Paper/Paper.thy
changeset 1657 d7dc35222afc
parent 1637 a5501c9fad9b
child 1662 e78cd33a246f
--- a/Paper/Paper.thy	Fri Mar 26 16:20:39 2010 +0100
+++ b/Paper/Paper.thy	Fri Mar 26 16:46:40 2010 +0100
@@ -3,15 +3,35 @@
 imports "../Nominal/Test" "LaTeXsugar"
 begin
 
+consts
+  fv :: "'a \<Rightarrow> 'b"
+  abs_set :: "'a \<Rightarrow> 'b \<Rightarrow> 'c" 
+  Abs_lst :: "'a \<Rightarrow> 'b \<Rightarrow> 'c"
+  Abs_res :: "'a \<Rightarrow> 'b \<Rightarrow> 'c"
+
+definition
+ "equal \<equiv> (op =)" 
+
 notation (latex output)
   swap ("'(_ _')" [1000, 1000] 1000) and
   fresh ("_ # _" [51, 51] 50) and
   fresh_star ("_ #* _" [51, 51] 50) and
   supp ("supp _" [78] 73) and
   uminus ("-_" [78] 73) and
-  If  ("if _ then _ else _" 10)
+  If  ("if _ then _ else _" 10) and
+  alpha_gen ("_ \<approx>\<^raw:\makebox[0mm][l]{$\,_{\textit{set}}$}>\<^bsup>_,_,_\<^esup> _") and
+  alpha_lst ("_ \<approx>\<^raw:\makebox[0mm][l]{$\,_{\textit{list}}$}>\<^bsup>_,_,_\<^esup> _") and
+  alpha_res ("_ \<approx>\<^raw:\makebox[0mm][l]{$\,_{\textit{res}}$}>\<^bsup>_,_,_\<^esup> _") and
+  abs_set ("_ \<approx>\<^raw:{$\,_{\textit{abs\_set}}$}> _") and
+  fv ("fv'(_')" [100] 100) and
+  equal ("=") and
+  alpha_abs ("_ \<approx>\<^raw:{$\,_{\textit{abs\_set}}$}> _") and 
+  Abs ("[_]\<^raw:$\!$>\<^bsub>set\<^esub>._") and
+  Abs_lst ("[_]\<^raw:$\!$>\<^bsub>list\<^esub>._") and
+  Abs_res ("[_]\<^raw:$\!$>\<^bsub>res\<^esub>._") 
 (*>*)
 
+
 section {* Introduction *}
 
 text {*
@@ -19,12 +39,12 @@
   alpha-equated terms, for example
 
   \begin{center}
-  $t ::= x \mid t\;t \mid \lambda x. t$
+  @{text "t ::= x | t t | \<lambda>x. t"}
   \end{center}
 
   \noindent
   where free and bound variables have names.  For such terms Nominal Isabelle
-  derives automatically a reasoning infrastructure that  has been used
+  derives automatically a reasoning infrastructure that has been used
   successfully in formalisations of an equivalence checking algorithm for LF
   \cite{UrbanCheneyBerghofer08}, Typed
   Scheme~\cite{TobinHochstadtFelleisen08}, several calculi for concurrency
@@ -39,7 +59,8 @@
   %
   \begin{equation}\label{tysch}
   \begin{array}{l}
-  T ::= x \mid T \rightarrow T \hspace{5mm} S ::= \forall \{x_1,\ldots, x_n\}. T
+  @{text "T ::= x | T \<rightarrow> T"}\hspace{5mm}
+  @{text "S ::= \<forall>{x\<^isub>1,\<dots>, x\<^isub>n}. T"}
   \end{array}
   \end{equation}
 
@@ -59,38 +80,38 @@
   we would like to regard the following two type-schemes as alpha-equivalent
   %
   \begin{equation}\label{ex1}
-  \forall \{x, y\}. x \rightarrow y  \;\approx_\alpha\; \forall \{y, x\}. y \rightarrow x 
+  @{text "\<forall>{x,y}. x \<rightarrow> y  \<approx>\<^isub>\<alpha>  \<forall>{y,x}. y \<rightarrow> x"} 
   \end{equation}
 
