lot of extra reasoning work.

  Although in informal settings a reasoning infrastructure for alpha-equated
  terms is nearly always taken for granted, establishing it automatically in
  the Isabelle/HOL theorem prover is a rather non-trivial task. For every
  specification we will need to construct a type containing as elements the
  alpha-equated terms. To do so, we use the standard HOL-technique of defining
  a new type by identifying a non-empty subset of an existing type.  The
  construction we perform in Isabelle/HOL can be illustrated by the following picture:

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tikzpicture}
  %\draw[step=2mm] (-4,-1) grid (4,1);
  
  \draw[very thick] (0.7,0.4) circle (4.25mm);
  \draw[rounded corners=1mm, very thick] ( 0.0,-0.8) rectangle ( 1.8, 0.9);
  \draw[rounded corners=1mm, very thick] (-1.95,0.85) rectangle (-2.85,-0.05);
  
  \draw (-2.0, 0.845) --  (0.7,0.845);
  \draw (-2.0,-0.045)  -- (0.7,-0.045);

  \draw ( 0.7, 0.4) node {\begin{tabular}{@ {}c@ {}}$\alpha$-\\[-1mm]clas.\end{tabular}};
  \draw (-2.4, 0.4) node {\begin{tabular}{@ {}c@ {}}$\alpha$-eq.\\[-1mm]terms\end{tabular}};
  \draw (1.8, 0.48) node[right=-0.1mm]
    {\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}}existing\\[-1mm] type\\ (sets of raw terms)\end{tabular}};
  \draw (0.9, -0.35) node {\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}}non-empty\\[-1mm]subset\end{tabular}};
  \draw (-3.25, 0.55) node {\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}}new\\[-1mm]type\end{tabular}};
  
  \draw[<->, very thick] (-1.8, 0.3) -- (-0.1,0.3);
  \draw (-0.95, 0.3) node[above=0mm] {isomorphism};

  \end{tikzpicture}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  We take as the starting point a definition of raw terms (defined as a
  datatype in Isabelle/HOL); identify then the alpha-equivalence classes in
  the type of sets of raw terms according to our alpha-equivalence relation
  and finally define the new type as these alpha-equivalence classes
  (non-emptiness is satisfied whenever the raw terms are definable as datatype
  in Isabelle/HOL and the property that our relation for alpha-equivalence is
  indeed an equivalence relation).

  The fact that we obtain an isomorphism between the new type and the
  non-empty subset shows that the new type is a faithful representation of
  alpha-equated terms. That is not the case for example for terms using the
  locally nameless representation of binders \cite{McKinnaPollack99}: in this
  representation there are ``junk'' terms that need to be excluded by
  reasoning about a well-formedness predicate.

  The problem with introducing a new type in Isabelle/HOL is that in order to
  be useful, a reasoning infrastructure needs to be ``lifted'' from the
  underlying subset to the new type. This is usually a tricky and arduous
  task. To ease it, we re-implemented in Isabelle/HOL the quotient package
  described by Homeier \cite{Homeier05} for the HOL4 system. This package
  allows us to lift definitions and theorems involving raw terms to
  definitions and theorems involving alpha-equated terms. For example if we
  define the free-variable function over raw lambda-terms

  \begin{center}
  @{text "fv(x) = {x}"}\hspace{10mm}
  @{text "fv(t\<^isub>1 t\<^isub>2) = fv(t\<^isub>1) \<union> fv(t\<^isub>2)"}\\[1mm]
  @{text "fv(\<lambda>x.t) = fv(t) - {x}"}
  \end{center}
  
  \noindent
  then with the help of the quotient package we can obtain a function @{text "fv\<^sup>\<alpha>"}
  operating on quotients, or alpha-equivalence classes of lambda-terms. This
  lifted function is characterised by the equations

  \begin{center}
  @{text "fv\<^sup>\<alpha>(x) = {x}"}\hspace{10mm}
  @{text "fv\<^sup>\<alpha>(t\<^isub>1 t\<^isub>2) = fv\<^sup>\<alpha>(t\<^isub>1) \<union> fv\<^sup>\<alpha>(t\<^isub>2)"}\\[1mm]
  @{text "fv\<^sup>\<alpha>(\<lambda>x.t) = fv\<^sup>\<alpha>(t) - {x}"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  (Note that this means also the term-constructors for variables, applications
  and lambda are lifted to the quotient level.)  This construction, of course,
  only works if alpha-equivalence is indeed an equivalence relation, and the
  lifted definitions and theorems are respectful w.r.t.~alpha-equivalence.
  For example, we will not be able to lift a bound-variable function. Although
  this function can be defined for raw terms, it does not respect
  alpha-equivalence and therefore cannot be lifted. To sum up, every lifting
  of theorems to the quotient level needs proofs of some respectfulness
  properties (see \cite{Homeier05}). In the paper we show that we are able to
  automate these proofs and therefore can establish a reasoning infrastructure
  for alpha-equated terms.

  The examples we have in mind where our reasoning infrastructure will be
  helpful includes the term language of System @{text "F\<^isub>C"}, also
  known as Core-Haskell (see Figure~\ref{corehas}). This term language
  involves patterns that have lists of type-, coercion- and term-variables,
  all of which are bound in @{text "\<CASE>"}-expressions. One
  difficulty is that we do not know in advance how many variables need to
  be bound. Another is that each bound variable comes with a kind or type
  annotation. Representing such binders with single binders and reasoning
  about them in a theorem prover would be a major pain.  \medskip

  \noindent
  {\bf Contributions:}  We provide new definitions for when terms
  involving multiple binders are alpha-equivalent. These definitions are
  inspired by earlier work of Pitts \cite{Pitts04}. By means of automatic
  proofs, we establish a reasoning infrastructure for alpha-equated
  terms, including properties about support, freshness and equality
  conditions for alpha-equated terms. We are also able to derive, at the moment 
  only manually, strong induction principles that 
  have the variable convention already built in.

  \begin{figure}
  \begin{boxedminipage}{\linewidth}
  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{r@ {\hspace{1mm}}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l}
  \multicolumn{3}{@ {}l}{Type Kinds}\\
  @{text "\<kappa>"} & @{text "::="} & @{text "\<star> | \<kappa>\<^isub>1 \<rightarrow> \<kappa>\<^isub>2"}\smallskip\\
  \multicolumn{3}{@ {}l}{Coercion Kinds}\\
  @{text "\<iota>"} & @{text "::="} & @{text "\<sigma>\<^isub>1 \<sim> \<sigma>\<^isub>2"}\smallskip\\
  \multicolumn{3}{@ {}l}{Types}\\
  @{text "\<sigma>"} & @{text "::="} & @{text "a | T | \<sigma>\<^isub>1 \<sigma>\<^isub>2 | S\<^isub>n"}$\;\overline{@{text "\<sigma>"}}$@{text "\<^sup>n"} 
  @{text "| \<forall>a:\<kappa>. \<sigma> | \<iota> \<Rightarrow> \<sigma>"}\smallskip\\
  \multicolumn{3}{@ {}l}{Coercion Types}\\
  @{text "\<gamma>"} & @{text "::="} & @{text "c | C | \<gamma>\<^isub>1 \<gamma>\<^isub>2 | S\<^isub>n"}$\;\overline{@{text "\<gamma>"}}$@{text "\<^sup>n"}
  @{text "| \<forall>c:\<iota>. \<gamma> | \<iota> \<Rightarrow> \<gamma> "}\\
  & @{text "|"} & @{text "refl \<sigma> | sym \<gamma> | \<gamma>\<^isub>1 \<circ> \<gamma>\<^isub>2 | \<gamma> @ \<sigma> | left \<gamma> | right \<gamma>"}\\
  & @{text "|"} & @{text "\<gamma>\<^isub>1 \<sim> \<gamma>\<^isub>2 | rightc \<gamma> | leftc \<gamma> | \<gamma>\<^isub>1 \<triangleright> \<gamma>\<^isub>2"}\smallskip\\
  \multicolumn{3}{@ {}l}{Terms}\\
  @{text "e"} & @{text "::="} & @{text "x | K | \<Lambda>a:\<kappa>. e | \<Lambda>c:\<iota>. e | e \<sigma> | e \<gamma>"}\\
  & @{text "|"} & @{text "\<lambda>x:\<sigma>. e | e\<^isub>1 e\<^isub>2 | \<LET> x:\<sigma> = e\<^isub>1 \<IN> e\<^isub>2"}\\
  & @{text "|"} & @{text "\<CASE> e\<^isub>1 \<OF>"}$\;\overline{@{text "p \<rightarrow> e\<^isub>2"}}$ @{text "| e \<triangleright> \<gamma>"}\smallskip\\
  \multicolumn{3}{@ {}l}{Patterns}\\
  @{text "p"} & @{text "::="} & @{text "K"}$\;\overline{@{text "a:\<kappa>"}}\;\overline{@{text "c:\<iota>"}}\;\overline{@{text "x:\<sigma>"}}$\smallskip\\
  \multicolumn{3}{@ {}l}{Constants}\\
  & @{text C} & coercion constants\\
  & @{text T} & value type constructors\\
  & @{text "S\<^isub>n"} & n-ary type functions (which need to be fully applied)\\
  & @{text K} & data constructors\smallskip\\
  \multicolumn{3}{@ {}l}{Variables}\\
  & @{text a} & type variables\\
  & @{text c} & coercion variables\\
  & @{text x} & term variables\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}
  \end{boxedminipage}
  \caption{The term-language of System @{text "F\<^isub>C"}
  \cite{CoreHaskell}, also often referred to as \emph{Core-Haskell}. In this
  version of the term-language we made a modification by separating the
  grammars for type kinds and coercion kinds, as well as for types and coercion
  types. For this paper the interesting term-constructor is @{text "\<CASE>"},
  which binds multiple type-, coercion- and term-variables.\label{corehas}}
  \end{figure}
*}

section {* A Short Review of the Nominal Logic Work *}

text {*
  At its core, Nominal Isabelle is an adaption of the nominal logic work by
  Pitts \cite{Pitts03}. This adaptation for Isabelle/HOL is described in
  \cite{HuffmanUrban10} (including proofs). We shall briefly review this work
  to aid the description of what follows. 

  Two central notions in the nominal logic work are sorted atoms and
  sort-respecting permutations of atoms. We will use the letters @{text "a,
  b, c, \<dots>"} to stand for atoms and @{text "p, q, \<dots>"} to stand for
  permutations.  The sorts of atoms can be used to represent different kinds of
  variables, such as the term-, coercion- and type-variables in Core-Haskell.
  It is assumed that there is an infinite supply of atoms for each
  sort. However, in order to simplify the description, we shall restrict ourselves 
  in what follows to only one sort of atoms.

