(*<*)
theory Paper
imports "../Nominal/Nominal2_Base"
"../Nominal/Atoms"
"../Nominal/Nominal2_Abs"
"~~/src/HOL/Library/LaTeXsugar"
begin
abbreviation
UNIV_atom ("\<allatoms>")
where
"UNIV_atom \<equiv> UNIV::atom set"
notation (latex output)
sort_of ("sort _" [1000] 100) and
Abs_perm ("_") and
Rep_perm ("_") and
swap ("'(_ _')" [1000, 1000] 1000) and
fresh ("_ # _" [51, 51] 50) and
fresh_star ("_ #\<^sup>* _" [51, 51] 50) and
Cons ("_::_" [78,77] 73) and
supp ("supp _" [78] 73) and
uminus ("-_" [78] 73) and
atom ("|_|") and
If ("if _ then _ else _" 10) and
Rep_name ("\<lfloor>_\<rfloor>") and
Abs_name ("\<lceil>_\<rceil>") and
Rep_var ("\<lfloor>_\<rfloor>") and
Abs_var ("\<lceil>_\<rceil>") and
sort_of_ty ("sort'_ty _")
(* BH: uncomment if you really prefer the dot notation
syntax (latex output)
"_Collect" :: "pttrn => bool => 'a set" ("(1{_ . _})")
*)
(* sort is used in Lists for sorting *)
hide_const sort
abbreviation
"sort \<equiv> sort_of"
lemma infinite_collect:
assumes "\<forall>x \<in> S. P x" "infinite S"
shows "infinite {x \<in> S. P x}"
using assms
apply(subgoal_tac "infinite {x. x \<in> S}")
apply(simp only: Inf_many_def[symmetric])
apply(erule INFM_mono)
apply(auto)
done
(*>*)
section {* Introduction *}
text {*
Nominal Isabelle provides a proving infratructure for convenient reasoning
about syntax involving binders, such as lambda terms or type schemes in Mini-ML:
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
@{text "\<lambda>x. t \<forall>{x\<^isub>1,\<dots>, x\<^isub>n}. \<tau>"}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
At its core Nominal Isabelle is based on the nominal logic work by
Pitts at al \cite{GabbayPitts02,Pitts03}, whose most basic notion is
a sort-respecting permutation operation defined over a countably
infinite collection of sorted atoms.
The aim of this paper is to
describe how we adapted this work so that it can be implemented in a
theorem prover based on Higher-Order Logic (HOL). For this we
present the definition we made in the implementation and also review
many proofs. There are a two main design choices to be made. One is
how to represent sorted atoms. We opt here for a single unified atom
type to represent atoms of different sorts. The other is how to
present sort-respecting permutations. For them we use the standard
technique of HOL-formalisations of introducing an appropriate
substype of functions from atoms to atoms.
The nominal logic work has been the starting point for a number of proving
infrastructures, most notable by Norrish \cite{norrish04} in HOL4, by
Aydemir et al \cite{AydemirBohannonWeirich07} in Coq and the work by Urban
and Berghofer in Isabelle/HOL \cite{Urban08}. Its key attraction is a very
general notion, called \emph{support}, for the `set of free variables, or
atoms, of an object' that applies not just to lambda terms and type schemes,
but also to sets, products, lists, booleans and even functions. The notion of support
is derived from the permutation operation defined over the
hierarchy of types. This
permutation operation, written @{text "_ \<bullet> _"}, has proved to be much more
convenient for reasoning about syntax, in comparison to, say, arbitrary
renaming substitutions of atoms. One reason is that permutations are
bijective renamings of atoms and thus they can be easily `undone'---namely
by applying the inverse permutation. A corresponding inverse substitution
might not always exist, since renaming substitutions are in general only injective.
Another reason is that permutations preserve many constructions when reasoning about syntax.
For example, suppose a typing context @{text "\<Gamma>"} of the form
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
@{text "x\<^isub>1:\<tau>\<^isub>1, \<dots>, x\<^isub>n:\<tau>\<^isub>n"}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
is said to be \emph{valid} provided none of its variables, or atoms, @{text "x\<^isub>i"}
occur twice. Then validity of typing contexts is preserved under
permutations in the sense that if @{text \<Gamma>} is valid then so is \mbox{@{text "\<pi> \<bullet> \<Gamma>"}} for
all permutations @{text "\<pi>"}. Again, this is \emph{not} the case for arbitrary
renaming substitutions, as they might identify some of the @{text "x\<^isub>i"} in @{text \<Gamma>}.
Permutations also behave uniformly with respect to HOL's logic connectives.
Applying a permutation to a formula gives, for example
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}lcl}
@{term "\<pi> \<bullet> (A \<and> B)"} & if and only if & @{text "(\<pi> \<bullet> A) \<and> (\<pi> \<bullet> B)"}\\
@{term "\<pi> \<bullet> (A \<longrightarrow> B)"} & if and only if & @{text "(\<pi> \<bullet> A) \<longrightarrow> (\<pi> \<bullet> B)"}\\
\end{tabular}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
This uniform behaviour can also be extended to quantifiers and functions.
Because of these good properties of permutations, we are able to automate
reasoning to do with \emph{equivariance}. By equivariance we mean the property
that every permutation leaves a function unchanged, that is @{term "\<pi> \<bullet> f = f"}
for all @{text "\<pi>"}. This will often simplify arguments involving support
of functions, since if they are equivariant then they have empty support---or
`no free atoms'.
There are a number of subtle differences between the nominal logic work by
Pitts and the formalisation we will present in this paper. One difference
is that our
formalisation is compatible with HOL, in the sense that we only extend
HOL by some definitions, withouth the introduction of any new axioms.
The reason why the original nominal logic work is
incompatible with HOL has to do with the way how the finite support property
is enforced: FM-set theory is defined in \cite{Pitts01b} so that every set
in the FM-set-universe has finite support. In nominal logic \cite{Pitts03},
the axioms (E3) and (E4) imply that every function symbol and proposition
has finite support. However, there are notions in HOL that do \emph{not}
have finite support (we will give some examples). In our formalisation, we
will avoid the incompatibility of the original nominal logic work by not a
priory restricting our discourse to only finitely supported entities, rather
we will explicitly assume this property whenever it is needed in proofs. One
consequence is that we state our basic definitions not in terms of nominal
sets (as done for example in \cite{Pitts06}), but in terms of the weaker
notion of permutation types---essentially sets equipped with a ``sensible''
notion of permutation operation.
In the nominal logic woworkrk, the `new quantifier' plays a prominent role.
$\new$
Obstacles for Coq; no type-classes, difficulties with quotient types,
need for classical reasoning
Two binders
A preliminary version
*}
section {* Sorted Atoms and Sort-Respecting Permutations *}
text {*
The two most basic notions in the nominal logic work are a countably
infinite collection of sorted atoms and sort-respecting permutations
of atoms. The atoms are used for representing variable names that
might be bound or free. Multiple sorts are necessary for being able
to represent different kinds of variables. For example, in the
language Mini-ML there are bound term variables in lambda
abstractions and bound type variables in type schemes. In order to
be able to separate them, each kind of variables needs to be
represented by a different sort of atoms.
The existing nominal logic work usually leaves implicit the sorting
information for atoms and leaves out a description of how sorts are
represented. In our formalisation, we therefore have to make a
design decision about how to implement sorted atoms and
sort-respecting permutations. One possibility, which we described in
\cite{Urban08}, is to have separate types for different sorts of
atoms. However, we found that this does not blend well with
type-classes in Isabelle/HOL (see Section~\ref{related} about
related work). Therefore we use here a single unified atom type to
represent atoms of different sorts. A basic requirement is that
there must be a countably infinite number of atoms of each sort.
This can be implemented in Isabelle/HOL as the datatype
*}
datatype atom\<iota> = Atom\<iota> string nat
text {*
\noindent
whereby the string argument specifies the sort of the
atom.\footnote{A similar design choice was made by Gunter et al
\cite{GunterOsbornPopescu09} for their variables.} The use of type
\emph{string} for sorts is merely for convenience; any countably
infinite type would work as well. In what follows we shall write
@{term "UNIV::atom set"} for the set of all atoms. We also have two
auxiliary functions for atoms, namely @{text sort} and @{const
nat_of} which are defined as
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}c@ {\hspace{2mm}}l}
@{thm (lhs) sort_of.simps[no_vars]} & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) sort_of.simps[no_vars]}\\
@{thm (lhs) nat_of.simps[no_vars]} & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) nat_of.simps[no_vars]}
\end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{sortnatof}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
We clearly have for every finite set @{text S}
of atoms and every sort @{text s} the property:
\begin{proposition}\label{choosefresh}\mbox{}\\
@{text "For a finite set of atoms S, there exists an atom a such that
sort a = s and a \<notin> S"}.
\end{proposition}
\noindent
This property will be used later whenever we have to chose a `fresh' atom.
For implementing sort-respecting permutations, we use functions of type @{typ
"atom => atom"} that are bijective; are the
identity on all atoms, except a finite number of them; and map
each atom to one of the same sort. These properties can be conveniently stated
in Isabelle/HOL for a function @{text \<pi>} as follows:
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{r@ {\hspace{4mm}}l}
i) & @{term "bij \<pi>"}\\
ii) & @{term "finite {a. \<pi> a \<noteq> a}"}\\
iii) & @{term "\<forall>a. sort (\<pi> a) = sort a"}
\end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{permtype}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
Like all HOL-based theorem provers, Isabelle/HOL allows us to
introduce a new type @{typ perm} that includes just those functions
satisfying all three properties. For example the identity function,
written @{term id}, is included in @{typ perm}. Also function composition,
written \mbox{@{text "_ \<circ> _"}}, and function inversion, given by Isabelle/HOL's
inverse operator and written \mbox{@{text "inv _"}}, preserve the properties
(\ref{permtype}.@{text "i"}-@{text "iii"}).