   \noindent
-  but assuming that $x$, $y$ and $z$ are distinct variables,
+  but assuming that @{text x}, @{text y} and @{text z} are distinct variables,
   the following two should \emph{not} be alpha-equivalent
   %
   \begin{equation}\label{ex2}
-  \forall \{x, y\}. x \rightarrow y  \;\not\approx_\alpha\; \forall \{z\}. z \rightarrow z 
+  @{text "\<forall>{x,y}. x \<rightarrow> y  \<notapprox>\<^isub>\<alpha>  \<forall>{z}. z \<rightarrow> z"} 
   \end{equation}
 
   \noindent
-  Moreover, we like to regard type-schemes as 
-  alpha-equivalent, if they differ only on \emph{vacuous} binders, such as
+  Moreover, we like to regard type-schemes as alpha-equivalent, if they differ
+  only on \emph{vacuous} binders, such as
   %
   \begin{equation}\label{ex3}
-  \forall \{x\}. x \rightarrow y  \;\approx_\alpha\; \forall \{x, z\}. x \rightarrow y
+  @{text "\<forall>{x}. x \<rightarrow> y  \<approx>\<^isub>\<alpha>  \<forall>{x,z}. x \<rightarrow> y"}
   \end{equation}
 
   \noindent
-  where $z$ does not occur freely in the type.
-  In this paper we will give a general binding mechanism and associated
-  notion of alpha-equivalence that can be used to faithfully represent
-  this kind of binding in Nominal Isabelle.  The difficulty of finding the right notion 
-  for alpha-equivalence can be appreciated in this case by considering that the 
-  definition given by Leroy in \cite{Leroy92} is incorrect (it omits a side-condition).
+  where @{text z} does not occur freely in the type.  In this paper we will
+  give a general binding mechanism and associated notion of alpha-equivalence
+  that can be used to faithfully represent this kind of binding in Nominal
+  Isabelle.  The difficulty of finding the right notion for alpha-equivalence
+  can be appreciated in this case by considering that the definition given by
+  Leroy in \cite{Leroy92} is incorrect (it omits a side-condition).
 
-  However, the notion of alpha-equivalence that is preserved by vacuous binders is not
-  always wanted. For example in terms like
+  However, the notion of alpha-equivalence that is preserved by vacuous
+  binders is not always wanted. For example in terms like
   %
   \begin{equation}\label{one}
-  \LET x = 3 \AND y = 2 \IN x\,-\,y \END
+  @{text "\<LET> x = 3 \<AND> y = 2 \<IN> x - y \<END>"}
   \end{equation}
 
   \noindent
@@ -99,7 +120,7 @@
   with
   %
   \begin{center}
-  $\LET x = 3 \AND y = 2 \AND z = loop \IN x\,-\,y \END$
+  @{text "\<LET> x = 3 \<AND> y = 2 \<AND> z = loop \<IN> x - y \<END>"}
   \end{center}
 
   \noindent
@@ -109,10 +130,10 @@
 
   However, we found that this is still not sufficient for dealing with
   language constructs frequently occurring in programming language
-  research. For example in $\mathtt{let}$s containing patterns
+  research. For example in @{text "\<LET>"}s containing patterns
   %
   \begin{equation}\label{two}
-  \LET (x, y) = (3, 2) \IN x\,-\,y \END
+  @{text "\<LET> (x, y) = (3, 2) \<IN> x - y \<END>"}
   \end{equation}
 
   \noindent
@@ -121,72 +142,79 @@
   we do not want to regard \eqref{two} as alpha-equivalent with
   %
   \begin{center}
-  $\LET (y, x) = (3, 2) \IN x\,- y\,\END$
+  @{text "\<LET> (y, x) = (3, 2) \<IN> x - y \<END>"}
   \end{center}
 
   \noindent
-  As a result, we provide three general binding mechanisms each of which binds multiple
-  variables at once, and let the user chose which one is intended when formalising a
-  programming language calculus.
+  As a result, we provide three general binding mechanisms each of which binds
+  multiple variables at once, and let the user chose which one is intended
+  when formalising a programming language calculus.
 