  Permutations are bijective functions from atoms to atoms that are 
  the identity everywhere except on a finite number of atoms. There is a 
  two-place permutation operation written
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "_ \<bullet> _  ::  perm \<Rightarrow> \<beta> \<Rightarrow> \<beta>"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent 
  in which the generic type @{text "\<beta>"} stands for the type of the object 
  over which the permutation 
  acts. In Nominal Isabelle, the identity permutation is written as @{term "0::perm"},
  the composition of two permutations @{term p} and @{term q} as \mbox{@{term "p + q"}}, 
  and the inverse permutation of @{term p} as @{text "- p"}. The permutation
  operation is defined by induction over the type-hierarchy (see \cite{HuffmanUrban10});
  for example permutations acting on products, lists, sets, functions and booleans is
  given by:
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{permute}
  \mbox{\begin{tabular}{@ {}cc@ {}}
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}}
  @{thm permute_prod.simps[no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]}\\[2mm]
  @{thm permute_list.simps(1)[no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]}\\
  @{thm permute_list.simps(2)[no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]}\\
  \end{tabular} &
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}}
  @{thm permute_set_eq[no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]}\\
  @{text "p \<bullet> f \<equiv> \<lambda>x. p \<bullet> (f (- p \<bullet> x))"}\\
  @{thm permute_bool_def[no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]}\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{tabular}}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  Concrete permutations in Nominal Isabelle are built up from swappings, 
  written as \mbox{@{text "(a b)"}}, which are permutations that behave 
  as follows:
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "(a b) = \<lambda>c. if a = c then b else if b = c then a else c"}
  \end{center}

  The most original aspect of the nominal logic work of Pitts is a general
  definition for the notion of the ``set of free variables of an object @{text
  "x"}''.  This notion, written @{term "supp x"}, is general in the sense that
  it applies not only to lambda-terms (alpha-equated or not), but also to lists,
  products, sets and even functions. The definition depends only on the
  permutation operation and on the notion of equality defined for the type of
  @{text x}, namely:
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{suppdef}
  @{thm supp_def[no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  There is also the derived notion for when an atom @{text a} is \emph{fresh}
  for an @{text x}, defined as
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{thm fresh_def[no_vars]}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  We also use for sets of atoms the abbreviation 
  @{thm (lhs) fresh_star_def[no_vars]}, defined as 
  @{thm (rhs) fresh_star_def[no_vars]}.
  A striking consequence of these definitions is that we can prove
  without knowing anything about the structure of @{term x} that
  swapping two fresh atoms, say @{text a} and @{text b}, leave 
  @{text x} unchanged. 

  \begin{property}\label{swapfreshfresh}
  @{thm[mode=IfThen] swap_fresh_fresh[no_vars]}
  \end{property}

  While often the support of an object can be relatively easily 
  described, for example for atoms, products, lists, function applications, 
  booleans and permutations as follows\\[-6mm]
  %
  \begin{eqnarray}
  @{term "supp a"} & = & @{term "{a}"}\\
  @{term "supp (x, y)"} & = & @{term "supp x \<union> supp y"}\\
  @{term "supp []"} & = & @{term "{}"}\\
  @{term "supp (x#xs)"} & = & @{term "supp x \<union> supp xs"}\\
  @{text "supp (f x)"} & @{text "\<subseteq>"} & @{term "supp f \<union> supp x"}\label{suppfun}\\
  @{term "supp b"} & = & @{term "{}"}\\
  @{term "supp p"} & = & @{term "{a. p \<bullet> a \<noteq> a}"}
  \end{eqnarray}
  
  \noindent 
  in some cases it can be difficult to characterise the support precisely, and
  only an approximation can be established (see \eqref{suppfun} above). Reasoning about
  such approximations can be simplified with the notion \emph{supports}, defined 
  as follows:

  \begin{defn}
  A set @{text S} \emph{supports} @{text x} if for all atoms @{text a} and @{text b}
  not in @{text S} we have @{term "(a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> x = x"}.
  \end{defn}

  \noindent
  The main point of @{text supports} is that we can establish the following 
  two properties.

  \begin{property}\label{supportsprop}
  {\it i)} @{thm[mode=IfThen] supp_is_subset[no_vars]}\\ 
  {\it ii)} @{thm supp_supports[no_vars]}.
  \end{property}

  Another important notion in the nominal logic work is \emph{equivariance}.
  For a function @{text f}, say of type @{text "\<alpha> \<Rightarrow> \<beta>"}, to be equivariant 
  it is required that every permutation leaves @{text f} unchanged, that is
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{equivariancedef}
  @{term "\<forall>p. p \<bullet> f = f"}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent or equivalently that a permutation applied to the application
  @{text "f x"} can be moved to the argument @{text x}. That means for equivariant
  functions @{text f} we have for all permutations @{text p}
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{equivariance}
  @{text "p \<bullet> f = f"} \;\;\;\textit{if and only if}\;\;\;
  @{text "p \<bullet> (f x) = f (p \<bullet> x)"}
  \end{equation}
 
  \noindent
  From property \eqref{equivariancedef} and the definition of @{text supp}, we 
  can be easily deduce that equivariant functions have empty support.

  Finally, the nominal logic work provides us with convenient means to rename 
  binders. While in the older version of Nominal Isabelle, we used extensively 
  Property~\ref{swapfreshfresh} for renaming single binders, this property 
  proved unwieldy for dealing with multiple binders. For such binders the 
  following generalisations turned out to be easier to use.

  \begin{property}\label{supppermeq}
  @{thm[mode=IfThen] supp_perm_eq[no_vars]}
  \end{property}

  \begin{property}\label{avoiding}
  For a finite set @{text as} and a finitely supported @{text x} with
  @{term "as \<sharp>* x"} and also a finitely supported @{text c}, there
  exists a permutation @{text p} such that @{term "(p \<bullet> as) \<sharp>* c"} and
  @{term "supp x \<sharp>* p"}.
  \end{property}

  \noindent
  The idea behind the second property is that given a finite set @{text as}
  of binders (being bound, or fresh, in @{text x} is ensured by the
  assumption @{term "as \<sharp>* x"}), then there exists a permutation @{text p} such that
  the renamed binders @{term "p \<bullet> as"} avoid @{text c} (which can be arbitrarily chosen
  as long as it is finitely supported) and also @{text "p"} does not affect anything
  in the support of @{text x} (that is @{term "supp x \<sharp>* p"}). The last 
  fact and Property~\ref{supppermeq} allow us to ``rename'' just the binders 
  @{text as} in @{text x}, because @{term "p \<bullet> x = x"}.

  Most properties given in this section are described in \cite{HuffmanUrban10}
  and of course all are formalised in Isabelle/HOL. In the next sections we will make 
  extensively use of these properties in order to define alpha-equivalence in 
  the presence of multiple binders.
*}


section {* General Binders\label{sec:binders} *}

text {*
  In Nominal Isabelle, the user is expected to write down a specification of a
  term-calculus and then a reasoning infrastructure is automatically derived
  from this specification (remember that Nominal Isabelle is a definitional
  extension of Isabelle/HOL, which does not introduce any new axioms).

  In order to keep our work with deriving the reasoning infrastructure
  manageable, we will wherever possible state definitions and perform proofs
  on the user-level of Isabelle/HOL, as opposed to write custom ML-code that
  generates them anew for each specification. To that end, we will consider
  first pairs @{text "(as, x)"} of type @{text "(atom set) \<times> \<beta>"}.  These pairs
  are intended to represent the abstraction, or binding, of the set @{text
  "as"} in the body @{text "x"}.

  The first question we have to answer is when two pairs @{text "(as, x)"} and
  @{text "(bs, y)"} are alpha-equivalent? (At the moment we are interested in
  the notion of alpha-equivalence that is \emph{not} preserved by adding
  vacuous binders.) To answer this, we identify four conditions: {\it i)}
  given a free-variable function @{text "fv"} of type \mbox{@{text "\<beta> \<Rightarrow> atom
  set"}}, then @{text x} and @{text y} need to have the same set of free
  variables; moreover there must be a permutation @{text p} such that {\it
  ii)} @{text p} leaves the free variables of @{text x} and @{text y} unchanged, but
  {\it iii)} ``moves'' their bound names so that we obtain modulo a relation,
  say \mbox{@{text "_ R _"}}, two equivalent terms. We also require {\it iv)} that
  @{text p} makes the sets of abstracted atoms @{text as} and @{text bs} equal. The
  requirements {\it i)} to {\it iv)} can be stated formally as follows:
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{alphaset}
  \begin{array}{@ {\hspace{10mm}}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l}
  \multicolumn{2}{l}{@{term "(as, x) \<approx>gen R fv p (bs, y)"}\hspace{2mm}@{text "\<equiv>"}\hspace{30mm}}\\[1mm]
               & @{term "fv(x) - as = fv(y) - bs"}\\
  @{text "\<and>"} & @{term "(fv(x) - as) \<sharp>* p"}\\
  @{text "\<and>"} & @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"}\\
  @{text "\<and>"} & @{term "(p \<bullet> as) = bs"}\\ 
  \end{array}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  Note that this relation is dependent on the permutation @{text
  "p"}. Alpha-equivalence between two pairs is then the relation where we
  existentially quantify over this @{text "p"}. Also note that the relation is
  dependent on a free-variable function @{text "fv"} and a relation @{text
  "R"}. The reason for this extra generality is that we will use
  $\approx_{\textit{set}}$ for both ``raw'' terms and alpha-equated terms. In
  the latter case, $R$ will be replaced by equality @{text "="} and we
  will prove that @{text "fv"} is equal to @{text "supp"}.

  The definition in \eqref{alphaset} does not make any distinction between the
  order of abstracted variables. If we want this, then we can define alpha-equivalence 
  for pairs of the form \mbox{@{text "(as, x)"}} with type @{text "(atom list) \<times> \<beta>"} 
  as follows
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{alphalist}
  \begin{array}{@ {\hspace{10mm}}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l}
  \multicolumn{2}{l}{@{term "(as, x) \<approx>lst R fv p (bs, y)"}\hspace{2mm}@{text "\<equiv>"}\hspace{30mm}}\\[1mm]
             & @{term "fv(x) - (set as) = fv(y) - (set bs)"}\\
  \wedge     & @{term "(fv(x) - set as) \<sharp>* p"}\\
  \wedge     & @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"}\\
  \wedge     & @{term "(p \<bullet> as) = bs"}\\ 
  \end{array}
  \end{equation}
  
  \noindent
  where @{term set} is a function that coerces a list of atoms into a set of atoms.
  Now the last clause ensures that the order of the binders matters (since @{text as}
  and @{text bs} are lists of atoms).

  If we do not want to make any difference between the order of binders \emph{and}
  also allow vacuous binders, then we keep sets of binders, but drop the fourth 
  condition in \eqref{alphaset}:
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{alphares}
  \begin{array}{@ {\hspace{10mm}}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l}
  \multicolumn{2}{l}{@{term "(as, x) \<approx>res R fv p (bs, y)"}\hspace{2mm}@{text "\<equiv>"}\hspace{30mm}}\\[1mm]
             & @{term "fv(x) - as = fv(y) - bs"}\\
  \wedge     & @{term "(fv(x) - as) \<sharp>* p"}\\
  \wedge     & @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"}\\
  \end{array}
  \end{equation}

  It might be useful to consider some examples for how these definitions of alpha-equivalence
  pan out in practise.
  For this consider the case of abstracting a set of variables over types (as in type-schemes). 
  We set @{text R} to be the equality and for @{text "fv(T)"} we define

  \begin{center}
  @{text "fv(x) = {x}"}  \hspace{5mm} @{text "fv(T\<^isub>1 \<rightarrow> T\<^isub>2) = fv(T\<^isub>1) \<union> fv(T\<^isub>2)"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  Now recall the examples shown in \eqref{ex1}, \eqref{ex2} and
  \eqref{ex3}. It can be easily checked that @{text "({x, y}, x \<rightarrow> y)"} and
  @{text "({y, x}, y \<rightarrow> x)"} are alpha-equivalent according to $\approx_{\textit{set}}$ and
  $\approx_{\textit{res}}$ by taking @{text p} to be the swapping @{term "(x \<rightleftharpoons>
  y)"}. In case of @{text "x \<noteq> y"}, then @{text "([x, y], x \<rightarrow> y)"}
  $\not\approx_{\textit{list}}$ @{text "([y, x], x \<rightarrow> y)"} since there is no permutation
  that makes the lists @{text "[x, y]"} and @{text "[y, x]"} equal, and also
  leaves the type \mbox{@{text "x \<rightarrow> y"}} unchanged. Another example is
  @{text "({x}, x)"} $\approx_{\textit{res}}$ @{text "({x, y}, x)"} which holds by 
  taking @{text p} to be the
  identity permutation.  However, if @{text "x \<noteq> y"}, then @{text "({x}, x)"}
  $\not\approx_{\textit{set}}$ @{text "({x, y}, x)"} since there is no permutation 
  that makes the
  sets @{text "{x}"} and @{text "{x, y}"} equal (similarly for $\approx_{\textit{list}}$).
  It can also relatively easily be shown that all tree notions of alpha-equivalence
  coincide, if we only abstract a single atom. 