However, a moment of thought is needed about how to construct non-trivial
permutations. In the nominal logic work it turned out to be most convenient
to work with swappings, written @{text "(a b)"}. In our setting the
type of swappings must be
@{text [display,indent=10] "(_ _) :: atom \<Rightarrow> atom \<Rightarrow> perm"}
\noindent
but since permutations are required to respect sorts, we must carefully
consider what happens if a user states a swapping of atoms with different
sorts. The following definition\footnote{To increase legibility, we omit
here and in what follows the @{term Rep_perm} and @{term "Abs_perm"}
wrappers that are needed in our implementation in Isabelle/HOL since we defined permutation
not to be the full function space, but only those functions of type @{typ
perm} satisfying properties @{text i}-@{text "iii"} in \eqref{permtype}.}
@{text [display,indent=10] "(a b) \<equiv> \<lambda>c. if a = c then b else (if b = c then a else c)"}
\noindent
does not work in general, because @{text a} and @{text b} may have different
sorts---in which case the function would violate property @{text iii} in \eqref{permtype}. We
could make the definition of swappings partial by adding the precondition
@{term "sort a = sort b"}, which would mean that in case @{text a} and
@{text b} have different sorts, the value of @{text "(a b)"} is unspecified.
However, this looked like a cumbersome solution, since sort-related side
conditions would be required everywhere, even to unfold the definition. It
turned out to be more convenient to actually allow the user to state
`ill-sorted' swappings but limit their `damage' by defaulting to the
identity permutation in the ill-sorted case:
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}rl}
@{text "(a b) \<equiv>"} & @{text "if (sort a = sort b)"}\\
& \hspace{3mm}@{text "then \<lambda>c. if a = c then b else (if b = c then a else c)"}\\
& \hspace{3mm}@{text "else id"}
\end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{swapdef}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
This function is bijective, the identity on all atoms except
@{text a} and @{text b}, and sort respecting. Therefore it is
a function in @{typ perm}.
One advantage of using functions as a representation for
permutations is that it is a unique representation. For example the swappings
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
@{thm swap_commute[no_vars]}\hspace{10mm}
@{text "(a a) = id"}
\end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{swapeqs}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
are \emph{equal} and can be used interchangeably. Another advantage of the function
representation is that they form a (non-com\-mu\-ta\-tive) group provided we define
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}c@ {\hspace{2mm}}l@ {\hspace{10mm}}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}c@ {\hspace{2mm}}l}
@{thm (lhs) zero_perm_def[no_vars]} & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) zero_perm_def[no_vars]} &
@{thm (lhs) plus_perm_def[where p="\<pi>\<^isub>1" and q="\<pi>\<^isub>2"]} & @{text "\<equiv>"} &
@{thm (rhs) plus_perm_def[where p="\<pi>\<^isub>1" and q="\<pi>\<^isub>2"]}\\
@{thm (lhs) uminus_perm_def[where p="\<pi>"]} & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{thm (rhs) uminus_perm_def[where p="\<pi>"]} &
@{thm (lhs) minus_perm_def[where ?p1.0="\<pi>\<^isub>1" and ?p2.0="\<pi>\<^isub>2"]} & @{text "\<equiv>"} &
@{thm (rhs) minus_perm_def[where ?p1.0="\<pi>\<^isub>1" and ?p2.0="\<pi>\<^isub>2"]}
\end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{groupprops}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
and verify the four simple properties
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
i)~~@{thm add_assoc[where a="\<pi>\<^isub>1" and b="\<pi>\<^isub>2" and c="\<pi>\<^isub>3"]}\\
ii)~~@{thm monoid_add_class.add_0_left[where a="\<pi>::perm"]} \hspace{9mm}
iii)~~@{thm monoid_add_class.add_0_right[where a="\<pi>::perm"]} \hspace{9mm}
iv)~~@{thm group_add_class.left_minus[where a="\<pi>::perm"]}
\end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{grouplaws}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
The technical importance of this fact is that we can rely on
Isabelle/HOL's existing simplification infrastructure for groups, which will
come in handy when we have to do calculations with permutations.
Note that Isabelle/HOL defies standard conventions of mathematical notation
by using additive syntax even for non-commutative groups. Obviously,
composition of permutations is not commutative in general; for example
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
@{text "(a b) + (b c) \<noteq> (b c) + (a b)"}\;.
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
But since the point of this paper is to implement the
nominal theory as smoothly as possible in Isabelle/HOL, we tolerate
the non-standard notation in order to reuse the existing libraries.
A \emph{permutation operation}, written infix as @{text "\<pi> \<bullet> x"},
applies a permutation @{text "\<pi>"} to an object @{text "x"}. This
operation has the type
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
@{text "_ \<bullet> _ :: perm \<Rightarrow> \<beta> \<Rightarrow> \<beta>"}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
whereby @{text "\<beta>"} is a generic type for the object @{text
x}.\footnote{We will use the standard notation @{text "((op \<bullet>) \<pi>)
x"} for this operation in the few cases where we need to indicate
that it is a function applied with two arguments.} The definition
of this operation will be given by in terms of `induction' over this
generic type. The type-class mechanism of Isabelle/HOL
\cite{Wenzel04} allows us to give a definition for `base' types,
such as atoms, permutations, booleans and natural numbers:
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {\hspace{4mm}}l@ {}}
atoms: & @{thm permute_atom_def[where p="\<pi>",no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]}\\
permutations: & @{thm permute_perm_def[where p="\<pi>" and q="\<pi>'", THEN eq_reflection]}\\
booleans: & @{thm permute_bool_def[where p="\<pi>", no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]}\\
nats: & @{thm permute_nat_def[where p="\<pi>", no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]}\\
\end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{permdefsbase}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
and for type-constructors, such as functions, sets, lists and products:
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {\hspace{4mm}}l@ {}}
functions: & @{text "\<pi> \<bullet> f \<equiv> \<lambda>x. \<pi> \<bullet> (f ((-\<pi>) \<bullet> x))"}\\
sets: & @{thm permute_set_eq[where p="\<pi>", no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]}\\
lists: & @{thm permute_list.simps(1)[where p="\<pi>", no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]}\\
& @{thm permute_list.simps(2)[where p="\<pi>", no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]}\\
products: & @{thm permute_prod.simps[where p="\<pi>", no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]}\\
\end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{permdefsconstrs}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
The type classes also allow us to reason abstractly about the permutation operation.
For this we state the following two
\emph{permutation properties}:
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}r@ {\hspace{4mm}}p{10cm}}
i) & @{thm permute_zero[no_vars]}\\
ii) & @{thm permute_plus[where p="\<pi>\<^isub>1" and q="\<pi>\<^isub>2",no_vars]}
\end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{newpermprops}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
From these properties and law (\ref{grouplaws}.{\it iv}) about groups
follows that a permutation and its inverse cancel each other. That is
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
@{thm permute_minus_cancel(1)[where p="\<pi>", no_vars]}\hspace{10mm}
@{thm permute_minus_cancel(2)[where p="\<pi>", no_vars]}
\end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{cancel}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
Consequently, the permutation operation @{text "\<pi> \<bullet> _"}~~is bijective,
which in turn implies the property
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
@{thm (lhs) permute_eq_iff[where p="\<pi>", no_vars]}
$\;$if and only if$\;$
@{thm (rhs) permute_eq_iff[where p="\<pi>", no_vars]}.
\end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{permuteequ}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
We can also show that the following property holds for the permutation
operation.
\begin{lemma}\label{permutecompose}
@{text "\<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> (\<pi>\<^isub>2 \<bullet> x) = (\<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> \<pi>\<^isub>2) \<bullet> (\<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> x)"}.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof} The proof is as follows:
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}[b]{@ {}c@ {\hspace{2mm}}l@ {\hspace{8mm}}l}
& @{text "\<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> \<pi>\<^isub>2 \<bullet> x"}\\
@{text "="} & @{text "\<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> \<pi>\<^isub>2 \<bullet> (-\<pi>\<^isub>1) \<bullet> \<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> x"} & by \eqref{cancel}\\
@{text "="} & @{text "(\<pi>\<^isub>1 + \<pi>\<^isub>2 - \<pi>\<^isub>1) \<bullet> (\<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> x)"} & by {\rm(\ref{newpermprops}.@{text "ii"})}\\
@{text "\<equiv>"} & @{text "(\<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> \<pi>\<^isub>2) \<bullet> (\<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> x)"}\\
\end{tabular}\hfill\qed
\end{isabelle}
\end{proof}
\noindent
Note that the permutation operation for functions is defined so that
we have for applications the equation
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
@{text "\<pi> \<bullet> (f x) ="}
@{thm (rhs) permute_fun_app_eq[where p="\<pi>", no_vars]}
\hfill\numbered{permutefunapp}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
provided the permutation properties hold for @{text x}. This equation can
be easily shown by unfolding the permutation operation for functions on
the right-hand side of the equation, simplifying the resulting beta-redex
and eliminating the permutations in front of @{text x} using \eqref{cancel}.
The main benefit of the use of type classes is that it allows us to delegate
much of the routine resoning involved in determining whether the permutation properties
are satisfied to Isabelle/HOL's type system: we only have to
establish that base types satisfy them and that type-constructors
preserve them. Then Isabelle/HOL will use this information and determine
whether an object @{text x} with a compound type, like @{typ "atom \<Rightarrow> (atom set * nat)"}, satisfies the
permutation properties. For this we define the notion of a
\emph{permutation type}:
\begin{definition}[Permutation Type]
A type @{text "\<beta>"} is a \emph{permutation type} if the permutation
properties in \eqref{newpermprops} are satisfied for every @{text
"x"} of type @{text "\<beta>"}.
\end{definition}
\noindent
and establish:
\begin{theorem}
The types @{type atom}, @{type perm}, @{type bool} and @{type nat}
are permutation types, and if @{text \<beta>}, @{text "\<beta>\<^isub>1"} and @{text
"\<beta>\<^isub>2"} are permutation types, then so are \mbox{@{text "\<beta>\<^isub>1 \<Rightarrow> \<beta>\<^isub>2"}},
@{text "\<beta> set"}, @{text "\<beta> list"} and @{text "\<beta>\<^isub>1 \<times> \<beta>\<^isub>2"}.