-  By providing these general binding mechanisms, however, we have to work around 
-  a problem that has been pointed out by Pottier \cite{Pottier06} and Cheney 
-  \cite{Cheney05}: in $\mathtt{let}$-constructs of the form
+  By providing these general binding mechanisms, however, we have to work
+  around a problem that has been pointed out by Pottier \cite{Pottier06} and
+  Cheney \cite{Cheney05}: in @{text "\<LET>"}-constructs of the form
   %
   \begin{center}
-  $\LET x_1 = t_1 \AND \ldots \AND x_n = t_n \IN s \END$
+  @{text "\<LET> x\<^isub>1 = t\<^isub>1 \<AND> \<dots> \<AND> x\<^isub>n = t\<^isub>n \<IN> s \<END>"}
   \end{center}
 
   \noindent
-  which bind all the $x_i$ in $s$, we might not care about the order in 
-  which the $x_i = t_i$ are given, but we do care about the information that there are 
-  as many $x_i$ as there are $t_i$. We lose this information if we represent the 
-  $\mathtt{let}$-constructor by something like 
+  which bind all the @{text "x\<^isub>i"} in @{text s}, we might not care
+  about the order in which the @{text "x\<^isub>i = t\<^isub>i"} are given,
+  but we do care about the information that there are as many @{text
+  "x\<^isub>i"} as there are @{text "t\<^isub>i"}. We lose this information if
+  we represent the @{text "\<LET>"}-constructor by something like
   %
   \begin{center}
-  $\LET [x_1,\ldots,x_n].s\;\; [t_1,\ldots,t_n]$
+  @{text "\<LET> [x\<^isub>1,\<dots>,x\<^isub>n].s [t\<^isub>1,\<dots>,t\<^isub>n]"}
   \end{center}
 
   \noindent
-  where the notation $[\_\!\_].\_\!\_$ indicates that the $x_i$ become bound
-  in $s$. In this representation the term \mbox{$\LET [x].s\;\;[t_1,t_2]$}
-  would be a perfectly legal instance. To exclude such terms, additional
-  predicates about well-formed terms are needed in order to ensure that the two
-  lists are of equal length. This can result into very messy reasoning (see
-  for example~\cite{BengtsonParow09}). To avoid this, we will allow type specifications
-  for $\mathtt{let}$s as follows
+  where the notation @{text "[_]._"} indicates that the @{text "x\<^isub>i"}
+  become bound in @{text s}. In this representation the term 
+  \mbox{@{text "\<LET> [x].s [t\<^isub>1,t\<^isub>2]"}} would be a perfectly legal
+  instance. To exclude such terms, additional predicates about well-formed
+  terms are needed in order to ensure that the two lists are of equal
+  length. This can result into very messy reasoning (see for
+  example~\cite{BengtsonParow09}). To avoid this, we will allow type
+  specifications for $\mathtt{let}$s as follows
   %
   \begin{center}
   \begin{tabular}{r@ {\hspace{2mm}}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l}
-  $trm$ & $::=$  & \ldots\\ 
-        & $\mid$ & $\mathtt{let}\;a\!::\!assn\;\;s\!::\!trm\quad\mathtt{bind}\;bn\,(a) \IN s$\\[1mm]
-  $assn$ & $::=$  & $\mathtt{anil}$\\
-         & $\mid$ & $\mathtt{acons}\;\;name\;\;trm\;\;assn$
+  @{text trm} & @{text "::="}  & @{text "\<dots>"}\\ 
+              & @{text "|"}    & @{text "\<LET> a::assn s::trm"}\hspace{4mm} 
+                                 \isacommand{bind} @{text "bn(a)"} \isacommand{in} @{text "s"}\\[1mm]
+  @{text assn} & @{text "::="} & @{text "\<ANIL>"}\\
+               & @{text "|"}   & @{text "\<ACONS> name trm assn"}
   \end{tabular}
   \end{center}
 