  % looks too ugly
  %\noindent
  %Let $\star$ range over $\{set, res, list\}$. We prove next under which 
  %conditions the $\approx\hspace{0.05mm}_\star^{\fv, R, p}$ are equivalence 
  %relations and equivariant:
  %
  %\begin{lemma}
  %{\it i)} Given the fact that $x\;R\;x$ holds, then 
  %$(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, 0}_\star (as, x)$. {\it ii)} Given
  %that @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"} implies @{text "(-p \<bullet> y) R x"}, then
  %$(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, p}_\star (bs, y)$ implies
  %$(bs, y) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, - p}_\star (as, x)$. {\it iii)} Given
  %that @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"} and @{text "(q \<bullet> y) R z"} implies 
  %@{text "((q + p) \<bullet> x) R z"}, then $(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, p}_\star (bs, y)$
  %and $(bs, y) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, q}_\star (cs, z)$ implies
  %$(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, q + p}_\star (cs, z)$. Given
  %@{text "(q \<bullet> x) R y"} implies @{text "(p \<bullet> (q \<bullet> x)) R (p \<bullet> y)"} and
  %@{text "p \<bullet> (fv x) = fv (p \<bullet> x)"} then @{text "p \<bullet> (fv y) = fv (p \<bullet> y)"}, then
  %$(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, q}_\star (bs, y)$ implies
  %$(p \;\isasymbullet\; as, p \;\isasymbullet\; x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, q}_\star 
  %(p \;\isasymbullet\; bs, p \;\isasymbullet\; y)$.
  %\end{lemma}
  
  %\begin{proof}
  %All properties are by unfolding the definitions and simple calculations. 
  %\end{proof}


  In the rest of this section we are going to introduce three abstraction 
  types. For this we define 
  %
  \begin{equation}
  @{term "abs_set (as, x) (bs, x) \<equiv> \<exists>p. alpha_gen (as, x) equal supp p (bs, x)"}
  \end{equation}
  
  \noindent
  (similarly for $\approx_{\textit{abs\_list}}$ 
  and $\approx_{\textit{abs\_res}}$). We can show that these relations are equivalence 
  relations and equivariant.

  \begin{lemma}\label{alphaeq} 
  The relations $\approx_{\textit{abs\_set}}$, $\approx_{\textit{abs\_list}}$
  and $\approx_{\textit{abs\_res}}$ are equivalence relations, and if @{term
  "abs_set (as, x) (bs, y)"} then also @{term "abs_set (p \<bullet> as, p \<bullet> x) (p \<bullet>
  bs, p \<bullet> y)"} (similarly for the other two relations).
  \end{lemma}

  \begin{proof}
  Reflexivity is by taking @{text "p"} to be @{text "0"}. For symmetry we have
  a permutation @{text p} and for the proof obligation take @{term "-p"}. In case 
  of transitivity, we have two permutations @{text p} and @{text q}, and for the
  proof obligation use @{text "q + p"}. All conditions are then by simple
  calculations. 
  \end{proof}

  \noindent
  This lemma allows us to use our quotient package and introduce 
  new types @{text "\<beta> abs_set"}, @{text "\<beta> abs_res"} and @{text "\<beta> abs_list"}
  representing alpha-equivalence classes of pairs. The elements in these types 
  will be, respectively, written as:

  \begin{center}
  @{term "Abs as x"} \hspace{5mm} 
  @{term "Abs_lst as x"} \hspace{5mm}
  @{term "Abs_res as x"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  indicating that a set (or list) @{text as} is abstracted in @{text x}. We will
  call the types \emph{abstraction types} and their elements
  \emph{abstractions}. The important property we need to derive is the support of 
  abstractions, namely:

  \begin{thm}[Support of Abstractions]\label{suppabs} 
  Assuming @{text x} has finite support, then\\[-6mm] 
  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{l@ {\hspace{2mm}}c@ {\hspace{2mm}}l}
  @{thm (lhs) supp_abs(1)[no_vars]} & $=$ & @{thm (rhs) supp_abs(1)[no_vars]}\\
  @{thm (lhs) supp_abs(2)[no_vars]} & $=$ & @{thm (rhs) supp_abs(2)[no_vars]}\\
  @{thm (lhs) supp_abs(3)[where bs="as", no_vars]} & $=$ & @{thm (rhs) supp_abs(3)[where bs="as", no_vars]}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}
  \end{thm}

  \noindent
  Below we will show the first equation. The others 
  follow by similar arguments. By definition of the abstraction type @{text "abs_set"} 
  we have 
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{abseqiff}
  @{thm (lhs) abs_eq_iff(1)[where bs="as" and cs="bs", no_vars]} \;\;\text{if and only if}\;\; 
  @{thm (rhs) abs_eq_iff(1)[where bs="as" and cs="bs", no_vars]}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  and also
  %
  \begin{equation}
  @{thm permute_Abs[no_vars]}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  The second fact derives from the definition of permutations acting on pairs 
  (see \eqref{permute}) and alpha-equivalence being equivariant 
  (see Lemma~\ref{alphaeq}). With these two facts at our disposal, we can show 
  the following lemma about swapping two atoms.
  
  \begin{lemma}
  @{thm[mode=IfThen] abs_swap1(1)[where bs="as", no_vars]}
  \end{lemma}

  \begin{proof}
  This lemma is straightforward using \eqref{abseqiff} and observing that
  the assumptions give us @{term "(a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> (supp x - as) = (supp x - as)"}.
  Moreover @{text supp} and set difference are equivariant (see \cite{HuffmanUrban10}).
  \end{proof}

  \noindent
  This lemma allows us to show
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{halfone}
  @{thm abs_supports(1)[no_vars]}
  \end{equation}
  
  \noindent
  which by Property~\ref{supportsprop} gives us ``one half'' of
  Theorem~\ref{suppabs}. The ``other half'' is a bit more involved. To establish 
  it, we use a trick from \cite{Pitts04} and first define an auxiliary 
  function @{text aux}, taking an abstraction as argument:
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{thm supp_gen.simps[THEN eq_reflection, no_vars]}
  \end{center}
  
  \noindent
  Using the second equation in \eqref{equivariance}, we can show that 
  @{text "aux"} is equivariant (since @{term "p \<bullet> (supp x - as) =
  (supp (p \<bullet> x)) - (p \<bullet> as)"}) and therefore has empty support. 
  This in turn means
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{term "supp (supp_gen (Abs as x)) \<subseteq> supp (Abs as x)"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  using \eqref{suppfun}. Assuming @{term "supp x - as"} is a finite set
  we further obtain
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{halftwo}
  @{thm (concl) supp_abs_subset1(1)[no_vars]}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  since for finite sets of atoms, @{text "bs"}, we have 
  @{thm (concl) supp_finite_atom_set[where S="bs", no_vars]}.
  Finally, taking \eqref{halfone} and \eqref{halftwo} together establishes 
  Theorem~\ref{suppabs}. 

  The method of first considering abstractions of the
  form @{term "Abs as x"} etc is motivated by the fact that properties about them
  can be conveninetly established at the Isabelle/HOL level.  It would be
  difficult to write custom ML-code that derives automatically such properties 
  for every term-constructor that binds some atoms. Also the generality of
  the definitions for alpha-equivalence will help us in definitions in the next section.
*}

section {* Alpha-Equivalence and Free Variables\label{sec:alpha} *}

text {*
  Our choice of syntax for specifications is influenced by the existing
  datatype package of Isabelle/HOL \cite{Berghofer99} and by the syntax of the
  Ott-tool \cite{ott-jfp}. For us a specification of a term-calculus is a
  collection of (possibly mutual recursive) type declarations, say @{text
  "ty\<AL>\<^isub>1, \<dots>, ty\<AL>\<^isub>n"}, and an associated collection of
  binding functions, say @{text "bn\<AL>\<^isub>1, \<dots>, bn\<AL>\<^isub>m"}. The
  syntax in Nominal Isabelle for such specifications is roughly as follows:
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{scheme}
  \mbox{\begin{tabular}{@ {\hspace{-5mm}}p{1.8cm}l}
  type \mbox{declaration part} &
  $\begin{cases}
  \mbox{\begin{tabular}{l}
  \isacommand{nominal\_datatype} @{text "ty\<AL>\<^isub>1 = \<dots>"}\\
  \isacommand{and} @{text "ty\<AL>\<^isub>2 = \<dots>"}\\
  $\ldots$\\ 
  \isacommand{and} @{text "ty\<AL>\<^isub>n = \<dots>"}\\ 
  \end{tabular}}
  \end{cases}$\\
  binding \mbox{function part} &
  $\begin{cases}
  \mbox{\begin{tabular}{l}
  \isacommand{with} @{text "bn\<AL>\<^isub>1"} \isacommand{and} \ldots \isacommand{and} @{text "bn\<AL>\<^isub>m"}\\
  \isacommand{where}\\
  $\ldots$\\
  \end{tabular}}
  \end{cases}$\\
  \end{tabular}}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  Every type declaration @{text ty}$^\alpha_{1..n}$ consists of a collection of 
  term-constructors, each of which come with a list of labelled 
  types that stand for the types of the arguments of the term-constructor.
  For example a term-constructor @{text "C\<^sup>\<alpha>"} might be specified with

  \begin{center}
  @{text "C\<^sup>\<alpha> label\<^isub>1::ty"}$'_1$ @{text "\<dots> label\<^isub>l::ty"}$'_l\;\;$  @{text "binding_clauses"} 
  \end{center}
  
  \noindent
  whereby some of the @{text ty}$'_{1..l}$ (or their components) might be contained
  in the collection of @{text ty}$^\alpha_{1..n}$ declared in
  \eqref{scheme}. 
  In this case we will call the corresponding argument a
  \emph{recursive argument} of @{text "C\<^sup>\<alpha>"}. 
  %The types of such recursive 
  %arguments need to satisfy a  ``positivity''
  %restriction, which ensures that the type has a set-theoretic semantics 
  %\cite{Berghofer99}.  
  The labels
  annotated on the types are optional. Their purpose is to be used in the
  (possibly empty) list of \emph{binding clauses}, which indicate the binders
  and their scope in a term-constructor.  They come in three \emph{modes}:

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{l}
  \isacommand{bind}\; {\it binders}\; \isacommand{in}\; {\it label}\\
  \isacommand{bind\_set}\; {\it binders}\; \isacommand{in}\; {\it label}\\
  \isacommand{bind\_res}\; {\it binders}\; \isacommand{in}\; {\it label}\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  The first mode is for binding lists of atoms (the order of binders matters);
  the second is for sets of binders (the order does not matter, but the
  cardinality does) and the last is for sets of binders (with vacuous binders
  preserving alpha-equivalence). The ``\isacommand{in}-part'' of a binding
  clause will be called the \emph{body}; the ``\isacommand{bind}-part'' will
  be called the \emph{binder}.

  In addition we distinguish between \emph{shallow} and \emph{deep}
  binders.  Shallow binders are of the form \isacommand{bind}\; {\it label}\;
  \isacommand{in}\; {\it label'} (similar for the other two modes). The
  restriction we impose on shallow binders is that the {\it label} must either
  refer to a type that is an atom type or to a type that is a finite set or
  list of an atom type. Two examples for the use of shallow binders are the
  specification of lambda-terms, where a single name is bound, and 
  type-schemes, where a finite set of names is bound:

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}cc@ {}}
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {\hspace{-1mm}}}
  \isacommand{nominal\_datatype} @{text lam} =\\
  \hspace{5mm}\phantom{$\mid$}~@{text "Var name"}\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{text "App lam lam"}\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{text "Lam x::name t::lam"}\\
  \hspace{21mm}\isacommand{bind} @{text x} \isacommand{in} @{text t}\\
  \end{tabular} &
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}}
  \isacommand{nominal\_datatype}~@{text ty} =\\
  \hspace{5mm}\phantom{$\mid$}~@{text "TVar name"}\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{text "TFun ty ty"}\\
  \isacommand{and}~@{text "tsc = All xs::(name fset) T::ty"}\\
  \hspace{24mm}\isacommand{bind\_res} @{text xs} \isacommand{in} @{text T}\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  Note that in this specification \emph{name} refers to an atom type.
  If we have shallow binders that ``share'' a body, for instance $t$ in
  the following term-constructor

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{ll}
  @{text "Foo x::name y::name t::lam"} &  
      \isacommand{bind} @{text x} \isacommand{in} @{text t},\;
      \isacommand{bind} @{text y} \isacommand{in} @{text t}  
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  then we have to make sure the modes of the binders agree. We cannot
  have, for instance, in the first binding clause the mode \isacommand{bind} 
  and in the second \isacommand{bind\_set}.