\end{theorem}
\begin{proof}
All statements are by unfolding the definitions of the permutation
operations and simple calculations involving addition and
minus. In case of permutations for example we have
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}[b]{@ {}rcl}
@{text "0 \<bullet> \<pi>'"} & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{text "0 + \<pi>' - 0 = \<pi>'"}\smallskip\\
@{text "(\<pi>\<^isub>1 + \<pi>\<^isub>2) \<bullet> \<pi>'"} & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{text "(\<pi>\<^isub>1 + \<pi>\<^isub>2) + \<pi>' - (\<pi>\<^isub>1 + \<pi>\<^isub>2)"}\\
& @{text "="} & @{text "(\<pi>\<^isub>1 + \<pi>\<^isub>2) + \<pi>' - \<pi>\<^isub>2 - \<pi>\<^isub>1"}\\
& @{text "="} & @{text "\<pi>\<^isub>1 + (\<pi>\<^isub>2 + \<pi>' - \<pi>\<^isub>2) - \<pi>\<^isub>1"}\\
& @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{text "\<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> \<pi>\<^isub>2 \<bullet> \<pi>'"}
\end{tabular}\hfill\qed
\end{isabelle}
\end{proof}
*}
section {* Equivariance *}
text {*
Two important notions in the nominal logic work are what Pitts calls
\emph{equivariance} and the \emph{equivariance principle}. These
notions allows us to characterise how permutations act upon compound
statements in HOL by analysing how these statements are constructed.
The notion of equivariance can defined as follows:
\begin{definition}[Equivariance]\label{equivariance}
An object @{text "x"} of permutation type is \emph{equivariant} provided
for all permutations @{text "\<pi>"}, \mbox{@{term "\<pi> \<bullet> x = x"}} holds.
\end{definition}
\noindent
In what follows we will primarily be interested in the cases where
@{text x} is a constant, but of course there is no way in
Isabelle/HOL to restrict this definition to just these cases.
There are a number of equivalent formulations for the equivariance
property. For example, assuming @{text f} is a function of permutation
type @{text "\<alpha> \<Rightarrow> \<beta>"}, then equivariance of @{text f} can also be stated as
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
@{text "\<forall>\<pi> x. \<pi> \<bullet> (f x) = f (\<pi> \<bullet> x)"}
\end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{altequivariance}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
We will call this formulation of equivariance in \emph{fully applied form}.
To see that this formulation implies the definition, we just unfold
the definition of the permutation operation for functions and
simplify with the equation and the cancellation property shown in
\eqref{cancel}. To see the other direction, we use
\eqref{permutefunapp}. Similarly for functions that take more than
one argument. The point to note is that equivariance and equivariance in fully
applied form are always interderivable (for permutation types).
Both formulations of equivariance have their advantages and
disadvantages: \eqref{altequivariance} is usually more convenient to
establish, since statements in HOL are commonly given in a
form where functions are fully applied. For example we can easily
show that equality is equivariant
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
@{thm eq_eqvt[where p="\<pi>", no_vars]}
\end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{eqeqvt}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
using the permutation operation on booleans and property
\eqref{permuteequ}.
Lemma~\ref{permutecompose} establishes that the
permutation operation is equivariant. The permutation operation for
lists and products, shown in \eqref{permdefsconstrs}, state that the
constructors for products, @{text "Nil"} and @{text Cons} are
equivariant. Furthermore a simple calculation will show that our
swapping functions are equivariant, that is
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
@{thm swap_eqvt[where p="\<pi>", no_vars]}
\end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{swapeqvt}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
for all @{text a}, @{text b} and @{text \<pi>}. Also the booleans
@{const True} and @{const False} are equivariant by the definition
of the permutation operation for booleans. Given this definition, it
is also easy to see that the boolean operators, like @{text "\<and>"},
@{text "\<or>"}, @{text "\<longrightarrow>"} and @{text "\<not>"} are equivariant:
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}lcl}
@{text "\<pi> \<bullet> (A \<and> B) = (\<pi> \<bullet> A) \<and> (\<pi> \<bullet> B)"}\\
@{text "\<pi> \<bullet> (A \<or> B) = (\<pi> \<bullet> A) \<or> (\<pi> \<bullet> B)"}\\
@{text "\<pi> \<bullet> (A \<longrightarrow> B) = (\<pi> \<bullet> A) \<longrightarrow> (\<pi> \<bullet> B)"}\\
@{text "\<pi> \<bullet> (\<not>A) = \<not>(\<pi> \<bullet> A)"}\\
\end{tabular}
\end{isabelle}
In contrast, the advantage of Definition \ref{equivariance} is that
it allows us to state a general principle how permutations act on
statements in HOL. For this we will define a rewrite system that
`pushes' a permutation towards the leaves of statements (i.e.~constants
and variables). Then the permutations disappear in cases where the
constants are equivariant. To do so, let us first define
\emph{HOL-terms}, which are the building blocks of statements in HOL.
They are given by the grammar
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
@{text "t ::= c | x | t\<^isub>1 t\<^isub>2 | \<lambda>x. t"}
\hfill\numbered{holterms}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
where @{text c} stands for constants and @{text x} for variables.
We assume HOL-terms are fully typed, but for the sake of better
legibility we leave the typing information implicit. We also assume
the usual notions for free and bound variables of a HOL-term.
Furthermore, HOL-terms are regarded as equal modulo alpha-, beta-
and eta-equivalence. The equivariance principle can now be stated
formally as follows:
\begin{theorem}[Equivariance Principle]\label{eqvtprin}
Suppose a HOL-term @{text t} whose constants are all equivariant. For any
permutation @{text \<pi>}, let @{text t'} be @{text t} except every
free variable @{text x} in @{term t} is replaced by @{text "\<pi> \<bullet> x"}, then
@{text "\<pi> \<bullet> t = t'"}.
\end{theorem}
\noindent
The significance of this principle is that we can automatically establish
the equivariance of a constant for which equivariance is not yet
known. For this we only have to make sure that the definiens of this
constant is a HOL-term whose constants are all equivariant. For example
the universal quantifier @{text "\<forall>"} is definied in HOL as
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
@{text "\<forall>x. P x \<equiv> "}~@{thm (rhs) All_def[no_vars]}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
The constants in the definiens @{thm (rhs) All_def[no_vars]}, namely @{text "="}
and @{text "True"}, are equivariant (we shown this above). Therefore
the equivariance principle gives us
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
@{text "\<pi> \<bullet> (\<forall>x. P x) \<equiv> \<pi> \<bullet> (P = (\<lambda>x. True)) = ((\<pi> \<bullet> P) = (\<lambda>x. True)) \<equiv> \<forall>x. (\<pi> \<bullet> P) x"}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
which means the constant @{text "\<forall>"} must be equivariant. From this
we can deduce that the existential quantifier @{text "\<exists>"} is equivariant.
Its definition in HOL is
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
@{text "\<exists>x. P x \<equiv> "}~@{thm (rhs) Ex_def[no_vars]}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
where again the HOL-term on the right-hand side only contains equivariant constants
(namely @{text "\<forall>"} and @{text "\<longrightarrow>"}). Taking both facts together, we can deduce that
the unique existential quantifier @{text "\<exists>!"} is equivariant. Its definition
is
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
@{text "\<exists>!x. P x \<equiv> "}~@{thm (rhs) Ex1_def[no_vars]}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
with all constants on the right-hand side being equivariant. With this kind
of reasoning we can build up a database of equivariant constants.
Before we proceed, let us give a justification for the equivariance principle.
This justification cannot be given directly inside Isabelle/HOL since we cannot
prove any statement about HOL-terms. Instead, we will use a rewrite
system consisting of a series of equalities
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
@{text "\<pi> \<cdot> t = ... = t'"}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
that establish the equality between @{term "\<pi> \<bullet> t"} and
@{text "t'"}. The idea of the rewrite system is to push the
permutation inside the term @{text t}. We have implemented this as a
conversion tactic on the ML-level of Isabelle/HOL. In what follows,
we will show that this tactic produces only finitely many equations
and also show that is correct (in the sense of pushing a permutation
@{text "\<pi>"} inside a term and the only remaining instances of @{text
"\<pi>"} are in front of the term's free variables). The tactic applies
four `oriented' equations. We will first give a naive version of
this tactic, which however in some cornercases produces incorrect
results or does not terminate. We then give a modification in order
to obtain the desired properties.
Consider the following for oriented equations
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}lr@ {\hspace{3mm}}c@ {\hspace{3mm}}l}
i) & @{text "\<pi> \<bullet> (t\<^isub>1 t\<^isub>2)"} & \rrh & @{term "(\<pi> \<bullet> t\<^isub>1) (\<pi> \<bullet> t\<^isub>2)"}\\
ii) & @{text "\<pi> \<bullet> (\<lambda>x. t)"} & \rrh & @{text "\<lambda>x. \<pi> \<bullet> (t[x := (-\<pi>) \<bullet> x])"}\\
iii) & @{term "\<pi> \<bullet> (- \<pi>) \<bullet> x"} & \rrh & @{term "x"}\\
iv) & @{term "\<pi> \<bullet> c"} & \rrh &
{\rm @{term "c"}\hspace{6mm}provided @{text c} is equivariant}\\
\end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{rewriteapplam}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
These equation are oriented in the sense of being applied in the left-to-right
direction. The first equation we established in \eqref{permutefunapp};
the second follows from the definition of permutations acting on functions
and the fact that HOL-terms are equal modulo beta-equivalence.