   \noindent
-  where $assn$ is an auxiliary type representing a list of assignments 
-  and $bn$ an auxiliary function identifying the variables to be bound by 
-  the $\mathtt{let}$. This function is defined by recursion over $assn$ as follows
+  where @{text assn} is an auxiliary type representing a list of assignments
+  and @{text bn} an auxiliary function identifying the variables to be bound
+  by the @{text "\<LET>"}. This function is defined by recursion over @{text
+  assn} as follows
 
   \begin{center}
-  $bn\,(\mathtt{anil}) = \varnothing \qquad bn\,(\mathtt{acons}\;x\;t\;as) = \{x\} \cup bn\,(as)$ 
+  @{text "bn(\<ANIL>) ="} @{term "{}"} \hspace{5mm} 
+  @{text "bn(\<ACONS> x t as) = {x} \<union> bn(as)"} 
   \end{center}
   
   \noindent
   The scope of the binding is indicated by labels given to the types, for
-  example \mbox{$s\!::\!trm$}, and a binding clause, in this case
-  $\mathtt{bind}\;bn\,(a) \IN s$, that states to bind in $s$ all the names the
-  function call $bn\,(a)$ returns.  This style of specifying terms and bindings is
-  heavily inspired by the syntax of the Ott-tool \cite{ott-jfp}.
+  example @{text "s::trm"}, and a binding clause, in this case
+  \isacommand{bind} @{text "bn(a)"} \isacommand{in} @{text "s"}, that states
+  to bind in @{text s} all the names the function call @{text "bn(a)"} returns.
+  This style of specifying terms and bindings is heavily inspired by the
+  syntax of the Ott-tool \cite{ott-jfp}.
+
 
   However, we will not be able to deal with all specifications that are
   allowed by Ott. One reason is that Ott lets the user to specify ``empty'' 
   types like
 
   \begin{center}
-  $t ::= t\;t \mid \lambda x. t$
+  @{text "t ::= t t | \<lambda>x. t"}
   \end{center}
 
   \noindent
@@ -204,32 +232,31 @@
   two type-schemes (with $x$, $y$ and $z$ being distinct)
 
   \begin{center}
-  $\forall \{x\}. x \rightarrow y  \;=\; \forall \{x, z\}. x \rightarrow y$ 
+  @{text "\<forall>{x}. x \<rightarrow> y  = \<forall>{x,z}. x \<rightarrow> y"} 
   \end{center}
   
   \noindent
-  are not just alpha-equal, but actually \emph{equal}. As a
-  result, we can only support specifications that make sense on the level of
-  alpha-equated terms (offending specifications, which for example bind a variable
-  according to a variable bound somewhere else, are not excluded by Ott, but we 
-  have to).  Our
-  insistence on reasoning with alpha-equated terms comes from the wealth of
-  experience we gained with the older version of Nominal Isabelle: for
-  non-trivial properties, reasoning about alpha-equated terms is much easier
-  than reasoning with raw terms. The fundamental reason for this is that the
-  HOL-logic underlying Nominal Isabelle allows us to replace
-  ``equals-by-equals''. In contrast, replacing ``alpha-equals-by-alpha-equals''
-  in a representation based on raw terms requires a lot of extra reasoning work.
+  are not just alpha-equal, but actually \emph{equal}. As a result, we can
+  only support specifications that make sense on the level of alpha-equated
+  terms (offending specifications, which for example bind a variable according
+  to a variable bound somewhere else, are not excluded by Ott, but we have
+  to).  Our insistence on reasoning with alpha-equated terms comes from the
+  wealth of experience we gained with the older version of Nominal Isabelle:
+  for non-trivial properties, reasoning about alpha-equated terms is much
+  easier than reasoning with raw terms. The fundamental reason for this is
+  that the HOL-logic underlying Nominal Isabelle allows us to replace
+  ``equals-by-equals''. In contrast, replacing
+  ``alpha-equals-by-alpha-equals'' in a representation based on raw terms
+  requires a lot of extra reasoning work.
 