  A \emph{deep} binder uses an auxiliary binding function that ``picks'' out
  the atoms in one argument of the term-constructor, which can be bound in  
  other arguments and also in the same argument (we will
  call such binders \emph{recursive}, see below). 
  The corresponding binding functions are expected to return either a set of atoms
  (for \isacommand{bind\_set} and \isacommand{bind\_res}) or a list of atoms
  (for \isacommand{bind}). They can be defined by primitive recursion over the
  corresponding type; the equations must be given in the binding function part of
  the scheme shown in \eqref{scheme}. For example a term-calculus containing @{text "Let"}s 
  with tuple patterns might be specified as:
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{letpat}
  \mbox{%
  \begin{tabular}{l}
  \isacommand{nominal\_datatype} @{text trm} =\\
  \hspace{5mm}\phantom{$\mid$}~@{term "Var name"}\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{term "App trm trm"}\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{text "Lam x::name t::trm"} 
     \;\;\isacommand{bind} @{text x} \isacommand{in} @{text t}\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{text "Let p::pat trm t::trm"} 
     \;\;\isacommand{bind} @{text "bn(p)"} \isacommand{in} @{text t}\\
  \isacommand{and} @{text pat} =\\
  \hspace{5mm}\phantom{$\mid$}~@{text PNil}\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{text "PVar name"}\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{text "PTup pat pat"}\\ 
  \isacommand{with}~@{text "bn::pat \<Rightarrow> atom list"}\\
  \isacommand{where}~@{text "bn(PNil) = []"}\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{text "bn(PVar x) = [atom x]"}\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{text "bn(PTup p\<^isub>1 p\<^isub>2) = bn(p\<^isub>1) @ bn(p\<^isub>2)"}\\ 
  \end{tabular}}
  \end{equation}
  
  \noindent
  In this specification the function @{text "bn"} determines which atoms of @{text  p} are
  bound in the argument @{text "t"}. Note that in the second-last clause the function @{text "atom"}
  coerces a name into the generic atom type of Nominal Isabelle \cite{HuffmanUrban10}. This allows
  us to treat binders of different atom type uniformly. 

  As will shortly become clear, we cannot return an atom in a binding function
  that is also bound in the corresponding term-constructor. That means in the
  example above that the term-constructors @{text PVar} and @{text PTup} must not have a
  binding clause.  In the version of Nominal Isabelle described here, we also adopted
  the restriction from the Ott-tool that binding functions can only return:
  the empty set or empty list (as in case @{text PNil}), a singleton set or singleton
  list containing an atom (case @{text PVar}), or unions of atom sets or appended atom
  lists (case @{text PTup}). This restriction will simplify definitions and 
  proofs later on.
  
  The most drastic restriction we have to impose on deep binders is that 
  we cannot have ``overlapping'' deep binders. Consider for example the 
  term-constructors:

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{ll}
  @{text "Foo p::pat q::pat t::trm"} & 
     \isacommand{bind} @{text "bn(p)"} \isacommand{in} @{text t},\;
     \isacommand{bind} @{text "bn(q)"} \isacommand{in} @{text t}\\
  @{text "Foo' x::name p::pat t::trm"} & 
     \isacommand{bind} @{text x} \isacommand{in} @{text t},\;
     \isacommand{bind} @{text "bn(p)"} \isacommand{in} @{text t} 
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  In the first case we might bind all atoms from the pattern @{text p} in @{text t}
  and also all atoms from @{text q} in @{text t}. As a result we have no way
  to determine whether the binder came from the binding function @{text
  "bn(p)"} or @{text "bn(q)"}. Similarly in the second case. The reason why
  we must exclude such specifications is that they cannot be represent by
  the general binders described in Section \ref{sec:binders}. However
  the following two term-constructors are allowed

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{ll}
  @{text "Bar p::pat t::trm s::trm"} & 
     \isacommand{bind} @{text "bn(p)"} \isacommand{in} @{text t},\;
     \isacommand{bind} @{text "bn(p)"} \isacommand{in} @{text s}\\
  @{text "Bar' p::pat t::trm"} &  
     \isacommand{bind} @{text "bn(p)"} \isacommand{in} @{text p},\;
     \isacommand{bind} @{text "bn(p)"} \isacommand{in} @{text t}\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  since there is no overlap of binders.
  
  Note that in the last example we wrote {\it\isacommand{bind}\;bn(p)\;\isacommand{in}\;p}.
  Whenever such a binding clause is present, we will call the corresponding binder \emph{recursive}.
  To see the purpose of such recursive binders, compare ``plain'' @{text "Let"}s and @{text "Let_rec"}s
  in the following specification:
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{letrecs}
  \mbox{%
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}}
  \isacommand{nominal\_datatype}~@{text "trm ="}\\
  \hspace{5mm}\phantom{$\mid$}\ldots\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{text "Let as::assn t::trm"} 
     \;\;\isacommand{bind} @{text "bn(as)"} \isacommand{in} @{text t}\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{text "Let_rec as::assn t::trm"}\\ 
  \hspace{20mm}\isacommand{bind} @{text "bn(as)"} \isacommand{in} @{text t},
         \isacommand{bind} @{text "bn(as)"} \isacommand{in} @{text as}\\
  \isacommand{and} {\it assn} =\\
  \hspace{5mm}\phantom{$\mid$}~@{text "ANil"}\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{text "ACons name trm assn"}\\
  \isacommand{with} @{text "bn::assn \<Rightarrow> atom list"}\\
  \isacommand{where}~@{text "bn(ANil) = []"}\\
  \hspace{5mm}$\mid$~@{text "bn(ACons a t as) = [atom a] @ bn(as)"}\\
  \end{tabular}}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  The difference is that with @{text Let} we only want to bind the atoms @{text
  "bn(as)"} in the term @{text t}, but with @{text "Let_rec"} we also want to bind the atoms
  inside the assignment. This difference has consequences for the free-variable 
  function and alpha-equivalence relation, which we are going to describe in the 
  rest of this section.
 
  Having dealt with all syntax matters, the problem now is how we can turn
  specifications into actual type definitions in Isabelle/HOL and then
  establish a reasoning infrastructure for them. Because of the problem
  Pottier and Cheney pointed out, we cannot in general re-arrange arguments of
  term-constructors so that binders and their bodies are next to each other, and
  then use the type constructors @{text "abs_set"}, @{text "abs_res"} and
  @{text "abs_list"} from Section \ref{sec:binders}. Therefore we will first
  extract datatype definitions from the specification and then define 
  expicitly an alpha-equivalence relation over them.


  The datatype definition can be obtained by stripping off the 
  binding clauses and the labels on the types. We also have to invent
  new names for the types @{text "ty\<^sup>\<alpha>"} and term-constructors @{text "C\<^sup>\<alpha>"}
  given by the user. In our implementation we just use the affix ``@{text "_raw"}''.
  But for the purpose of this paper, we just use the superscript @{text "_\<^sup>\<alpha>"} to indicate 
  that a notion is defined over alpha-equivalence classes and leave it out 
  for the corresponding notion defined on the ``raw'' level. So for example 
  we have
  
  \begin{center}
  @{text "ty\<^sup>\<alpha> \<mapsto> ty"} \hspace{2mm}and\hspace{2mm} @{text "C\<^sup>\<alpha> \<mapsto> C"}
  \end{center}
  
  \noindent
  where @{term ty} is the type used in the quotient construction for 
  @{text "ty\<^sup>\<alpha>"} and @{text "C"} is the term-constructor on the ``raw'' type @{text "ty"}. 

  The resulting datatype definition is legal in Isabelle/HOL provided the datatypes are 
  non-empty and the types in the constructors only occur in positive 
  position (see \cite{Berghofer99} for an indepth description of the datatype package
  in Isabelle/HOL). We then define the user-specified binding 
  functions, called @{term "bn"}, by primitive recursion over the corresponding 
  raw datatype. We can also easily define permutation operations by 
  primitive recursion so that for each term constructor @{text "C ty\<^isub>1 \<dots> ty\<^isub>n"} 
  we have that
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{ceqvt}
  @{text "p \<bullet> (C x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>n) = C (p \<bullet> x\<^isub>1) \<dots> (p \<bullet> x\<^isub>n)"}
  \end{equation}
  
  % TODO: we did not define permutation types
  %\noindent
  %From this definition we can easily show that the raw datatypes are 
  %all permutation types (Def ??) by a simple structural induction over
  %the @{text "ty"}s.

  The first non-trivial step we have to perform is the generation free-variable 
  functions from the specifications. Given the raw types @{text "ty\<^isub>1 \<dots> ty\<^isub>n"}
  we need to define free-variable functions

  \begin{center}
  @{text "fv_ty\<^isub>1, \<dots>, fv_ty\<^isub>n"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  We define them together with auxiliary free-variable functions for
  the binding functions. Given binding functions 
  @{text "bn\<^isub>1 \<dots> bn\<^isub>m"} we need to define
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "fv_bn\<^isub>1, \<dots>, fv_bn\<^isub>m"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  The reason for this setup is that in a deep binder not all atoms have to be
  bound, as we shall see in an example below. We need therefore a function
  that calculates those unbound atoms. 

  While the idea behind these
  free-variable functions is clear (they just collect all atoms that are not bound),
  because of our rather complicated binding mechanisms their definitions are
  somewhat involved.
  Given a term-constructor @{text "C"} of type @{text ty} with argument types
  \mbox{@{text "ty\<^isub>1 \<dots> ty\<^isub>n"}}, the function
  @{text "fv_ty (C x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>n)"} will be the union of the values
  calculated below for each argument. 
  First we deal with the case that @{text "x\<^isub>i"} is a binder. From the binding clauses, 
  we can determine whether the argument is a shallow or deep
  binder, and in the latter case also whether it is a recursive or
  non-recursive binder. 
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{deepbinder}
  \mbox{%
  \begin{tabular}{c@ {\hspace{2mm}}p{7cm}}
  $\bullet$ & @{term "{}"} provided @{text "x\<^isub>i"} is a shallow binder\\
  $\bullet$ & @{text "fv_bn x\<^isub>i"} provided @{text "x\<^isub>i"} is a deep
      non-recursive binder with the auxiliary binding function @{text "bn"}\\
  $\bullet$ & @{text "fv_ty\<^isub>i x\<^isub>i - bn x\<^isub>i"} provided @{text "x\<^isub>i"} is
      a deep recursive binder with the auxiliary binding function @{text "bn"}
  \end{tabular}}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  The first clause states that shallow binders do not contribute to the
  free variables; in the second clause, we have to collect all
  variables that are left unbound by the binding function @{text "bn"}---this
  is done with function @{text "fv_bn"}; in the third clause, since the 
  binder is recursive, we need to bind all variables specified by 
  @{text "bn"}---therefore we subtract @{text "bn x\<^isub>i"} from the free
  variables of @{text "x\<^isub>i"}.

  In case the argument is \emph{not} a binder, we need to consider 
  whether the @{text "x\<^isub>i"} is the body of one or more binding clauses. 
  In this case we first calculate the set @{text "bnds"} as follows: 
  either the corresponding binders are all shallow or there is a single deep binder.
  In the former case we take @{text bnds} to be the union of all shallow 
  binders; in the latter case, we just take the set of atoms specified by the 
  corresponding binding function. The value for @{text "x\<^isub>i"} is then given by:
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{deepbody}
  \mbox{%
  \begin{tabular}{c@ {\hspace{2mm}}p{7cm}}
  $\bullet$ & @{text "{atom x\<^isub>i} - bnds"} provided @{term "x\<^isub>i"} is an atom\\
  $\bullet$ & @{text "(atoms x\<^isub>i) - bnds"} provided @{term "x\<^isub>i"} is a set of atoms\\
  $\bullet$ & @{text "(atoms (set x\<^isub>i)) - bnds"} provided @{term "x\<^isub>i"} is a list of atoms\\
  $\bullet$ & @{text "(fv_ty\<^isub>i x\<^isub>i) - bnds"} provided @{term "ty\<^isub>i"} is one of the raw datatypes
     corresponding to the types specified by the user\\
%  $\bullet$ & @{text "(fv\<^isup>\<alpha> x\<^isub>i) - bnds"} provided @{term "x\<^isub>i"} is a defined nominal datatype
%     with a free-variable function @{text "fv\<^isup>\<alpha>"}\\
  $\bullet$ & @{term "{}"} otherwise
  \end{tabular}}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent 
  Like the coercion function @{text atom} used earlier, @{text "atoms"} coerces 
  the set of atoms to a set of the generic atom type.
  It is defined as @{text "atoms as \<equiv> {atom a | a \<in> as}"}.