The third is a consequence of \eqref{cancel} and the fourth from
Definition~\ref{equivariance}. Unfortunately, we have to be careful with
the rules {\it i)} and {\it iv}) since they can lead to a loop whenever
\mbox{@{text "t\<^isub>1 t\<^isub>2"}} is of the form @{text "((op \<bullet>) \<pi>') t"}.\footnote{Note we
deviate here from our usual convention of writing the permutation operation infix,
instead as an application.} Recall that we established in Lemma \ref{permutecompose} that the
constant @{text "(op \<bullet>)"} is equivariant and consider the infinite
reduction sequence
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
@{text "\<pi> \<bullet> (\<pi>' \<bullet> t)"}
$\;\;\stackrel{\text{\it i)}}{\rrh}\stackrel{\text{\it i)}}{\rrh}\stackrel{\text{\it iv)}}{\rrh}\;\;$
@{text "(\<pi> \<bullet> \<pi>') \<bullet> (\<pi> \<bullet> t)"}
$\;\;\stackrel{\text{\it i)}}{\rrh}\stackrel{\text{\it i)}}{\rrh}\stackrel{\text{\it iv)}}{\rrh}\;\;$
@{text "((\<pi> \<bullet> \<pi>') \<bullet> \<pi>) \<bullet> ((\<pi> \<bullet> \<pi>') \<bullet> t)"}~~\ldots%
\end{tabular}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
where the last term is again an instance of rewrite rule {\it i}), but bigger.
To avoid this loop we will apply the rewrite rule
using an `outside to inside' strategy. This strategy is sufficient
since we are only interested of rewriting terms of the form @{term
"\<pi> \<bullet> t"}, where an outermost permutation needs to pushed inside a term.
Another problem we have to avoid is that the rules {\it i)} and {\it
iii)} can `overlap'. For this note that the term @{term "\<pi>
\<bullet>(\<lambda>x. x)"} reduces by {\it ii)} to @{term "\<lambda>x. \<pi> \<bullet> (- \<pi>) \<bullet> x"}, to
which we can apply rule {\it iii)} in order to obtain @{term
"\<lambda>x. x"}, as is desired---since there is no free variable in the original
term. the permutation should completely vanish. However, the
subterm @{text "(- \<pi>) \<bullet> x"} is also an application. Consequently,
the term @{term "\<lambda>x. \<pi> \<bullet> (- \<pi>) \<bullet>x"} can also reduce to @{text "\<lambda>x. (- (\<pi>
\<bullet> \<pi>)) \<bullet> (\<pi> \<bullet> x)"} using {\it i)}. Given our strategy, we cannot
apply rule {\it iii)} anymore in order to eliminate the permutation.
In contrast, if we start
with the term @{text "\<pi> \<bullet> ((- \<pi>) \<bullet> x)"} where @{text \<pi>} and @{text
x} are free variables, then we \emph{do} want to apply rule {\it i)}
in order to obtain @{text "(\<pi> \<bullet> (- \<pi>)) \<bullet> (\<pi> \<bullet> x)"}
and not rule {\it iii)}. The latter would eliminate @{text \<pi>}
completely and thus violating our correctness property. The problem is that
rule {\it iii)} should only apply to
instances where the corresponding variable is to bound; for free variables we want
to use {\it ii)}. In order to distinguish these cases we have to
maintain the information which variable is bound when inductively
taking a term `apart'. This, unfortunately, does not mesh well with
the way how conversion tactics are implemented in Isabelle/HOL.
Our remedy is to use a standard trick in HOL: we introduce a
separate definition for terms of the form @{text "(- \<pi>) \<bullet> x"},
namely as
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
@{term "unpermute \<pi> x \<equiv> (- \<pi>) \<bullet> x"}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
The point is that now we can re-formulate the rewrite rules as follows
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}lrcl}
i') & @{text "\<pi> \<bullet> (t\<^isub>1 t\<^isub>2)"} & \rrh &
@{term "(\<pi> \<bullet> t\<^isub>1) (\<pi> \<bullet> t\<^isub>2)"}\hspace{45mm}\mbox{}\\
\multicolumn{4}{r}{\rm provided @{text "t\<^isub>1 t\<^isub>2"} is not of the form @{text "unpermute \<pi> x"}}\smallskip\\
ii') & @{text "\<pi> \<bullet> (\<lambda>x. t)"} & \rrh & @{text "\<lambda>x. \<pi> \<bullet> (t[x := unpermute \<pi> x])"}\\
iii') & @{text "\<pi> \<bullet> (unpermute \<pi> x)"} & \rrh & @{term x}\\
iv') & @{term "\<pi> \<bullet> c"} & \rrh & @{term "c"}
\hspace{6mm}{\rm provided @{text c} is equivariant}\\
\end{tabular}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
where @{text unpermutes} are only generated in case of bound variables.
Clearly none of these rules overlap. Moreover, given our
outside-to-inside strategy, applying them repeatedly must terminate.
To see this, notice that
the permutation on the right-hand side of the rewrite rules is
always applied to a smaller term, provided we take the measure consisting
of lexicographically ordered pairs whose first component is the size
of a term (counting terms of the form @{text "unpermute \<pi> x"} as
leaves) and the second is the number of occurences of @{text
"unpermute \<pi> x"} and @{text "\<pi> \<bullet> c"}.
With the rewrite rules of the conversions tactic in place, we can
establish its correctness. The property we are after is that
for a HOL-term @{text t} whose constants are all equivariant the
term \mbox{@{text "\<pi> \<bullet> t"}} is equal to @{text "t'"} with @{text "t'"}
being equal to @{text t} except that every free variable @{text x}
in @{text t} is replaced by \mbox{@{text "\<pi> \<bullet> x"}}. Let us call
a variable @{text x} \emph{really free}, if it is free and not occuring
in an @{term unpermute}, such as @{text "unpermute _ x"} and @{text "unpermute x _"}.
We need the following technical notion characterising \emph{@{text "\<pi>"}-proper} HOL-terms
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}ll}
$\bullet$ & variables and constants are @{text \<pi>}-proper,\\
$\bullet$ & @{term "unpermute \<pi> x"} is @{text \<pi>}-proper,\\
$\bullet$ & @{term "\<lambda>x. t"} is @{text \<pi>}-proper, if @{text t} is @{text \<pi>}-proper and @{text x} is
really free in @{text t}, and\\
$\bullet$ & @{term "t\<^isub>1 t\<^isub>2"} is @{text \<pi>}-proper, if @{text "t\<^isub>1"} and @{text "t\<^isub>2"} are
@{text \<pi>}-proper.
\end{tabular}
\end{isabelle}
\begin{proof}[Theorem~\ref{eqvtprin}] We establish the property if @{text t}
is @{text \<pi>}-proper and only contains equivaraint constants, then
@{text "\<pi> \<bullet> t = t'"} where @{text "t'"} is equal to @{text "t"} except all really
free variables @{text x} are replaced by @{text "\<pi> \<bullet> x"}, and all semi-free variables
@{text "unpermute \<pi> x"} by @{text "x"}. We establish this property by induction
on the size of HOL-terms, counting terms like @{text "unpermuting \<pi> x"} as leafes,
like variables and constants. The cases for variables, constants and @{text unpermutes}
are routine. In the case of abstractions we have by induction hypothesis that
@{text "\<pi> \<bullet> (t[x := unpermute \<pi> x]) = t'"} with @{text "t'"} satisfying our
correctness property. This implies that @{text "\<lambda>x. \<pi> \<bullet> (t[x := unpermute \<pi> x]) = \<lambda>x. t'"}
and hence @{text "\<pi> \<bullet> (\<lambda>x. t) = \<lambda>x. t'"} as needed.\hfill\qed
\end{proof}
Pitts calls this property \emph{equivariance principle} (book ref ???).
Problems with @{text undefined}
Lines of code
*}
section {* Support and Freshness *}
text {*
The most original aspect of the nominal logic work of Pitts is a general
definition for `the set of free variables, or free atoms, of an object @{text "x"}'. This
definition is general in the sense that it applies not only to lambda terms,
but to any type for which a permutation operation is defined
(like lists, sets, functions and so on).
\begin{definition}[Support] \label{support}
Given @{text x} is of permutation type, then
@{thm [display,indent=10] supp_def[no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]}
\end{definition}
\noindent
(Note that due to the definition of swapping in \eqref{swapdef}, we do not
need to explicitly restrict @{text a} and @{text b} to have the same sort.)
There is also the derived notion for when an atom @{text a} is \emph{fresh}
for an @{text x} of permutation type, defined as
@{thm [display,indent=10] fresh_def[no_vars]}
\noindent
We also use the notation @{thm (lhs) fresh_star_def[no_vars]} for sets ot atoms
defined as follows
@{thm [display,indent=10] fresh_star_def[no_vars]}
\noindent
Using the equivariance principle, it can be easily checked that all three notions
are equivariant. A simple consequence of the definition of support and equivariance
is that if @{text x} is equivariant then we have
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
@{thm (concl) supp_fun_eqvt[where f="x", no_vars]}
\end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{suppeqvtfun}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
For function applications we can establish the following two properties.
\begin{lemma}\label{suppfunapp} Let @{text f} and @{text x} be of permutation type, then
\begin{isabelle}
\begin{tabular}{r@ {\hspace{4mm}}p{10cm}}
{\it i)} & @{thm[mode=IfThen] fresh_fun_app[no_vars]}\\
{\it ii)} & @{thm supp_fun_app[no_vars]}\\
\end{tabular}
\end{isabelle}
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
For the first property, we know from the assumption that @{term
"finite {b. (a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> f \<noteq> f}"} and @{term "finite {b . (a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> x \<noteq>
x}"} hold. That means for all, but finitely many @{text b} we have
@{term "(a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> f = f"} and @{term "(a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> x = x"}. Similarly,
we have to show that for but, but finitely @{text b} the equation
@{term "(a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> f x = f x"} holds. The left-hand side of this
equation is equal to @{term "((a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> f) ((a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> x)"} by
\eqref{permutefunapp}, which we know by the previous two facts for
@{text f} and @{text x} is equal to the right-hand side for all,
but finitely many @{text b}. This establishes the first
property. The second is a simple corollary of {\it i)} by
unfolding the definition of freshness.\qed
\end{proof}
A striking consequence of the definitions for support and freshness
is that we can prove without knowing anything about the structure of
@{term x} that swapping two fresh atoms, say @{text a} and @{text
b}, leave @{text x} unchanged. For the proof we use the following
lemma about swappings applied to an @{text x}:
\begin{lemma}\label{swaptriple}
Assuming @{text x} is of permutation type, and @{text a}, @{text b} and @{text c}
have the same sort, then \mbox{@{thm (prem 3) swap_rel_trans[no_vars]}} and
@{thm (prem 4) swap_rel_trans[no_vars]} imply @{thm (concl) swap_rel_trans[no_vars]}.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
The cases where @{text "a = c"} and @{text "b = c"} are immediate.