-  Although in informal settings a reasoning infrastructure for alpha-equated 
-  terms is nearly always taken for granted, establishing 
-  it automatically in the Isabelle/HOL theorem prover is a rather non-trivial task. 
-  For every specification we will need to construct a type containing as 
-  elements the alpha-equated terms. To do so, we use 
-  the standard HOL-technique of defining a new type by  
-  identifying a non-empty subset of an existing type.   The construction we 
-  perform in HOL can be illustrated by the following picture:
- 
+  Although in informal settings a reasoning infrastructure for alpha-equated
+  terms is nearly always taken for granted, establishing it automatically in
+  the Isabelle/HOL theorem prover is a rather non-trivial task. For every
+  specification we will need to construct a type containing as elements the
+  alpha-equated terms. To do so, we use the standard HOL-technique of defining
+  a new type by identifying a non-empty subset of an existing type.  The
+  construction we perform in HOL can be illustrated by the following picture:
+
   \begin{center}
   \begin{tikzpicture}
   %\draw[step=2mm] (-4,-1) grid (4,1);
@@ -255,45 +282,45 @@
   \end{center}
 
   \noindent
-  We take as the starting point a definition of raw terms (defined as a 
-  datatype in Isabelle/HOL); identify then the 
-  alpha-equivalence classes in the type of sets of raw terms according to our 
-  alpha-equivalence relation and finally define the new type as these 
-  alpha-equivalence classes (non-emptiness is satisfied whenever the raw terms are 
-  definable as datatype in Isabelle/HOL and the fact that our relation for 
-  alpha-equivalence is indeed an equivalence relation).
+  We take as the starting point a definition of raw terms (defined as a
+  datatype in Isabelle/HOL); identify then the alpha-equivalence classes in
+  the type of sets of raw terms according to our alpha-equivalence relation
+  and finally define the new type as these alpha-equivalence classes
+  (non-emptiness is satisfied whenever the raw terms are definable as datatype
+  in Isabelle/HOL and the fact that our relation for alpha-equivalence is
+  indeed an equivalence relation).
 
-  The fact that we obtain an isomorphism between the new type and the non-empty 
-  subset shows that the new type is a faithful representation of alpha-equated terms. 
-  That is not the case for example for terms using the locally 
-  nameless representation of binders \cite{McKinnaPollack99}: in this representation 
-  there are ``junk'' terms that need to
-  be excluded by reasoning about a well-formedness predicate.
+  The fact that we obtain an isomorphism between the new type and the
+  non-empty subset shows that the new type is a faithful representation of
+  alpha-equated terms. That is not the case for example for terms using the
+  locally nameless representation of binders \cite{McKinnaPollack99}: in this
+  representation there are ``junk'' terms that need to be excluded by
+  reasoning about a well-formedness predicate.
 
-  The problem with introducing a new type in Isabelle/HOL is that in order to be useful, 
-  a reasoning infrastructure needs to be ``lifted'' from the underlying subset to 
-  the new type. This is usually a tricky and arduous task. To ease it,
-  we re-implemented in Isabelle/HOL the quotient package described by Homeier 
-  \cite{Homeier05} for the HOL4 system. This package 
-  allows us to  lift definitions and theorems involving raw terms
-  to definitions and theorems involving alpha-equated terms. For example
-  if we define the free-variable function over raw lambda-terms
+  The problem with introducing a new type in Isabelle/HOL is that in order to
+  be useful, a reasoning infrastructure needs to be ``lifted'' from the
+  underlying subset to the new type. This is usually a tricky and arduous
+  task. To ease it, we re-implemented in Isabelle/HOL the quotient package
+  described by Homeier \cite{Homeier05} for the HOL4 system. This package
+  allows us to lift definitions and theorems involving raw terms to
+  definitions and theorems involving alpha-equated terms. For example if we
+  define the free-variable function over raw lambda-terms
 
   \begin{center}
-  $\fv(x) = \{x\}$\hspace{10mm}
-  $\fv(t_1\;t_2) = \fv(t_1) \cup \fv(t_2)$\\[1mm]
-  $\fv(\lambda x.t) = \fv(t) - \{x\}$
+  @{text "fv(x) = {x}"}\hspace{10mm}
+  @{text "fv(t\<^isub>1 t\<^isub>2) = fv(t\<^isub>1) \<union> fv(t\<^isub>2)"}\\[1mm]
+  @{text "fv(\<lambda>x.t) = fv(t) - {x}"}
   \end{center}
   