  The last case we need to consider is when @{text "x\<^isub>i"} is neither
  a binder nor a body of an abstraction. In this case it is defined 
  as in \eqref{deepbody}, except that we do not need to subtract the 
  set @{text bnds}.

  The definitions of the free-variable functions for binding
  functions are similar. For each binding function
  @{text "bn\<^isub>j"} we need to define a free-variable function
  @{text "fv_bn\<^isub>j"}. Given a term-constructor @{term "C"}, the
  function @{text "fv_bn\<^isub>j(C x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>n)"} is the union of the
  values calculated for the arguments. For each argument @{term "x\<^isub>i"}
  we know whether it appears in the @{term "rhs"} of the binding
  function equation @{text "bn\<^isub>j (C x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>n) = rhs"}. If it does not
  appear in @{text "rhs"} we generate the premise according to the
  rules for @{text "fv_ty"} described above in (\ref{deepbinder}--\ref{deepbody}). Otherwise:

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{c@ {\hspace{2mm}}p{7cm}}
   $\bullet$ & @{text "fv_bn x\<^isub>i"} provided @{text "rhs"} contains the
    recursive call @{text "bn x\<^isub>i"}\medskip\\
  $\bullet$ & @{term "{}"} provided @{text "rhs"} contains
    @{term "x\<^isub>i"} and @{term "x\<^isub>i"} is of atom type.
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  To see how these definitions work in practise, let us reconsider the term-constructors 
  @{text "Let"} and @{text "Let_rec"} from the example shown in \eqref{letrecs}. 
  For this specification we need to define three free-variable functions, namely
  @{text "fv\<^bsub>trm\<^esub>"}, @{text "fv\<^bsub>assn\<^esub>"} and @{text "fv\<^bsub>bn\<^esub>"}. They are as follows:
  %
  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {\hspace{1mm}}c@ {\hspace{1mm}}l@ {}}
  @{text "fv\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> (Let as t)"} & @{text "="} & @{text "fv\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> as \<union> (fv\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> t - set (bn as))"}\\
  @{text "fv\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> (Let_rec as t)"} & @{text "="} &\\
  \multicolumn{3}{r}{@{text "(fv\<^bsub>assn\<^esub> as - set (bn as)) \<union> (fv\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> t - set (bn as))"}}\\[1mm]

  @{text "fv\<^bsub>assn\<^esub> (ANil)"} & @{text "="} & @{text "[]"}\\
  @{text "fv\<^bsub>assn\<^esub> (ACons a t as)"} & @{text "="} & @{text "{atom a} \<union> (fv\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> t) \<union> (fv\<^bsub>assn\<^esub> as)"}\\[1mm]

  @{text "fv\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> (ANil)"} & @{text "="} & @{text "[]"}\\
  @{text "fv\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> (ACons a t as)"} & @{text "="} & @{text "(fv\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> t) \<union> (fv\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> as)"}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  Since there are no binding clauses for the term-constructors @{text ANil}
  and @{text "ACons"}, the corresponding free-variable function @{text
  "fv\<^bsub>assn\<^esub>"} returns all atoms occuring in an assignment. The
  binding only takes place in @{text Let} and @{text "Let_rec"}. In the @{text
  "Let"}-clause we want to bind all atoms given by @{text "set (bn as)"} in
  @{text t}. Therefore we have to subtract @{text "set (bn as)"} from @{text
  "fv\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> t"}. However, we also need to add all atoms that are
  free in @{text "as"}. This is what the purpose of the function @{text
  "fv\<^bsub>bn\<^esub>"} is.  In contrast, in @{text "Let_rec"} we have a
  recursive binder where we want to also bind all occurrences of the atoms
  in @{text "set (bn as)"} inside @{text "as"}. Therefore we have to subtract @{text
  "set (bn as)"} from @{text "fv\<^bsub>assn\<^esub> as"}, as well as from
  @{text "fv\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> t"}. An interesting point in this example is
  that an assignment ``alone'' does not have any bound variables. Only in the
  context of a @{text Let} or @{text "Let_rec"} will some atoms become bound.  
  This is a phenomenon 
  that has also been pointed out in \cite{ott-jfp}. We can also see that
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{bnprop}
  @{text "fv_ty x  =  bn x \<union> fv_bn x"}.
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  holds for any @{text "bn"}-function defined for the type @{text "ty"}.

  Next we define alpha-equivalence relations for the types @{text "ty\<^isub>1, \<dots>, ty\<^isub>n"}. We call them
  @{text "\<approx>ty\<^isub>1, \<dots>, \<approx>ty\<^isub>n"}. Like with the free-variable functions, 
  we also need to  define auxiliary alpha-equivalence relations for the binding functions. 
  Say we have @{text "bn\<^isub>1, \<dots>, bn\<^isub>m"}, then we also define @{text "\<approx>bn\<^isub>1, \<dots>, \<approx>bn\<^isub>m"}.
  To simplify our definitions we will use the following abbreviations for 
  relations and free-variable acting on products.
  %
  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{r@ {\hspace{2mm}}c@ {\hspace{2mm}}l}
  @{text "(x\<^isub>1, y\<^isub>1) (R\<^isub>1 \<otimes> R\<^isub>2) (x\<^isub>2, y\<^isub>2)"} & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{text "x\<^isub>1 R\<^isub>1 y\<^isub>1 \<and> x\<^isub>2 R\<^isub>2 y\<^isub>2"}\\
  @{text "(fv\<^isub>1 \<oplus> fv\<^isub>2) (x, y)"} & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{text "fv\<^isub>1 x \<union> fv\<^isub>2 y"}\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}


  The relations for alpha-equivalence are inductively defined predicates, whose clauses have
  conclusions of the form  
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "C x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>n  \<approx>ty  C y\<^isub>1 \<dots> y\<^isub>n"} 
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  For what follows, let us assume 
  @{text C} is of type @{text ty} and its arguments are given by @{text "C ty\<^isub>1 \<dots> ty\<^isub>n"}.
  The task is to specify what the premises of these clauses are. For this we
  consider the pairs \mbox{@{text "(x\<^isub>i, y\<^isub>i)"}}, but instead of considering them in turn, it will 
  be easier to analyse these pairs according to  ``clusters'' of the binding clauses. 
  Therefore we distinguish the following cases:
*}
(*<*)
consts alpha_ty ::'a
consts alpha_trm ::'a
consts fv_trm :: 'a
consts alpha_trm2 ::'a
consts fv_trm2 :: 'a
notation (latex output) 
  alpha_ty ("\<approx>ty") and
  alpha_trm ("\<approx>\<^bsub>trm\<^esub>") and
  fv_trm ("fv\<^bsub>trm\<^esub>") and
  alpha_trm2 ("\<approx>\<^bsub>assn\<^esub> \<otimes> \<approx>\<^bsub>trm\<^esub>") and
  fv_trm2 ("fv\<^bsub>assn\<^esub> \<oplus> fv\<^bsub>trm\<^esub>") 
(*>*)
text {*
  \begin{itemize}
  \item The @{text "(x\<^isub>i, y\<^isub>i)"} is a body of shallow binder with type @{text "ty"}. We assume the 
  \mbox{@{text "(u\<^isub>1, v\<^isub>1),\<dots>,(u\<^isub>m, v\<^isub>m)"}} are the corresponding binders. For the binding mode
  \isacommand{bind\_set} we generate the premise
  \begin{center}
   @{term "\<exists>p. (u\<^isub>1 \<union> \<xi> \<union> u\<^isub>m, x\<^isub>i) \<approx>gen alpha_ty fv_ty p (v\<^isub>1 \<union> \<xi> \<union> v\<^isub>m, y\<^isub>i)"}
  \end{center}

  For the binding mode \isacommand{bind}, we use $\approx_{\textit{list}}$, and for
  binding mode \isacommand{bind\_res} we use $\approx_{\textit{res}}$ instead. 

  \item The @{text "(x\<^isub>i, y\<^isub>i)"} is a deep non-recursive binder with type @{text "ty"}
  and @{text bn} is corresponding the binding function. We assume 
  @{text "(u\<^isub>1, v\<^isub>1),\<dots>,(u\<^isub>m, v\<^isub>m)"} are the corresponding bodies with types @{text "ty\<^isub>1,\<dots>, ty\<^isub>m"}. 
  For the binding mode \isacommand{bind\_set} we generate two premises
  %
  \begin{center}
   @{text "x\<^isub>i \<approx>bn y\<^isub>i"}\hfill
   @{term "\<exists>p. (bn x\<^isub>i, (u\<^isub>1,\<xi>,u\<^isub>m)) \<approx>gen R fv p (bn y\<^isub>i, (v\<^isub>1,\<xi>,v\<^isub>m))"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  where @{text R} is @{text "\<approx>ty\<^isub>1 \<otimes> ... \<otimes> \<approx>ty\<^isub>m"} and @{text fv} is
  @{text "fv_ty\<^isub>1 \<oplus> ... \<oplus> fv_ty\<^isub>m"}. Similarly for the other binding modes.

  \item The @{text "(x\<^isub>i, y\<^isub>i)"} is a deep recursive binders with type @{text "ty"}
  and  @{text bn} is the corresponding binding function. We assume 
  @{text "(u\<^isub>1, v\<^isub>1),\<dots>,(u\<^isub>m, v\<^isub>m)"} are the corresponding bodies with types @{text "ty\<^isub>1,\<dots>, ty\<^isub>m"}. 
  For the binding mode \isacommand{bind\_set} we generate the premise
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{term "\<exists>p. (bn x\<^isub>i, (x\<^isub>i, u\<^isub>1,\<xi>,u\<^isub>m)) \<approx>gen R fv p (bn y\<^isub>i, (y\<^isub>i, v\<^isub>1,\<xi>,v\<^isub>m))"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  where @{text R} is @{text "\<approx>ty \<otimes> \<approx>ty\<^isub>1 \<otimes> ... \<otimes> \<approx>ty\<^isub>m"} and @{text fv} is
  @{text "fv_ty \<oplus> fv_ty\<^isub>1 \<oplus> ... \<oplus> fv_ty\<^isub>m"}. Similarly for the other modes.
  \end{itemize}

  \noindent
  From this definition it is clear why we can only support one binding mode per binder
  and body, as we cannot mix the relations $\approx_{\textit{set}}$, $\approx_{\textit{list}}$
  and $\approx_{\textit{res}}$. It is also clear why we have to impose the restriction
  of excluding overlapping binders, as these would need to be translated into separate
  abstractions.


  The only cases that are not covered by the rules above are the cases where @{text "(x\<^isub>i, y\<^isub>i)"} is
  neither a binder nor a body in a binding clause. Then we just generate @{text "x\<^isub>i \<approx>ty y\<^isub>i"}  provided
  the type of @{text "x\<^isub>i"} and @{text "y\<^isub>i"} is @{text ty} and the arguments are 
  recursive arguments of the term-constructor. If they are non-recursive arguments,
  then we generate the premise @{text "x\<^isub>i = y\<^isub>i"}.