For the remaining case it is, given our assumptions, easy to calculate
that the permutations
@{thm [display,indent=10] (concl) swap_triple[no_vars]}
\noindent
are equal. The lemma is then by application of the second permutation
property shown in~\eqref{newpermprops}.\qed
\end{proof}
\begin{theorem}\label{swapfreshfresh}
Let @{text x} be of permutation type.
@{thm [mode=IfThen] swap_fresh_fresh[no_vars]}
\end{theorem}
\begin{proof}
If @{text a} and @{text b} have different sort, then the swapping is the identity.
If they have the same sort, we know by definition of support that both
@{term "finite {c. (a \<rightleftharpoons> c) \<bullet> x \<noteq> x}"} and @{term "finite {c. (b \<rightleftharpoons> c) \<bullet> x \<noteq> x}"}
hold. So the union of these sets is finite too, and we know by Proposition~\ref{choosefresh}
that there is an atom @{term c}, with the same sort as @{term a} and @{term b},
that satisfies \mbox{@{term "(a \<rightleftharpoons> c) \<bullet> x = x"}} and @{term "(b \<rightleftharpoons> c) \<bullet> x = x"}.
Now the theorem follows from Lemma~\ref{swaptriple}.\hfill\qed
\end{proof}
While the abstract properties of support and freshness, particularly
Theorem~\ref{swapfreshfresh}, are useful for developing Nominal Isabelle,
one often has to calculate the support of concrete objects.
For booleans, nats, products and lists it is easy to check that
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {\hspace{4mm}}l@ {}}
@{text "booleans"}: & @{term "supp b = {}"}\\
@{text "nats"}: & @{term "supp n = {}"}\\
@{text "products"}: & @{thm supp_Pair[no_vars]}\\
@{text "lists:"} & @{thm supp_Nil[no_vars]}\\
& @{thm supp_Cons[no_vars]}\\
\end{tabular}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
hold. Establishing the support of atoms and permutations is a bit
trickier. To do so we will use the following notion about a \emph{supporting set}.
\begin{definition}[Supporting Set]
A set @{text S} \emph{supports} @{text x} if for all atoms @{text a} and @{text b}
not in @{text S} we have @{term "(a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> x = x"}.
\end{definition}
\noindent
The main motivation for this notion is that we can characterise @{text "supp x"}
as the smallest finite set that supports @{text "x"}. For this we prove:
\begin{lemma}\label{supports} Let @{text x} be of permutation type.
\begin{isabelle}
\begin{tabular}{r@ {\hspace{4mm}}p{10cm}}
i) & @{thm[mode=IfThen] supp_is_subset[no_vars]}\\
ii) & @{thm[mode=IfThen] supp_supports[no_vars]}\\
iii) & @{thm (concl) supp_is_least_supports[no_vars]}
provided @{thm (prem 1) supp_is_least_supports[no_vars]},
@{thm (prem 2) supp_is_least_supports[no_vars]}
and @{text "S"} is the least such set, that means formally,
for all @{text "S'"}, if @{term "finite S'"} and
@{term "S' supports x"} then @{text "S \<subseteq> S'"}.
\end{tabular}
\end{isabelle}
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
For {\it i)} we derive a contradiction by assuming there is an atom @{text a}
with @{term "a \<in> supp x"} and @{text "a \<notin> S"}. Using the second fact, the
assumption that @{term "S supports x"} gives us that @{text S} is a superset of
@{term "{b. (a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> x \<noteq> x}"}, which is finite by the assumption of @{text S}
being finite. But this means @{term "a \<notin> supp x"}, contradicting our assumption.
Property {\it ii)} is by a direct application of
Theorem~\ref{swapfreshfresh}. For the last property, part {\it i)} proves
one ``half'' of the claimed equation. The other ``half'' is by property
{\it ii)} and the fact that @{term "supp x"} is finite by {\it i)}.\hfill\qed
\end{proof}
\noindent
These are all relatively straightforward proofs adapted from the existing
nominal logic work. However for establishing the support of atoms and
permutations we found the following `optimised' variant of {\it iii)}
more useful:
\begin{lemma}\label{optimised} Let @{text x} be of permutation type.
We have that @{thm (concl) finite_supp_unique[no_vars]}
provided @{thm (prem 1) finite_supp_unique[no_vars]},
@{thm (prem 2) finite_supp_unique[no_vars]}, and for
all @{text "a \<in> S"} and all @{text "b \<notin> S"}, with @{text a}
and @{text b} having the same sort, \mbox{@{term "(a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> x \<noteq> x"}}
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
By Lemma \ref{supports}@{text ".iii)"} we have to show that for every finite
set @{text S'} that supports @{text x}, \mbox{@{text "S \<subseteq> S'"}} holds. We will
assume that there is an atom @{text "a"} that is element of @{text S}, but
not @{text "S'"} and derive a contradiction. Since both @{text S} and
@{text S'} are finite, we can by Proposition \ref{choosefresh} obtain an atom
@{text b}, which has the same sort as @{text "a"} and for which we know
@{text "b \<notin> S"} and @{text "b \<notin> S'"}. Since we assumed @{text "a \<notin> S'"} and
we have that @{text "S' supports x"}, we have on one hand @{term "(a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> x
= x"}. On the other hand, the fact @{text "a \<in> S"} and @{text "b \<notin> S"} imply
@{term "(a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> x \<noteq> x"} using the assumed implication. This gives us the
contradiction.\hfill\qed
\end{proof}
\noindent
Using this lemma we only have to show the following three proof-obligations
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}r@ {\hspace{4mm}}l}
i) & @{term "{c} supports c"}\\
ii) & @{term "finite {c}"}\\
iii) & @{text "\<forall>a \<in> {c} b \<notin> {c}. sort a = sort b \<longrightarrow> (a b) \<bullet> c \<noteq> c"}
\end{tabular}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
in order to establish that @{thm supp_atom[where a="c", no_vars]} holds. In
Isabelle/HOL these proof-obligations can be discharged by easy
simplifications. Similar proof-obligations arise for the support of
permutations, which is
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
@{thm supp_perm[where p="\<pi>", no_vars]}
\end{tabular}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
The only proof-obligation that is
interesting is the one where we have to show that
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
@{text "If \<pi> \<bullet> a \<noteq> a, \<pi> \<bullet> b = b and sort a = sort b, then (a b) \<bullet> \<pi> \<noteq> \<pi>"}.
\end{tabular}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
For this we observe that
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}rcl}
@{thm (lhs) perm_swap_eq[where p="\<pi>", no_vars]} &
if and only if &
@{thm (rhs) perm_swap_eq[where p="\<pi>", no_vars]}
\end{tabular}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
holds by a simple calculation using the group properties of permutations.
The proof-obligation can then be discharged by analysing the inequality
between the permutations @{term "(\<pi> \<bullet> a \<rightleftharpoons> b)"} and @{term "(a \<rightleftharpoons> b)"}.
The main point about support is that whenever an object @{text x} has finite
support, then Proposition~\ref{choosefresh} allows us to choose for @{text x} a
fresh atom with arbitrary sort. This is a crucial operation in Nominal
Isabelle in situations where, for example, a bound variable needs to be
renamed. To allow such a choice, we only have to assume that
@{text "finite (supp x)"} holds. For more convenience we
can define a type class in Isabelle/HOL corresponding to the
property:
\begin{definition}[Finitely Supported Type]
A type @{text "\<beta>"} is \emph{finitely supported} if @{term "finite (supp x)"}
holds for all @{text x} of type @{text "\<beta>"}.
\end{definition}
\noindent
By the calculations above we can easily establish
\begin{theorem}\label{finsuptype}
The types @{type atom}, @{type perm}, @{type bool} and @{type nat}
are fintitely supported, and assuming @{text \<beta>}, @{text "\<beta>\<^isub>1"} and
@{text "\<beta>\<^isub>2"} are finitely supported types, then @{text "\<beta> list"} and
@{text "\<beta>\<^isub>1 \<times> \<beta>\<^isub>2"} are finitely supported.
\end{theorem}
\noindent
The main benefit of using the finite support property for choosing a
fresh atom is that the reasoning is `compositional'. To see this,
assume we have a list of atoms and a method of choosing a fresh atom
that is not a member in this list---for example the maximum plus
one. Then if we enlarge this list \emph{after} the choice, then
obviously the fresh atom might not be fresh anymore. In contrast, by
the classical reasoning of Proposition~\ref{choosefresh} we know a
fresh atom exists for every list of atoms and no matter how we
extend this list of atoms, we always preserve the property of being
finitely supported. Consequently the existence of a fresh atom is
still guarantied by Proposition~\ref{choosefresh}. Using the method
of `maximum plus one' we might have to adapt the choice of a fresh
atom.