   \noindent
-  then with not too great effort we obtain a function $\fv^\alpha$
+  then with not too great effort we obtain a function @{text "fv\<^sup>\<alpha>"}
   operating on quotients, or alpha-equivalence classes of lambda-terms. This
   lifted function is characterised by the equations
 
   \begin{center}
-  $\fv^\alpha(x) = \{x\}$\hspace{10mm}
-  $\fv^\alpha(t_1\;t_2) = \fv^\alpha(t_1) \cup \fv^\alpha(t_2)$\\[1mm]
-  $\fv^\alpha(\lambda x.t) = \fv^\alpha(t) - \{x\}$
+  @{text "fv\<^sup>\<alpha>(x) = {x}"}\hspace{10mm}
+  @{text "fv\<^sup>\<alpha>(t\<^isub>1 t\<^isub>2) = fv\<^sup>\<alpha>(t\<^isub>1) \<union> fv\<^sup>\<alpha>(t\<^isub>2)"}\\[1mm]
+  @{text "fv\<^sup>\<alpha>(\<lambda>x.t) = fv\<^sup>\<alpha>(t) - {x}"}
   \end{center}
 
   \noindent
@@ -400,44 +427,47 @@
   from this specification (remember that Nominal Isabelle is a definitional
   extension of Isabelle/HOL, which does not introduce any new axioms).
 
-
-  In order to keep our work manageable, we will wherever possible state
-  definitions and perform proofs inside Isabelle, as opposed to write custom
-  ML-code that generates them anew for each specification. To that
-  end, we will consider pairs @{text "(as, x)"} of type @{text "(atom set) \<times> \<beta>"}.
-  These pairs are intended to represent the abstraction, or binding, of the set @{text "as"} 
-  in the body @{text "x"}.
+  In order to keep our work with deriving the reasoning infrastructure
+  manageable, we will wherever possible state definitions and perform proofs
+  on the user-level of Isabelle/HOL, as opposed to write custom ML-code that
+  generates them anew for each specification. To that end, we will consider
+  first pairs @{text "(as, x)"} of type @{text "(atom set) \<times> \<beta>"}.  These pairs
+  are intended to represent the abstraction, or binding, of the set @{text
+  "as"} in the body @{text "x"}.
 
-  The first question we have to answer is when the pairs $(as, x)$ and $(bs, y)$ are
-  alpha-equivalent? (At the moment we are interested in
-  the notion of alpha-equivalence that is \emph{not} preserved by adding 
-  vacuous binders.) To answer this, we identify four conditions: {\it i)} given 
-  a free-variable function $\fv$ of type \mbox{@{text "\<beta> \<Rightarrow> atom set"}}, then @{text x} and @{text y} 
-  need to have the same set of free variables; moreover there must be a permutation
-  @{text p}  such that {\it ii)} it leaves the free variables of @{text x} and @{text y} unchanged, 
-  but {\it iii)} ``moves'' their bound names so that we obtain modulo a relation, 
-  say \mbox{@{text "_ R _"}}, two equal terms. We also require {\it iv)} that @{text p} makes 
-  the abstracted sets @{text as} and @{text bs} equal. The requirements {\it i)} to {\it iv)} can 
-  be stated formally as follows:
+  The first question we have to answer is when the pairs @{text "(as, x)"} and
+  @{text "(bs, y)"} are alpha-equivalent? (At the moment we are interested in
+  the notion of alpha-equivalence that is \emph{not} preserved by adding
+  vacuous binders.) To answer this, we identify four conditions: {\it i)}
+  given a free-variable function @{text "fv"} of type \mbox{@{text "\<beta> \<Rightarrow> atom
+  set"}}, then @{text x} and @{text y} need to have the same set of free
+  variables; moreover there must be a permutation @{text p} such that {\it
+  ii)} it leaves the free variables of @{text x} and @{text y} unchanged, but
+  {\it iii)} ``moves'' their bound names so that we obtain modulo a relation,
+  say \mbox{@{text "_ R _"}}, two equal terms. We also require {\it iv)} that
+  @{text p} makes the abstracted sets @{text as} and @{text bs} equal. The
+  requirements {\it i)} to {\it iv)} can be stated formally as follows:
   %
   \begin{equation}\label{alphaset}
   \begin{array}{@ {\hspace{10mm}}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l}
-  \multicolumn{2}{l}{(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}_{set}^{\fv, R, p} (bs, y) \;\dn\hspace{30mm}\;}\\[1mm]
-             & @{text "fv(x) - as = fv(y) - bs"}\\
-  \wedge     & @{text "(fv(x) - as) #* p"}\\
-  \wedge     & @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"}\\
-  \wedge     & @{text "(p \<bullet> as) = bs"}\\ 
+  \multicolumn{2}{l}{@{term "(as, x) \<approx>gen R fv p (bs, y)"} @{text "\<equiv>"}\hspace{30mm}}\\
+               & @{term "fv(x) - as = fv(y) - bs"}\\
+  @{text "\<and>"} & @{term "(fv(x) - as) \<sharp>* p"}\\
+  @{text "\<and>"} & @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"}\\
+  @{text "\<and>"} & @{term "(p \<bullet> as) = bs"}\\ 
   \end{array}
   \end{equation}
 