  The alpha-equivalence relations @{text "\<approx>bn\<^isub>j"} for binding functions 
  are similar. We again have conclusions of the form \mbox{@{text "C x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>n \<approx>bn C y\<^isub>1 \<dots> y\<^isub>n"}}
  and need to generate appropriate premises. We generate first premises according to the first three
  rules given above. Only the ``left-over'' pairs  @{text "(x\<^isub>i, y\<^isub>i)"} need to be treated 
  differently. They depend on whether @{text "x\<^isub>i"}  occurs in @{text "rhs"} of  the 
  clause @{text "bn (C x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>n) = rhs"}:

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{c@ {\hspace{2mm}}p{7cm}}
  $\bullet$ & @{text "x\<^isub>i \<approx>ty y\<^isub>i"} provided @{text "x\<^isub>i"} does not occur in @{text rhs}
  and the type of @{text "x\<^isub>i"} is @{text ty} and @{text "x\<^isub>i"} is a recursive argument 
  in the term-constructor\\
  $\bullet$ & @{text "x\<^isub>i = y\<^isub>i"} provided @{text "x\<^isub>i"} does not occur in @{text rhs}
  and @{text "x\<^isub>i"} is not a recursive argument in the term-constructor\\
  $\bullet$ & @{text "x\<^isub>i \<approx>bn y\<^isub>i"} provided @{text "x\<^isub>i"} occurs in @{text rhs}
  with the recursive call @{text "bn x\<^isub>i"}\\
  $\bullet$ & none provided @{text "x\<^isub>i"} occurs in @{text rhs} but it is not
  in a recursive call involving a @{text "bn"}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  Again lets take a look at a concrete example for these definitions. For \eqref{letrecs}
  we have three relations, namely $\approx_{\textit{trm}}$, $\approx_{\textit{assn}}$ and
  $\approx_{\textit{bn}}$, with the clauses as follows:

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}c @ {}}
  \infer{@{text "Let as t \<approx>\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> Let as' t'"}}
  {@{text "as \<approx>\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> as'"} & @{term "\<exists>p. (bn as, t) \<approx>lst alpha_trm fv_trm p (bn as', t')"}}\smallskip\\
  \infer{@{text "Let_rec as t \<approx>\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> Let_rec as' t'"}}
  {@{term "\<exists>p. (bn as, (as, t)) \<approx>lst alpha_trm2 fv_trm2 p (bn as', (as', t'))"}}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}c @ {}}
  \infer{@{text "ANil \<approx>\<^bsub>assn\<^esub> ANil"}}{}\\
  \infer{@{text "ACons a t as \<approx>\<^bsub>assn\<^esub> ACons a' t' as"}}
  {@{text "a = a'"} & @{text "t \<approx>\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> t'"} & @{text "as \<approx>\<^bsub>assn\<^esub> as'"}}\medskip\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{@ {}c @ {}}
  \infer{@{text "ANil \<approx>\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> ANil"}}{}\\
  \infer{@{text "ACons a t as \<approx>\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> ACons a' t' as"}}
  {@{text "t \<approx>\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> t'"} & @{text "as \<approx>\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> as'"}}\medskip\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  Note the difference between  $\approx_{\textit{assn}}$ and
  $\approx_{\textit{bn}}$: the latter only ``tracks'' alpha-equivalence of 
  the components in an assignment that are \emph{not} bound. Therefore we have
  a $\approx_{\textit{bn}}$-premise in the clause for @{text "Let"} (which is 
  a non-recursive binder). The reason is that the terms inside an assignment are not meant 
  to be ``under'' the binder. Such a premise is \emph{not} needed in @{text "Let_rec"}, 
  because there everything from the assignment is under the binder. 
*}

section {* Establishing the Reasoning Infrastructure *}

text {*
  Having made all necessary definitions for raw terms, we can start
  introducing the reasoning infrastructure for the alpha-equated types the
  user originally specified. We sketch in this section the facts we need for establishing
  this reasoning infrastructure. First we have to show that the
  alpha-equivalence relations defined in the previous section are indeed
  equivalence relations.

  \begin{lemma}\label{equiv} 
  Given the raw types @{text "ty\<^isub>1, \<dots>, ty\<^isub>n"} and binding functions
  @{text "bn\<^isub>1, \<dots>, bn\<^isub>m"}, the relations @{text "\<approx>ty\<^isub>1, \<dots>, \<approx>ty\<^isub>n"} and 
  @{text "\<approx>bn\<^isub>1 \<dots> \<approx>bn\<^isub>m"} are equivalence relations and equivariant.
  \end{lemma}

  \begin{proof} 
  The proof is by mutual induction over the definitions. The non-trivial
  cases involve premises build up by $\approx_{\textit{set}}$, 
  $\approx_{\textit{res}}$ and $\approx_{\textit{list}}$. They 
  can be dealt with as in Lemma~\ref{alphaeq}.
  \end{proof}

  \noindent 
  We can feed this lemma into our quotient package and obtain new types @{text
  "ty\<AL>\<^bsub>1..n\<^esub>"} representing alpha-equated terms of types @{text "ty\<^bsub>1..n\<^esub>"}. We also obtain 
  definitions for the term-constructors @{text
  "C"}$^\alpha_{1..m}$ from the raw term-constructors @{text
  "C"}$_{1..m}$, and similar definitions for the free-variable functions @{text
  "fv_ty"}$^\alpha_{1..n}$ and the binding functions @{text
  "bn"}$^\alpha_{1..k}$. However, these definitions are not really useful to the 
  user, since the are given in terms of the isomorphisms we obtained by 
  creating new types in Isabelle/HOL (recall the picture shown in the 
  Introduction).

  The first useful property to the user is the fact that term-constructors are 
  distinct, that is
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{distinctalpha}
  \mbox{@{text "C"}$^\alpha_i$@{text "x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>n"} @{text "\<noteq>"} 
  @{text "C"}$^\alpha_j$@{text "y\<^isub>1 \<dots> y\<^isub>m"} holds for @{text "i \<noteq> j"}.} 
  \end{equation}
  
  \noindent
  By definition of alpha-equivalence we can show that
  for the raw term-constructors
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{distinctraw}
  \mbox{@{text "C\<^isub>i x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>n"}\;$\not\approx$@{text ty}\;@{text "C\<^isub>j y\<^isub>1 \<dots> y\<^isub>m"} holds for @{text "i \<noteq> j"}.}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  In order to generate \eqref{distinctalpha} from \eqref{distinctraw}, the quotient
  package needs to know that the term-constructors @{text "C\<^isub>i"} and @{text "C\<^isub>j"} 
  are \emph{respectful} w.r.t.~the alpha-equivalence relations (see \cite{Homeier05}).
  Assuming @{text "C\<^isub>i"} is of type @{text "ty"} with argument types
  @{text "ty\<^isub>1, \<dots>, ty\<^isub>n"}, then respectfulness amounts to showing that
  
  \begin{center}
  @{text "C\<^isub>i x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>n \<approx>ty C\<^isub>i y\<^isub>1 \<dots> y\<^isub>n"}
  \end{center}  

  \noindent
  are alpha-equivalent under the assumption that @{text "x\<^isub>i \<approx>ty\<^isub>i y\<^isub>i"} holds for all recursive arguments
  and  @{text "x\<^isub>i = y\<^isub>i"} holds for all non-recursive arguments of @{text "C\<^isub>i"}. We can prove this by 
  analysing the definition of @{text "\<approx>ty"}. For this proof to succeed we have to establish 
  the following auxiliary fact about binding functions. Given a binding function @{text bn\<^isub>i} defined 
  for the type @{text ty\<^isub>i}, we have that
  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "x \<approx>ty\<^isub>i y"} implies @{text "x \<approx>bn\<^isub>i y"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  This can be established by induction on the definition of @{text "\<approx>ty\<^isub>i"}. 
   
  Having established respectfulness for every raw term-constructor, the 
  quotient package is able to automatically deduce \eqref{distinctalpha} from \eqref{distinctraw}.
  In fact we can from now on lift facts from the raw level to the alpha-equated level
  as long as they contain raw term-constructors only. The 
  induction principles derived by the datatype package in Isabelle/HOL for the types @{text
  "ty\<AL>\<^bsub>1..n\<^esub>"} fall into this category. So we can also add to our infrastructure
  induction principles that establish

  \begin{center}
  @{text "P\<^bsub>ty\<^isub>1\<^esub> y\<^isub>1 \<dots> P\<^bsub>ty\<^isub>n\<^esub> y\<^isub>n "}
  \end{center} 

  \noindent
  for all @{text "y\<^isub>i"} wherby the variables @{text "P\<^bsub>ty\<^isub>i\<^esub>"} stand for properties
  defined over the types @{text "ty\<AL>\<^isub>1 \<dots> ty\<AL>\<^isub>n"}. The premises of 
  these induction principles look
  as follows

  \begin{center}
  @{text "\<forall>x\<^isub>1\<dots>x\<^isub>n. P\<^bsub>ty\<^isub>i\<^esub> x\<^isub>i \<and> \<dots> \<and> P\<^bsub>ty\<^isub>j\<^esub> x\<^isub>j \<Rightarrow> P\<^bsub>ty\<^esub> (C\<^sup>\<alpha> x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>n)"} 
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  where the @{text "x\<^isub>i, \<dots>, x\<^isub>j"} are the recursive arguments of @{text "C\<^sup>\<alpha>"}. 
  Next we lift the permutation operations defined in \eqref{ceqvt} for
  the raw term-constructors @{text "C"}. These facts contain, in addition 
  to the term-constructors, also permutations operations. In order to make the 
  lifting to go through, 
  we have to know that the permutation operations are respectful 
  w.r.t.~alpha-equivalence. This amounts to showing that the 
  alpha-equivalence relations are equivariant, which we already established 
  in Lemma~\ref{equiv}. As a result we can establish the equations
  
  \begin{equation}\label{ceqvt}
  @{text "p \<bullet> (C\<^sup>\<alpha> x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>n) = C\<^sup>\<alpha> (p \<bullet> x\<^isub>1) \<dots> (p \<bullet> x\<^isub>n)"}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  for our infrastructure. In a similar fashion we can lift the equations
  characterising the free-variable functions @{text "fn_ty\<AL>\<^isub>j"} and @{text "fv_bn\<AL>\<^isub>k"}, and the 
  binding functions @{text "bn\<AL>\<^isub>k"}. The necessary respectfulness lemmas for this
  lifting are the properties:
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{fnresp}
  \mbox{%
  \begin{tabular}{l}
  @{text "x \<approx>ty\<^isub>j y"} implies @{text "fv_ty\<^isub>j x = fv_ty\<^isub>j y"}\\
  @{text "x \<approx>ty\<^isub>k y"} implies @{text "fv_bn\<^isub>k x = fv_bn\<^isub>k y"}\\
  @{text "x \<approx>ty\<^isub>k y"} implies @{text "bn\<^isub>k x = bn\<^isub>k y"}
  \end{tabular}}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  which can be established by induction on @{text "\<approx>ty"}. Whereas the first
  property is always true by the way how we defined the free-variable
  functions for types, the second and third do \emph{not} hold in general. There is, in principle, 
  the possibility that the user defines @{text "bn\<^isub>k"} so that it returns an already bound
  variable. Then the third property is just not true. However, our 
  restrictions imposed on the binding functions
  exclude this possibility.

  Having the facts \eqref{fnresp} at our disposal, we can lift the
  definitions that characterise when two terms of the form

  \begin{center}
  @{text "C x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>n \<approx>ty C y\<^isub>1 \<dots> y\<^isub>n"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  are alpha-equivalent. This gives us conditions when the corresponding
  alpha-equated terms are equal, namely

  \begin{center}
  @{text "C\<^sup>\<alpha> x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>n = C\<^sup>\<alpha> y\<^isub>1 \<dots> y\<^isub>n"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  We call these conditions as \emph{quasi-injectivity}. Except for one function, which
  we have to lift in the next section, we completed
  the lifting part of establishing the reasoning infrastructure. 

  Working bow completely on the alpha-equated level, we can first show that 
  the free-variable functions and binding functions
  are equivariant, namely

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{rcl}
  @{text "p \<bullet> (fv_ty\<^sup>\<alpha> x)"} & $=$ & @{text "fv_ty\<^sup>\<alpha> (p \<bullet> x)"}\\
  @{text "p \<bullet> (fv_bn\<^sup>\<alpha> x)"} & $=$ & @{text "fv_bn\<^sup>\<alpha> (p \<bullet> x)"}\\
  @{text "p \<bullet> (bn\<^sup>\<alpha> x)"}    & $=$ & @{text "bn\<^sup>\<alpha> (p \<bullet> x)"}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  These properties can be established by structural induction over the @{text x}
  (using the induction principles we lifted above for the types @{text "ty\<AL>\<^bsub>1..n\<^esub>"}).