Unfortunately, Theorem~\ref{finsuptype} does not work in general for the
types of sets and functions. There are functions definable in HOL
for which the finite support property does not hold. A simple
example of a function with infinite support is @{const nat_of} shown
in \eqref{sortnatof}. This function's support is the set of
\emph{all} atoms @{term "UNIV::atom set"}. To establish this we
show @{term "\<not> a \<sharp> nat_of"}. This is equivalent to assuming the set
@{term "{b. (a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> nat_of \<noteq> nat_of}"} is finite and deriving a
contradiction. From the assumption we also know that @{term "{a} \<union>
{b. (a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> nat_of \<noteq> nat_of}"} is finite. Then we can use
Proposition~\ref{choosefresh} to choose an atom @{text c} such that
@{term "c \<noteq> a"}, @{term "sort_of c = sort_of a"} and @{term "(a \<rightleftharpoons> c)
\<bullet> nat_of = nat_of"}. Now we can reason as follows:
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}[b]{@ {}rcl@ {\hspace{5mm}}l}
@{text "nat_of a"} & @{text "="} & @{text "(a \<rightleftharpoons> c) \<bullet> (nat_of a)"} & by def.~of permutations on nats\\
& @{text "="} & @{term "((a \<rightleftharpoons> c) \<bullet> nat_of) ((a \<rightleftharpoons> c) \<bullet> a)"} & by \eqref{permutefunapp}\\
& @{text "="} & @{term "nat_of c"} & by assumptions on @{text c}\\
\end{tabular}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
But this means we have that @{term "nat_of a = nat_of c"} and @{term "sort_of a = sort_of c"}.
This implies that atoms @{term a} and @{term c} must be equal, which clashes with our
assumption @{term "c \<noteq> a"} about how we chose @{text c}.\footnote{Cheney \cite{Cheney06}
gives similar examples for constructions that have infinite support.}
*}
section {* Support of Finite Sets *}
text {*
Also the set type is an instance whose elements are not generally finitely
supported (we will give an example in Section~\ref{concrete}).
However, we can easily show that finite sets and co-finite sets of atoms are finitely
supported. Their support can be characterised as:
\begin{lemma}\label{finatomsets}
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}[b]{@ {}rl}
{\it i)} & If @{text S} is a finite set of atoms, then @{thm (concl) supp_finite_atom_set[no_vars]}.\\
{\it ii)} & If @{term "UNIV - (S::atom set)"} is a finite set of atoms, then
@{thm (concl) supp_cofinite_atom_set[no_vars]}.
\end{tabular}
\end{isabelle}
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
Both parts can be easily shown by Lemma~\ref{optimised}. We only have to observe
that a swapping @{text "(a b)"} leaves a set @{text S} unchanged provided both
@{text a} and @{text b} are elements in @{text S} or both are not in @{text S}.
However if the sorts of a @{text a} and @{text b} agree, then the swapping will
change @{text S} if either of them is an element in @{text S} and the other is
not.\hfill\qed
\end{proof}
\noindent
Note that a consequence of the second part of this lemma is that
@{term "supp (UNIV::atom set) = {}"}.
More difficult, however, is it to establish that finite sets of finitely
supported objects are finitely supported. For this we first show that
the union of the supports of finitely many and finitely supported objects
is finite, namely
\begin{lemma}\label{unionsupp}
If @{text S} is a finite set whose elements are all finitely supported, then
%
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}[b]{@ {}rl}
{\it i)} & @{thm (concl) Union_of_finite_supp_sets[no_vars]} and\\
{\it ii)} & @{thm (concl) Union_included_in_supp[no_vars]}.
\end{tabular}
\end{isabelle}
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
The first part is by a straightforward induction on the finiteness
of @{text S}. For the second part, we know that @{term "\<Union>x\<in>S. supp
x"} is a set of atoms, which by the first part is finite. Therefore
we know by Lemma~\ref{finatomsets}.{\it i)} that @{term "(\<Union>x\<in>S. supp
x) = supp (\<Union>x\<in>S. supp x)"}. Taking @{text "f"} to be the function
\mbox{@{text "\<lambda>S. \<Union> (supp ` S)"}}, we can write the right-hand side
as @{text "supp (f S)"}. Since @{text "f"} is an equivariant
function (can be easily checked by the equivariance principle), we
have that @{text "supp (f S) \<subseteq> supp S"} by
Lemma~\ref{suppfunapp}.{\it ii)}. This completes the second
part.\hfill\qed
\end{proof}
\noindent
With this lemma in place we can establish that
\begin{lemma}
@{thm[mode=IfThen] supp_of_finite_sets[no_vars]}
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
The right-to-left inclusion is proved in Lemma~\ref{unionsupp}.{\it ii)}. To show the inclusion
in the other direction we can use Lemma~\ref{supports}.{\it i)}. This means
for all @{text a} and @{text b} that are not in @{text S} we have to show that
@{term "(a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> (\<Union>x \<in> S. supp x) = (\<Union>x \<in> S. supp x)"} holds. By the equivariance
principle, the left-hand side is equal to @{term "\<Union>x \<in> ((a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> S). supp x"}. Now
the swapping in front of @{text S} disappears, since @{term "a \<sharp> S"} and @{term "b \<sharp> S"}
whenever @{text "a, b \<notin> S"}. Thus we are done.\hfill\qed
\end{proof}
\noindent
To sum up, every finite set of finitely supported elements has
finite support. Unfortunately, we cannot use
Theorem~\ref{finsuptype} to let Isabelle/HOL find this out
automatically. This would require to introduce a separate type of
finite sets, which however is not so convenient to reason about as
Isabelle's standard set type.
*}
section {* Induction Principles for Permutations *}
text {*
While the use of functions as permutation provides us with a unique
representation for permutations (for example @{term "(a \<rightleftharpoons> b)"} and
@{term "(b \<rightleftharpoons> a)"} are equal permutations), this representation does
not come automatically with an induction principle. Such an
induction principle is however handy for generalising
Lemma~\ref{swapfreshfresh} from swappings to permutations
\begin{lemma}
@{thm [mode=IfThen] perm_supp_eq[no_vars]}
\end{lemma}
\noindent
In this section we will establish an induction principle for permutations
with which this lemma can be easily proved. It is not too difficult to derive
an induction principle for permutations, given the fact that we allow only
permutations having a finite support.
Using a the property from \cite{???}
\begin{lemma}\label{smallersupp}
@{thm [mode=IfThen] smaller_supp[no_vars]}
\end{lemma}
*}
section {* An Abstraction Type *}
text {*
To that end, we will consider
first pairs @{text "(as, x)"} of type @{text "(atom set) \<times> \<beta>"}. These pairs
are intended to represent the abstraction, or binding, of the set of atoms @{text
"as"} in the body @{text "x"}.
The first question we have to answer is when two pairs @{text "(as, x)"} and
@{text "(bs, y)"} are $\alpha$-equivalent? (For the moment we are interested in
the notion of $\alpha$-equivalence that is \emph{not} preserved by adding
vacuous binders.) To answer this question, we identify four conditions: {\it (i)}
given a free-atom function @{text "fa"} of type \mbox{@{text "\<beta> \<Rightarrow> atom
set"}}, then @{text x} and @{text y} need to have the same set of free
atoms; moreover there must be a permutation @{text p} such that {\it
(ii)} @{text p} leaves the free atoms of @{text x} and @{text y} unchanged, but
{\it (iii)} ``moves'' their bound names so that we obtain modulo a relation,
say \mbox{@{text "_ R _"}}, two equivalent terms. We also require that {\it (iv)}
@{text p} makes the sets of abstracted atoms @{text as} and @{text bs} equal. The
requirements {\it (i)} to {\it (iv)} can be stated formally as follows:
%
\begin{equation}\label{alphaset}
\begin{array}{@ {\hspace{10mm}}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l@ {\hspace{4mm}}r}
\multicolumn{3}{l}{@{text "(as, x) \<approx>set R fa p (bs, y)"}\hspace{2mm}@{text "\<equiv>"}}\\[1mm]
& @{term "fa(x) - as = fa(y) - bs"} & \mbox{\it (i)}\\
@{text "\<and>"} & @{term "(fa(x) - as) \<sharp>* p"} & \mbox{\it (ii)}\\
@{text "\<and>"} & @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"} & \mbox{\it (iii)}\\
@{text "\<and>"} & @{term "(p \<bullet> as) = bs"} & \mbox{\it (iv)}\\
\end{array}
\end{equation}
\noindent
Note that this relation depends on the permutation @{text
"p"}; $\alpha$-equivalence between two pairs is then the relation where we
existentially quantify over this @{text "p"}. Also note that the relation is
dependent on a free-atom function @{text "fa"} and a relation @{text
"R"}. The reason for this extra generality is that we will use
$\approx_{\,\textit{set}}$ for both ``raw'' terms and $\alpha$-equated terms. In
the latter case, @{text R} will be replaced by equality @{text "="} and we
will prove that @{text "fa"} is equal to @{text "supp"}.
It might be useful to consider first some examples about how these definitions
of $\alpha$-equivalence pan out in practice. For this consider the case of
abstracting a set of atoms over types (as in type-schemes). We set
@{text R} to be the usual equality @{text "="} and for @{text "fa(T)"} we
define
\begin{center}
@{text "fa(x) = {x}"} \hspace{5mm} @{text "fa(T\<^isub>1 \<rightarrow> T\<^isub>2) = fa(T\<^isub>1) \<union> fa(T\<^isub>2)"}
\end{center}
\noindent
Now recall the examples shown in \eqref{ex1}, \eqref{ex2} and
\eqref{ex3}. It can be easily checked that @{text "({x, y}, x \<rightarrow> y)"} and
@{text "({y, x}, y \<rightarrow> x)"} are $\alpha$-equivalent according to
$\approx_{\,\textit{set}}$ and $\approx_{\,\textit{res}}$ by taking @{text p} to
be the swapping @{term "(x \<rightleftharpoons> y)"}. In case of @{text "x \<noteq> y"}, then @{text
"([x, y], x \<rightarrow> y)"} $\not\approx_{\,\textit{list}}$ @{text "([y, x], x \<rightarrow> y)"}
since there is no permutation that makes the lists @{text "[x, y]"} and
@{text "[y, x]"} equal, and also leaves the type \mbox{@{text "x \<rightarrow> y"}}
unchanged. Another example is @{text "({x}, x)"} $\approx_{\,\textit{res}}$
@{text "({x, y}, x)"} which holds by taking @{text p} to be the identity
permutation. However, if @{text "x \<noteq> y"}, then @{text "({x}, x)"}
$\not\approx_{\,\textit{set}}$ @{text "({x, y}, x)"} since there is no
permutation that makes the sets @{text "{x}"} and @{text "{x, y}"} equal
(similarly for $\approx_{\,\textit{list}}$). It can also relatively easily be
shown that all three notions of $\alpha$-equivalence coincide, if we only
abstract a single atom.