  Until now we have not yet derived anything about the support of the 
  alpha-equated terms. This however will be necessary in order to derive
  the strong induction principles in the next section.
  Using the equivariance properties in \eqref{ceqvt} we can
  show for every term-constructor @{text "C\<^sup>\<alpha>"} that 

  \begin{center}
  @{text "(supp x\<^isub>1 \<union> \<dots> supp x\<^isub>n) supports (C\<^sup>\<alpha> x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>n)"}
  \end{center}
 
  \noindent
  holds. This together with Property~\ref{supportsprop} allows us to show
 
  \begin{center}
  @{text "finite (supp x\<^isub>i)"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  by a structural induction over @{text "x\<^isub>1, \<dots>, x\<^isub>n"} (whereby @{text "x\<^isub>i"} ranges over the types 
  @{text "ty\<AL>\<^isub>1 \<dots> ty\<AL>\<^isub>n"}). Lastly, we can show that the support of elements in 
  @{text "ty\<AL>\<^bsub>1..n\<^esub>"} coincides with @{text "fv_ty\<AL>\<^bsub>1..n\<^esub>"}.

  \begin{lemma} 
  For every @{text "x\<^isub>i"} of type @{text "ty\<AL>\<^bsub>1..n\<^esub>"}, we have that 
  @{text "supp x\<^isub>i = fv_ty\<AL>\<^isub>i x\<^isub>i"} holds.
  \end{lemma}

  \begin{proof}
  The proof proceeds by structural induction over the @{text "x\<^isub>i"}. In each case
  we unfold the definition of @{text "supp"}, move the swapping inside the 
  term-constructors and the use then quasi-injectivity lemmas in order to complete the
  proof. For the abstraction cases we use the facts derived in Theorem~\ref{suppabs}.
  \end{proof}

  \noindent
  To sum up, we can established automatically a reasoning infrastructure
  for the types @{text "ty\<AL>\<^isub>1, \<dots>, ty\<AL>\<^isub>n"} 
  by first lifting definitions from the raw level to the quotient level and
  then establish facts about these lifted definitions. All necessary proofs
  are generated automatically by custom ML-code. This code can deal with 
  specifications like the one shown in Figure~\ref{nominalcorehas} for Core-Haskell.  

  \begin{figure}[t!]
  \begin{boxedminipage}{\linewidth}
  \small
  \begin{tabular}{l}
  \isacommand{atom\_decl}~@{text "var"}\\
  \isacommand{atom\_decl}~@{text "cvar"}\\
  \isacommand{atom\_decl}~@{text "tvar"}\\[1mm]
  \isacommand{nominal\_datatype}~@{text "tkind ="}\\
  \phantom{$|$}~@{text "KStar"}~$|$~@{text "KFun tkind tkind"}\\ 
  \isacommand{and}~@{text "ckind ="}\\
  \phantom{$|$}~@{text "CKSim ty ty"}\\
  \isacommand{and}~@{text "ty ="}\\
  \phantom{$|$}~@{text "TVar tvar"}~$|$~@{text "T string"}~$|$~@{text "TApp ty ty"}\\
  $|$~@{text "TFun string ty_list"}~%
  $|$~@{text "TAll tv::tvar tkind ty::ty"}  \isacommand{bind}~@{text "tv"}~\isacommand{in}~@{text ty}\\
  $|$~@{text "TArr ckind ty"}\\
  \isacommand{and}~@{text "ty_lst ="}\\
  \phantom{$|$}~@{text "TNil"}~$|$~@{text "TCons ty ty_lst"}\\
  \isacommand{and}~@{text "cty ="}\\
  \phantom{$|$}~@{text "CVar cvar"}~%
  $|$~@{text "C string"}~$|$~@{text "CApp cty cty"}~$|$~@{text "CFun string co_lst"}\\
  $|$~@{text "CAll cv::cvar ckind cty::cty"}  \isacommand{bind}~@{text "cv"}~\isacommand{in}~@{text cty}\\
  $|$~@{text "CArr ckind cty"}~$|$~@{text "CRefl ty"}~$|$~@{text "CSym cty"}~$|$~@{text "CCirc cty cty"}\\
  $|$~@{text "CAt cty ty"}~$|$~@{text "CLeft cty"}~$|$~@{text "CRight cty"}~$|$~@{text "CSim cty cty"}\\
  $|$~@{text "CRightc cty"}~$|$~@{text "CLeftc cty"}~$|$~@{text "Coerce cty cty"}\\
  \isacommand{and}~@{text "co_lst ="}\\
  \phantom{$|$}@{text "CNil"}~$|$~@{text "CCons cty co_lst"}\\
  \isacommand{and}~@{text "trm ="}\\
  \phantom{$|$}~@{text "Var var"}~$|$~@{text "K string"}\\
  $|$~@{text "LAM_ty tv::tvar tkind t::trm"}  \isacommand{bind}~@{text "tv"}~\isacommand{in}~@{text t}\\
  $|$~@{text "LAM_cty cv::cvar ckind t::trm"}   \isacommand{bind}~@{text "cv"}~\isacommand{in}~@{text t}\\
  $|$~@{text "App_ty trm ty"}~$|$~@{text "App_cty trm cty"}~$|$~@{text "App trm trm"}\\
  $|$~@{text "Lam v::var ty t::trm"}  \isacommand{bind}~@{text "v"}~\isacommand{in}~@{text t}\\
  $|$~@{text "Let x::var ty trm t::trm"}  \isacommand{bind}~@{text x}~\isacommand{in}~@{text t}\\
  $|$~@{text "Case trm assoc_lst"}~$|$~@{text "Cast trm co"}\\
  \isacommand{and}~@{text "assoc_lst ="}\\
  \phantom{$|$}~@{text ANil}~%
  $|$~@{text "ACons p::pat t::trm assoc_lst"}  \isacommand{bind}~@{text "bv p"}~\isacommand{in}~@{text t}\\
  \isacommand{and}~@{text "pat ="}\\
  \phantom{$|$}~@{text "Kpat string tvtk_lst tvck_lst vt_lst"}\\
  \isacommand{and}~@{text "vt_lst ="}\\
  \phantom{$|$}~@{text VTNil}~$|$~@{text "VTCons var ty vt_lst"}\\
  \isacommand{and}~@{text "tvtk_lst ="}\\
  \phantom{$|$}~@{text TVTKNil}~$|$~@{text "TVTKCons tvar tkind tvtk_lst"}\\
  \isacommand{and}~@{text "tvck_lst ="}\\ 
  \phantom{$|$}~@{text TVCKNil}~$|$ @{text "TVCKCons cvar ckind tvck_lst"}\\
  \isacommand{binder}\\
  @{text "bv :: pat \<Rightarrow> atom list"}~\isacommand{and}~%
  @{text "bv1 :: vt_lst \<Rightarrow> atom list"}~\isacommand{and}\\
  @{text "bv2 :: tvtk_lst \<Rightarrow> atom list"}~\isacommand{and}~%
  @{text "bv3 :: tvck_lst \<Rightarrow> atom list"}\\
  \isacommand{where}\\
  \phantom{$|$}~@{text "bv (K s tvts tvcs vs) = (bv3 tvts) @ (bv2 tvcs) @ (bv1 vs)"}\\
  $|$~@{text "bv1 VTNil = []"}\\
  $|$~@{text "bv1 (VTCons x ty tl) = (atom x)::(bv1 tl)"}\\
  $|$~@{text "bv2 TVTKNil = []"}\\
  $|$~@{text "bv2 (TVTKCons a ty tl) = (atom a)::(bv2 tl)"}\\
  $|$~@{text "bv3 TVCKNil = []"}\\
  $|$~@{text "bv3 (TVCKCons c cty tl) = (atom c)::(bv3 tl)"}\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{boxedminipage}
  \caption{The nominal datatype declaration for Core-Haskell. At the moment we
  do not support nested types; therefore we explicitly have to unfold the 
  lists @{text "co_lst"}, @{text "assoc_lst"} and so on. This will be improved
  in a future version of Nominal Isabelle. Apart from that, the 
  declaration follows closely the original in Figure~\ref{corehas}. The
  point of our work is that having made such a declaration in Nominal Isabelle,
  one obtains automatically a reasoning infrastructure for Core-Haskell.
  \label{nominalcorehas}}
  \end{figure}
*}


section {* Strong Induction Principles *}

text {*
  In the previous section we were able to provide induction principles that 
  allow us to perform structural inductions over alpha-equated terms. 
  We call such induction principles \emph{weak}, because in case of a term-constructor @{text "C\<^sup>\<alpha> x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>n"},
  the induction hypothesis requires us to establish the implication
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{weakprem}
  @{text "\<forall>x\<^isub>1\<dots>x\<^isub>n. P\<^isub>i x\<^isub>i \<and> \<dots> \<and> P\<^isub>j x\<^isub>j \<Rightarrow> P (C\<^sup>\<alpha> x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>n)"} 
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  where the @{text "x\<^isub>i, \<dots>, x\<^isub>j"} are the recursive arguments of @{text "C\<^sup>\<alpha>"}. 
  The problem with this implication is that in general it is not easy to establish it.
  The reason is we cannot make any assumption about the binders in @{text "C\<^sup>\<alpha>"} 
  (for example we cannot assume the variable convention for them).

  In \cite{UrbanTasson05} we introduced a method for automatically
  strengthening weak induction principles for terms containing single
  binders. These stronger induction principles allow the user to make additional
  assumptions about binders when proving the induction hypotheses. 
  These additional assumptions amount to a formal
  version of the informal variable convention for binders. A natural question is
  whether we can also strengthen the weak induction principles involving
  general binders. We will indeed be able to so, but for this we need an 
  additional notion for permuting deep binders. 

  Given a binding function @{text "bn"} we define an auxiliary permutation 
  operation @{text "_ \<bullet>\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> _"} which permutes only bound arguments in a deep binder.
  Assuming a clause of @{text bn} is defined as @{text "bn (C x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>n) = rhs"}, then
  we define  %
  \begin{center}
  @{text "p \<bullet>\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> (C x\<^isub>1 \<dots> x\<^isub>n) \<equiv> C y\<^isub>1 \<dots> y\<^isub>n"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  with @{text "y\<^isub>i"} determined as follows:
  %
  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{c@ {\hspace{2mm}}p{7cm}}
  $\bullet$ & @{text "y\<^isub>i \<equiv> x\<^isub>i"} provided @{text "x\<^isub>i"} does not occur in @{text "rhs"}\\
  $\bullet$ & @{text "y\<^isub>i \<equiv> p \<bullet>\<^bsub>bn'\<^esub> x\<^isub>i"} provided @{text "bn' x\<^isub>i"} is in @{text "rhs"}\\
  $\bullet$ & @{text "y\<^isub>i \<equiv> p \<bullet> x\<^isub>i"} otherwise
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}
  
  \noindent
  Using the quotient package again we can lift the @{text "_ \<bullet>\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> _"} function to 
  alpha-equated terms. We can then prove the following two facts

  \begin{lemma}\label{permutebn} 
  Given a binding function @{text "bn\<^sup>\<alpha>"} then for all @{text p}
  {\it i)} @{text "p \<bullet> (bn\<^sup>\<alpha> x) = bn\<^sup>\<alpha> (p \<bullet>\<^bsub>bn\<^sup>\<alpha>\<^esub> x)"} and {\it ii)}
    @{text "fv_bn\<^isup>\<alpha> x = fv_bn\<^isup>\<alpha> (p \<bullet>\<^bsub>bn\<^sup>\<alpha>\<^esub> x)"}.
  \end{lemma}

  \begin{proof} 
  By induction on @{text x}. The equation follow by simple unfolding 
  of the definitions. 
  \end{proof}

  \noindent
  The first property states that a permutation applied to a binding function is
  equivalent to first permuting the binders and then calculating the bound
  variables. The second amounts to the fact that permuting the binders has no 
  effect on the free-variable function. The main point of this permutation
  function, however, is that if we have a permutation that is fresh 
  for the support of an object @{text x}, then we can use this permutation 
  to rename the binders in @{text x}, without ``changing'' @{text x}. In case of the 
  @{text "Let"} term-constructor from the example shown 
  \eqref{letpat} this means for a permutation @{text "r"}:
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{renaming}
  \mbox{if @{term "supp (Abs_lst (bn p) t)  \<sharp>* r"} 
  then @{text "Let p t = Let (r \<bullet>\<^bsub>bn\<^bsub>pat\<^esub>\<^esub> p) (r \<bullet> t)"}}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  This fact will be used when establishing the strong induction principles. 
  

  In our running example about @{text "Let"}, they state that instead 
  of establishing the implication 

  \begin{center}
  @{text "\<forall>p t. P\<^bsub>pat\<^esub> p \<and> P\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> t \<Rightarrow> P\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> (Let p t)"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  it is sufficient to establish the following implication
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{strong}
  \mbox{\begin{tabular}{l}
  @{text "\<forall>p t c."}\\
  \hspace{5mm}@{text "set (bn p) #\<^sup>* c \<and> (\<forall>d. P\<^bsub>pat\<^esub> d p) \<and> (\<forall>d. P\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> d t)"}\\
  \hspace{15mm}@{text "\<Rightarrow> P\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> c (Let p t)"}
  \end{tabular}}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent 
  While this implication contains an additional argument, namely @{text c}, and 
  also additional universal quantifications, it is usually easier to establish.
  The reason is that we can make the freshness 
  assumption @{text "set (bn\<^sup>\<alpha> p) #\<^sup>* c"}, whereby @{text c} can be arbitrarily 
  chosen by the user as long as it has finite support.

  Let us now show how we derive the strong induction principles from the
  weak ones. In case of the @{text "Let"}-example we derive by the weak 
  induction the following two properties
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{hyps}
  @{text "\<forall>q c. P\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> c (q \<bullet> t)"} \hspace{4mm} 
  @{text "\<forall>q\<^isub>1 q\<^isub>2 c. P\<^bsub>pat\<^esub> (q\<^isub>1 \<bullet>\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> (q\<^isub>2 \<bullet> p))"}
  \end{equation} 

  \noindent
  For the @{text Let} term-constructor  we therefore have to establish @{text "P\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> c (q \<bullet> Let p t)"} 
  assuming \eqref{hyps} as induction hypotheses. By Property~\ref{avoiding} we
  obtain a permutation @{text "r"} such that 
  %
  \begin{equation}\label{rprops}
  @{term "(r \<bullet> set (bn (q \<bullet> p))) \<sharp>* c "}\hspace{4mm}
  @{term "supp (Abs_lst (bn (q \<bullet> p)) (q \<bullet> t)) \<sharp>* r"}
  \end{equation}

  \noindent
  hold. The latter fact and \eqref{renaming} give us

  \begin{center}
  @{text "Let (q \<bullet> p) (q \<bullet> t) = Let (r \<bullet>\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> (q \<bullet> p)) (r \<bullet> (q \<bullet> t))"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  So instead of proving @{text "P\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> c (q \<bullet> Let p t)"}, we are can equally
  establish

  \begin{center}
  @{text "P\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> c (Let (r \<bullet>\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> (q \<bullet> p)) (r \<bullet> (q \<bullet> t)))"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  To do so, we will use the implication \eqref{strong} of the strong induction
  principle, which requires us to discharge
  the following three proof obligations:

  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{rl}
  {\it i)} &   @{text "set (bn (r \<bullet>\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> (q \<bullet> p))) #\<^sup>* c"}\\
  {\it ii)} &  @{text "\<forall>d. P\<^bsub>pat\<^esub> d (r \<bullet>\<^bsub>bn\<^esub> (q \<bullet> p))"}\\
  {\it iii)} & @{text "\<forall>d. P\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> d (r \<bullet> (q \<bullet> t))"}\\
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  The first follows from \eqref{rprops} and Lemma~\ref{permutebn}.{\it i)}; the 
  second and third from the induction hypotheses in \eqref{hyps} (in the latter case
  we have to use the fact that @{term "(r \<bullet> (q \<bullet> t)) = (r + q) \<bullet> t"}).

  Taking now the identity permutation @{text 0} for the permutations in \eqref{hyps},
  we can establish our original goals, namely @{text "P\<^bsub>trm\<^esub> c t"} and \mbox{@{text "P\<^bsub>pat\<^esub> c p"}}.
  This completes the proof showing that the strong induction principle derives from
  the weak induction principle. At the moment we can derive the difficult cases of 
  the strong induction principles only by hand, but they are very schematically 
  so that with little effort we can even derive the strong induction principle for 
  Core-Haskell given in Figure~\ref{nominalcorehas}. 
*}


section {* Related Work *}

text {*
  To our knowledge, the earliest usage of general binders in a theorem prover
  is described in \cite{NaraschewskiNipkow99} about a formalisation of the
  algorithm W. This formalisation implements binding in type schemes using a
  de-Bruijn indices representation. Since type schemes of W contain only a single
  binder, different indices do not refer to different binders (as in the usual
  de-Bruijn representation), but to different bound variables. A similar idea
  has been recently explored for general binders in the locally nameless
  approach to binding \cite{chargueraud09}.  There, de-Bruijn indices consist
  of two numbers, one referring to the place where a variable is bound and the
  other to which variable is bound. The reasoning infrastructure for both
  representations of bindings comes for free in the theorem provers Isabelle/HOL and
  Coq, for example, as the corresponding term-calculi can be implemented as ``normal''
  datatypes.  However, in both approaches it seems difficult to achieve our
  fine-grained control over the ``semantics'' of bindings (i.e.~whether the
  order of binders should matter, or vacuous binders should be taken into
  account). To do so, one would require additional predicates that filter out
  unwanted terms. Our guess is that such predicates results in rather
  intricate formal reasoning.

  Another representation technique for binding is higher-order abstract syntax
  (HOAS), which for example is implemented in the Twelf system. This representation
  technique supports very elegantly many aspects of \emph{single} binding, and
  impressive work is in progress that uses HOAS for mechanising the metatheory
  of SML~\cite{LeeCraryHarper07}. We are, however, not aware how multiple
  binders of SML are represented in this work. Judging from the submitted
  Twelf-solution for the POPLmark challenge, HOAS cannot easily deal with
  binding constructs where the number of bound variables is not fixed. For
  example in the second part of this challenge, @{text "Let"}s involve
  patterns that bind multiple variables at once. In such situations, HOAS
  representations have to resort to the iterated-single-binders-approach with
  all the unwanted consequences when reasoning about the resulting terms.

  Two formalisations involving general binders have also been performed in older
  versions of Nominal Isabelle \cite{BengtsonParow09, UrbanNipkow09}.  Both
  use the approach based on iterated single binders. Our experience with
  the latter formalisation has been disappointing. The major pain arose from
  the need to ``unbind'' variables. This can be done in one step with our
  general binders, for example @{term "Abs as x"}, but needs a cumbersome
  iteration with single binders. The resulting formal reasoning turned out to
  be rather unpleasant. The hope is that the extension presented in this paper
  is a substantial improvement.
 
  The most closely related work to the one presented here is the Ott-tool \cite{ott-jfp}. This tool is a
  nifty front-end for creating \LaTeX{} documents from specifications of
  term-calculi involving general binders. For a subset of the specifications, Ott can also generate
  theorem prover code using a raw representation of terms, and in Coq also a
  locally nameless representation. The developers of this tool have also put
  forward (on paper) a definition for alpha-equivalence of terms that can be
  specified in Ott.  This definition is rather different from ours, not using
  any nominal techniques. Although we were heavily inspired by their syntax,
  their definition of alpha-equivalence is unsuitable for our extension of
  Nominal Isabelle. First, it is far too complicated to be a basis for
  automated proofs implemented on the ML-level of Isabelle/HOL. Second, it
  covers cases of binders depending on other binders, which just do not make
  sense for our alpha-equated terms. Third, it allows empty types that have no
  meaning in a HOL-based theorem prover.

  Because of how we set up our definitions, we had to impose restrictions,
  like excluding overlapping deep binders, that are not present in Ott. Our
  expectation is that we can still cover many interesting term-calculi from
  programming language research, for example Core-Haskell. For prviding support
  of neat features in Ott, such as subgrammars, the existing datatype
  infrastructure in Isabelle/HOL is unfortunately not powerful enough. On the
  other hand, we are not aware that Ott can make the distinction between our
  three different binding modes. Also, definitions for notions like the free
  variables of a term are work in progress in Ott.
*}

section {* Conclusion *}

text {*
  We have presented an extension of Nominal Isabelle for deriving
  automatically a convenient reasoning infrastructure that can deal with
  general binders, that is term-constructors binding multiple variables at
  once. This extension has been tried out with the Core-Haskell
  term-calculus. For such general binders, we can also extend
  earlier work that derives strong induction principles which have the usual
  variable convention already built in. At the moment we can do so only with manual help,
  but future work will automate them completely.  The code underlying the presented
  extension will become part of the Isabelle distribution, but for the moment
  it can be downloaded from the Mercurial repository linked at
  \href{http://isabelle.in.tum.de/nominal/download}
  {http://isabelle.in.tum.de/nominal/download}.

  We have left out a discussion about how functions can be defined over
  alpha-equated terms that involve general binders. In earlier versions of Nominal
  Isabelle \cite{UrbanBerghofer06} this turned out to be a thorny issue.  We
  hope to do better this time by using the function package that has recently
  been implemented in Isabelle/HOL and also by restricting function
  definitions to equivariant functions (for such functions it is possible to
  provide more automation).

  There are some restrictions we imposed in this paper, we like to lift in
  future work. One is the exclusion of nested datatype definitions. Nested
  datatype definitions allow one to specify, for instance, the function kinds
  in Core-Haskell as @{text "TFun string (ty list)"} instead of the unfolded
  version @{text "TFun string ty_list"} in Figure~\ref{nominalcorehas}. For
  them we need a more clever implementation than we have at the moment. 

  More
  interesting is lifting our restriction about overlapping deep binders. Given
  our current setup, we cannot deal with specifications such as

 
  \begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{ll}
  @{text "Foo r::pat s::pat t::trm"} & 
     \isacommand{bind} @{text "bn(r)"} \isacommand{in} @{text t},\;
     \isacommand{bind} @{text "bn(s)"} \isacommand{in} @{text t}
  \end{tabular}
  \end{center}
  
  \noindent
  where the deep binders @{text "bn(r)"} and @{text "bn(s)"} overlap. 
  The difficulty is that we would need to implement such overlapping bindings 
  with alpha-equivalences like

  \begin{center}
  @{term "\<exists>p q. abs_set2 (bn r\<^isub>1, t\<^isub>1) p (bn r\<^isub>2, t\<^isub>2) \<and> abs_set2 (bn s\<^isub>1, t\<^isub>1) q (bn s\<^isub>2, t\<^isub>2)"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  or

  \begin{center}
  @{term "\<exists>p q. abs_set2 (bn r\<^isub>1 \<union> bn s\<^isub>1, t\<^isub>1) (p + q)  (bn r\<^isub>2 \<union> bn s\<^isub>2, t\<^isub>2)"}
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  Both versions require two permutations (for each binding). But unfortunately the 
  first version cannot work since it leaves some atoms unbound that should be 
  bound by the respective other binder. This problem is avoided in the second
  version, but at the expense that the two permutations can interfere with each 
  other. We have not yet been able to find a way to avoid such interferences. 
  On the other hand, such bindings can be made sense of informally \cite{SewellBestiary}.
  This suggest there should be an approriate notion of alpha-equivalence.

  Another interesting line of investigation is whether we can go beyond the 
  simple-minded form of binding function we adopted from Ott. At the moment, binding
  functions can only return the empty set, a singleton atom set or unions
  of atom sets (similarly for lists). It remains to be seen whether 
  properties like \eqref{bnprop} provide us with means to support more interesting
  binding functions. 


  We have also not yet played with other binding modes. For example we can
  imagine that there is need for a binding mode \isacommand{bind\_\#list} with an associated
  alpha-equivalence definition as follows:
  %
  \begin{center}
  $\begin{array}{@ {\hspace{10mm}}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l}
  \multicolumn{2}{l}{@{term "alpha2 (as, x) R fv p (bs, y)"}\hspace{2mm}@{text "\<equiv>"}\hspace{30mm}}\\[1mm]
             & @{term "fv(x) - (set as) = fv(y) - (set bs)"}\\
  \wedge     & @{term "(fv(x) - set as) \<sharp>* p"}\\
  \wedge     & @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"}\\
  \wedge     & @{term "(p \<bullet> as) = bs"}\\
  \wedge     & @{term "distinct as"} 
  \end{array}$
  \end{center}

  \noindent
  In this definition we added the requirement that all bound variables in a
  list are distinct. Once we feel confident about such binding modes, our implementation 
  can be easily extended to accommodate them.

  \medskip
  \noindent
  {\bf Acknowledgements:} We are very grateful to Andrew Pitts for  
  many discussions about Nominal Isabelle. We thank Peter Sewell for 
  making the informal notes \cite{SewellBestiary} available to us and 
  also for patiently explaining some of the finer points of the work on the Ott-tool. We
  also thank Stephanie Weirich for suggesting to separate the subgrammars
  of kinds and types in our Core-Haskell example.  
*}

(*<*)
end
(*>*)