In the rest of this section we are going to introduce three abstraction
types. For this we define
%
\begin{equation}
@{term "abs_set (as, x) (bs, x) \<equiv> \<exists>p. alpha_set (as, x) equal supp p (bs, x)"}
\end{equation}
\noindent
(similarly for $\approx_{\,\textit{abs\_res}}$
and $\approx_{\,\textit{abs\_list}}$). We can show that these relations are equivalence
relations and equivariant.
\begin{lemma}\label{alphaeq}
The relations $\approx_{\,\textit{abs\_set}}$, $\approx_{\,\textit{abs\_list}}$
and $\approx_{\,\textit{abs\_res}}$ are equivalence relations, and if @{term
"abs_set (as, x) (bs, y)"} then also @{term "abs_set (p \<bullet> as, p \<bullet> x) (p \<bullet>
bs, p \<bullet> y)"} (similarly for the other two relations).
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
Reflexivity is by taking @{text "p"} to be @{text "0"}. For symmetry we have
a permutation @{text p} and for the proof obligation take @{term "-p"}. In case
of transitivity, we have two permutations @{text p} and @{text q}, and for the
proof obligation use @{text "q + p"}. All conditions are then by simple
calculations.
\end{proof}
\noindent
This lemma allows us to use our quotient package for introducing
new types @{text "\<beta> abs_set"}, @{text "\<beta> abs_res"} and @{text "\<beta> abs_list"}
representing $\alpha$-equivalence classes of pairs of type
@{text "(atom set) \<times> \<beta>"} (in the first two cases) and of type @{text "(atom list) \<times> \<beta>"}
(in the third case).
The elements in these types will be, respectively, written as:
\begin{center}
@{term "Abs_set as x"} \hspace{5mm}
@{term "Abs_res as x"} \hspace{5mm}
@{term "Abs_lst as x"}
\end{center}
\noindent
indicating that a set (or list) of atoms @{text as} is abstracted in @{text x}. We will
call the types \emph{abstraction types} and their elements
\emph{abstractions}. The important property we need to derive is the support of
abstractions, namely:
\begin{theorem}[Support of Abstractions]\label{suppabs}
Assuming @{text x} has finite support, then\\[-6mm]
\begin{center}
\begin{tabular}{l@ {\hspace{2mm}}c@ {\hspace{2mm}}l}
%@ {thm (lhs) supp_abs(1)[no_vars]} & $=$ & @ {thm (rhs) supp_abs(1)[no_vars]}\\
%@ {thm (lhs) supp_abs(2)[no_vars]} & $=$ & @ {thm (rhs) supp_abs(2)[no_vars]}\\
%@ {thm (lhs) supp_abs(3)[where bs="as", no_vars]} & $=$ & @ {thm (rhs) supp_abs(3)[where bs="as", no_vars]}
\end{tabular}
\end{center}
\end{theorem}
\noindent
Below we will show the first equation. The others
follow by similar arguments. By definition of the abstraction type @{text "abs_set"}
we have
%
\begin{equation}\label{abseqiff}
%@ {thm (lhs) abs_eq_iff(1)[where bs="as" and cs="bs", no_vars]} \;\;\text{if and only if}\;\;
%@ {thm (rhs) abs_eq_iff(1)[where bs="as" and cs="bs", no_vars]}
\end{equation}
\noindent
and also
%
\begin{equation}\label{absperm}
@{thm permute_Abs[no_vars]}
\end{equation}
\noindent
The second fact derives from the definition of permutations acting on pairs
\eqref{permute} and $\alpha$-equivalence being equivariant
(see Lemma~\ref{alphaeq}). With these two facts at our disposal, we can show
the following lemma about swapping two atoms in an abstraction.
\begin{lemma}
%@ {thm[mode=IfThen] abs_swap1(1)[where bs="as", no_vars]}
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
This lemma is straightforward using \eqref{abseqiff} and observing that
the assumptions give us @{term "(a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> (supp x - as) = (supp x - as)"}.
Moreover @{text supp} and set difference are equivariant (see \cite{HuffmanUrban10}).
\end{proof}
\noindent
Assuming that @{text "x"} has finite support, this lemma together
with \eqref{absperm} allows us to show
%
\begin{equation}\label{halfone}
%@ {thm abs_supports(1)[no_vars]}
\end{equation}
\noindent
which by Property~\ref{supportsprop} gives us ``one half'' of
Theorem~\ref{suppabs}. The ``other half'' is a bit more involved. To establish
it, we use a trick from \cite{Pitts04} and first define an auxiliary
function @{text aux}, taking an abstraction as argument:
%
\begin{center}
@{thm supp_set.simps[THEN eq_reflection, no_vars]}
\end{center}
\noindent
Using the second equation in \eqref{equivariance}, we can show that
@{text "aux"} is equivariant (since @{term "p \<bullet> (supp x - as) =
(supp (p \<bullet> x)) - (p \<bullet> as)"}) and therefore has empty support.
This in turn means
%
\begin{center}
@{term "supp (supp_gen (Abs_set as x)) \<subseteq> supp (Abs_set as x)"}
\end{center}
\noindent
using \eqref{suppfun}. Assuming @{term "supp x - as"} is a finite set,
we further obtain
%
\begin{equation}\label{halftwo}
%@ {thm (concl) supp_abs_subset1(1)[no_vars]}
\end{equation}
\noindent
since for finite sets of atoms, @{text "bs"}, we have
@{thm (concl) supp_finite_atom_set[where S="bs", no_vars]}.
Finally, taking \eqref{halfone} and \eqref{halftwo} together establishes
Theorem~\ref{suppabs}.
The method of first considering abstractions of the
form @{term "Abs_set as x"} etc is motivated by the fact that
we can conveniently establish at the Isabelle/HOL level
properties about them. It would be
laborious to write custom ML-code that derives automatically such properties
for every term-constructor that binds some atoms. Also the generality of
the definitions for $\alpha$-equivalence will help us in the next section.
*}
section {* Concrete Atom Types\label{concrete} *}
text {*
So far, we have presented a system that uses only a single multi-sorted atom
type. This design gives us the flexibility to define operations and prove
theorems that are generic with respect to atom sorts. For example, as
illustrated above the @{term supp} function returns a set that includes the
free atoms of \emph{all} sorts together.
However, the single multi-sorted atom type does not make an ideal interface
for end-users of Nominal Isabelle. If sorts are not distinguished by
Isabelle's type system, users must reason about atom sorts manually. That
means for example that subgoals involving sorts must be discharged explicitly within proof
scripts, instead of being inferred automatically. In other
cases, lemmas might require additional side conditions about sorts to be true.
For example, swapping @{text a} and @{text b} in the pair \mbox{@{term "(a,
b)"}} will only produce the expected result if we state the lemma in
Isabelle/HOL as:
*}
lemma
fixes a b :: "atom"
assumes asm: "sort a = sort b"
shows "(a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> (a, b) = (b, a)"
using asm by simp
text {*
\noindent
Fortunately, it is possible to regain most of the type-checking automation
that is lost by moving to a single atom type. We accomplish this by defining
\emph{subtypes} of the generic atom type that only include atoms of a single
specific sort. We call such subtypes \emph{concrete atom types}.
The following Isabelle/HOL command defines a concrete atom type called
\emph{name}, which consists of atoms whose sort equals the string @{term
"''name''"}.
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\isacommand{typedef}\ \ @{typ name} = @{term "{a. sort\<iota> a = ''name''}"}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
This command automatically generates injective functions that map from the
concrete atom type into the generic atom type and back, called
representation and abstraction functions, respectively. We will write these
functions as follows:
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {\hspace{10mm}}l}
@{text "\<lfloor>_\<rfloor> :: name \<Rightarrow> atom"} &
@{text "\<lceil>_\<rceil> :: atom \<Rightarrow> name"}
\end{tabular}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
With the definition @{thm permute_name_def [where p="\<pi>", THEN
eq_reflection, no_vars]}, it is straightforward to verify that the type
@{typ name} is a permutation type.
In order to reason uniformly about arbitrary concrete atom types, we define a
type class that characterises type @{typ name} and other similarly-defined
types. The definition of the concrete atom type class is as follows: First,
every concrete atom type must be a permutation type. In addition, the class
defines an overloaded function that maps from the concrete type into the
generic atom type, which we will write @{text "|_|"}. For each class
instance, this function must be injective and equivariant, and its outputs
must all have the same sort, that is
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}r@ {\hspace{3mm}}l}
i) & if @{thm (lhs) atom_eq_iff [no_vars]} then @{thm (rhs) atom_eq_iff [no_vars]}\\
ii) & @{thm atom_eqvt[where p="\<pi>", no_vars]}\\
iii) & @{thm sort_of_atom_eq [no_vars]}
\end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{atomprops}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
With the definition @{thm atom_name_def [THEN eq_reflection, no_vars]} we can
show that @{typ name} satisfies all the above requirements of a concrete atom
type.
The whole point of defining the concrete atom type class is to let users
avoid explicit reasoning about sorts. This benefit is realised by defining a
special swapping operation of type @{text "\<alpha> \<Rightarrow> \<alpha>
\<Rightarrow> perm"}, where @{text "\<alpha>"} is a concrete atom type:
@{thm [display,indent=10] flip_def [THEN eq_reflection, no_vars]}
\noindent
As a consequence of its type, the @{text "\<leftrightarrow>"}-swapping
operation works just like the generic swapping operation, but it does not
require any sort-checking side conditions---the sort-correctness is ensured by
the types! For @{text "\<leftrightarrow>"} we can establish the following
simplification rule:
@{thm [display,indent=10] permute_flip_at[no_vars]}
\noindent
If we now want to swap the \emph{concrete} atoms @{text a} and @{text b}
in the pair @{term "(a, b)"} we can establish the lemma as follows:
*}
lemma
fixes a b :: "name"
shows "(a \<leftrightarrow> b) \<bullet> (a, b) = (b, a)"
by simp
text {*
\noindent
There is no need to state an explicit premise involving sorts.
We can automate the process of creating concrete atom types, so that users
can define a new one simply by issuing the command
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
\isacommand{atom\_decl}~~@{text "name"}
\end{tabular}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
This command can be implemented using less than 100 lines of custom ML-code.
*}
section {* Related Work\label{related} *}
text {*
Coq-tries, but failed
Add here comparison with old work.
In comparison, the old version of Nominal Isabelle included more than 1000
lines of ML-code for creating concrete atom types, and for defining various
type classes and instantiating generic lemmas for them. In addition to
simplifying the ML-code, the setup here also offers user-visible improvements:
Now concrete atoms can be declared at any point of a formalisation, and
theories that separately declare different atom types can be merged
together---it is no longer required to collect all atom declarations in one
place.
Using a single atom type to represent atoms of different sorts and
representing permutations as functions are not new ideas; see
\cite{GunterOsbornPopescu09} \footnote{function rep.} The main contribution
of this paper is to show an example of how to make better theorem proving
tools by choosing the right level of abstraction for the underlying
theory---our design choices take advantage of Isabelle's type system, type
classes and reasoning infrastructure. The novel technical contribution is a
mechanism for dealing with ``Church-style'' lambda-terms \cite{Church40} and
HOL-based languages \cite{PittsHOL4} where variables and variable binding
depend on type annotations.
The paper is organised as follows\ldots
The main point is that the above reasoning blends smoothly with the reasoning
infrastructure of Isabelle/HOL; no custom ML-code is necessary and a single
type class suffices.
With this
design one can represent permutations as lists of pairs of atoms and the
operation of applying a permutation to an object as the function
@{text [display,indent=10] "_ \<bullet> _ :: (\<alpha> \<times> \<alpha>) list \<Rightarrow> \<beta> \<Rightarrow> \<beta>"}
\noindent
where @{text "\<alpha>"} stands for a type of atoms and @{text "\<beta>"} for the type
of the objects on which the permutation acts. For atoms
the permutation operation is defined over the length of lists as follows
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}c@ {\hspace{2mm}}l}
@{text "[] \<bullet> c"} & @{text "="} & @{text c}\\
@{text "(a b)::\<pi> \<bullet> c"} & @{text "="} &
$\begin{cases} @{text a} & \textrm{if}~@{text "\<pi> \<bullet> c = b"}\\
@{text b} & \textrm{if}~@{text "\<pi> \<bullet> c = a"}\\
@{text "\<pi> \<bullet> c"} & \textrm{otherwise}\end{cases}$
\end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{atomperm}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
where we write @{text "(a b)"} for a swapping of atoms @{text "a"} and
@{text "b"}. For atoms with different type than the permutation, we
define @{text "\<pi> \<bullet> c \<equiv> c"}.
With the separate atom types and the list representation of permutations it
is impossible in systems like Isabelle/HOL to state an ``ill-sorted''
permutation, since the type system excludes lists containing atoms of
different type. However, a disadvantage is that whenever we need to
generalise induction hypotheses by quantifying over permutations, we have to
build quantifications like
@{text [display,indent=10] "\<forall>\<pi>\<^isub>1 \<dots> \<forall>\<pi>\<^isub>n. \<dots>"}
\noindent
where the @{text "\<pi>\<^isub>i"} are of type @{text "(\<alpha>\<^isub>i \<times> \<alpha>\<^isub>i) list"}.
The reason is that the permutation operation behaves differently for
every @{text "\<alpha>\<^isub>i"} and the type system does not allow use to have a
single quantification to stand for all permutations. Similarly, the
notion of support
@{text [display,indent=10] "supp _ :: \<beta> \<Rightarrow> \<alpha> set"}
\noindent
which we will define later, cannot be
used to express the support of an object over \emph{all} atoms. The reason
is that support can behave differently for each @{text
"\<alpha>\<^isub>i"}. This problem is annoying, because if we need to know in
a statement that an object, say @{text "x"}, is finitely supported we end up
with having to state premises of the form
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
@{text "finite ((supp x) :: \<alpha>\<^isub>1 set) , \<dots>, finite ((supp x) :: \<alpha>\<^isub>n set)"}
\end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{fssequence}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
Because of these disadvantages, we will use in this paper a single unified atom type to
represent atoms of different sorts. Consequently, we have to deal with the
case that a swapping of two atoms is ill-sorted: we cannot rely anymore on
the type systems to exclude them.
We also will not represent permutations as lists of pairs of atoms (as done in
\cite{Urban08}). Although an
advantage of this representation is that the basic operations on
permutations are already defined in Isabelle's list library: composition of
two permutations (written @{text "_ @ _"}) is just list append, and
inversion of a permutation (written @{text "_\<^sup>-\<^sup>1"}) is just
list reversal, and another advantage is that there is a well-understood
induction principle for lists, a disadvantage is that permutations
do not have unique representations as lists. We have to explicitly identify
them according to the relation
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
@{text "\<pi>\<^isub>1 \<sim> \<pi>\<^isub>2 \<equiv> \<forall>a. \<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> a = \<pi>\<^isub>2 \<bullet> a"}
\end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{permequ}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
This is a problem when lifting the permutation operation to other types, for
example sets, functions and so on. For this we need to ensure that every definition
is well-behaved in the sense that it satisfies some
\emph{permutation properties}. In the list representation we need
to state these properties as follows:
\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
\begin{tabular}{@ {}r@ {\hspace{4mm}}p{10cm}}
i) & @{text "[] \<bullet> x = x"}\\
ii) & @{text "(\<pi>\<^isub>1 @ \<pi>\<^isub>2) \<bullet> x = \<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> (\<pi>\<^isub>2 \<bullet> x)"}\\
iii) & if @{text "\<pi>\<^isub>1 \<sim> \<pi>\<^isub>2"} then @{text "\<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> x = \<pi>\<^isub>2 \<bullet> x"}
\end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{permprops}
\end{isabelle}
\noindent
where the last clause explicitly states that the permutation operation has
to produce the same result for related permutations. Moreover,
``permutations-as-lists'' do not satisfy the group properties. This means by
using this representation we will not be able to reuse the extensive
reasoning infrastructure in Isabelle about groups. Because of this, we will represent
in this paper permutations as functions from atoms to atoms. This representation
is unique and satisfies the laws of non-commutative groups.
*}
section {* Conclusion *}
text {*
This proof pearl describes a new formalisation of the nominal logic work by
Pitts et al. With the definitions we presented here, the formal reasoning blends
smoothly with the infrastructure of the Isabelle/HOL theorem prover.
Therefore the formalisation will be the underlying theory for a
new version of Nominal Isabelle.
The main difference of this paper with respect to existing work on Nominal
Isabelle is the representation of atoms and permutations. First, we used a
single type for sorted atoms. This design choice means for a term @{term t},
say, that its support is completely characterised by @{term "supp t"}, even
if the term contains different kinds of atoms. Also, whenever we have to
generalise an induction so that a property @{text P} is not just established
for all @{text t}, but for all @{text t} \emph{and} under all permutations
@{text \<pi>}, then we only have to state @{term "\<forall>\<pi>. P (\<pi> \<bullet> t)"}. The reason is
that permutations can now consist of multiple swapping each of which can
swap different kinds of atoms. This simplifies considerably the reasoning
involved in building Nominal Isabelle.
Second, we represented permutations as functions so that the associated
permutation operation has only a single type parameter. This is very convenient
because the abstract reasoning about permutations fits cleanly
with Isabelle/HOL's type classes. No custom ML-code is required to work
around rough edges. Moreover, by establishing that our permutations-as-functions
representation satisfy the group properties, we were able to use extensively
Isabelle/HOL's reasoning infrastructure for groups. This often reduced proofs
to simple calculations over @{text "+"}, @{text "-"} and @{text "0"}.
An interesting point is that we defined the swapping operation so that a
swapping of two atoms with different sorts is \emph{not} excluded, like
in our older work on Nominal Isabelle, but there is no ``effect'' of such
a swapping (it is defined as the identity). This is a crucial insight
in order to make the approach based on a single type of sorted atoms to work.
But of course it is analogous to the well-known trick of defining division by
zero to return zero.
We noticed only one disadvantage of the permutations-as-functions: Over
lists we can easily perform inductions. For permutations made up from
functions, we have to manually derive an appropriate induction principle. We
can establish such a principle, but we have no real experience yet whether ours
is the most useful principle: such an induction principle was not needed in
any of the reasoning we ported from the old Nominal Isabelle, except
when showing that if @{term "\<forall>a \<in> supp x. a \<sharp> p"} implies @{term "p \<bullet> x = x"}.
Finally, our implementation of sorted atoms turned out powerful enough to
use it for representing variables that carry on additional information, for
example typing annotations. This information is encoded into the sorts. With
this we can represent conveniently binding in ``Church-style'' lambda-terms
and HOL-based languages. While dealing with such additional information in
dependent type-theories, such as LF or Coq, is straightforward, we are not
aware of any other approach in a non-dependent HOL-setting that can deal
conveniently with such binders.
The formalisation presented here will eventually become part of the Isabelle
distribution, but for the moment it can be downloaded from the
Mercurial repository linked at
\href{http://isabelle.in.tum.de/nominal/download}
{http://isabelle.in.tum.de/nominal/download}.\smallskip
\noindent
{\bf Acknowledgements:} We are very grateful to Jesper Bengtson, Stefan
Berghofer and Cezary Kaliszyk for their comments on earlier versions
of this paper. We are also grateful to the anonymous referee who helped us to
put the work into the right context.
*}
(*<*)
end
(*>*)