   \noindent
-  Note that this relation is dependent on $p$. Alpha-equivalence is then the relation where 
-  we existentially quantify over this $p$. 
-  Also note that the relation is dependent on a free-variable function $\fv$ and a relation 
-  $R$. The reason for this extra generality is that we will use $\approx_{set}$ for both 
-  ``raw'' terms and alpha-equated terms. In the latter case, $R$ will be replaced by 
-  equality $(op =)$ and we are going to prove that $\fv$ will be equal to the support 
-  of $x$ and $y$. 
+  Note that this relation is dependent on the permutation @{text
+  "p"}. Alpha-equivalence between two pairs is then the relation where we
+  existentially quantify over this @{text "p"}. Also note that the relation is
+  dependent on a free-variable function @{text "fv"} and a relation @{text
+  "R"}. The reason for this extra generality is that we will use
+  $\approx_{\textit{set}}$ for both ``raw'' terms and alpha-equated terms. In
+  the latter case, $R$ will be replaced by equality @{text "="} and for raw terms we
+  will prove that @{text "fv"} is equal to the support of @{text
+  x} and @{text y}.
 
   The definition in \eqref{alphaset} does not make any distinction between the
   order of abstracted variables. If we want this, then we can define alpha-equivalence 
@@ -446,26 +476,27 @@
   %
   \begin{equation}\label{alphalist}
   \begin{array}{@ {\hspace{10mm}}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l}
-  \multicolumn{2}{l}{(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}_{list}^{\fv, R, p} (bs, y) \;\dn\hspace{30mm}\;}\\[1mm]
-             & @{text "fv(x) - (set as) = fv(y) - (set bs)"}\\
-  \wedge     & @{text "(fv(x) - set as) #* p"}\\
+  \multicolumn{2}{l}{@{term "(as, x) \<approx>lst R fv p (bs, y)"} @{text "\<equiv>"}\hspace{30mm}}\\[1mm]
+             & @{term "fv(x) - (set as) = fv(y) - (set bs)"}\\
+  \wedge     & @{term "(fv(x) - set as) \<sharp>* p"}\\
   \wedge     & @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"}\\
-  \wedge     & @{text "(p \<bullet> as) = bs"}\\ 
+  \wedge     & @{term "(p \<bullet> as) = bs"}\\ 
   \end{array}
   \end{equation}
   
   \noindent
-  where $set$ is the function that coerces a list of atoms into a set of atoms.
+  where @{term set} is a function that coerces a list of atoms into a set of atoms.
+  Now the last clause ensures that the order of the binders matters.
 
-  If we do not want to make any difference between the order of binders and
+  If we do not want to make any difference between the order of binders \emph{and}
   also allow vacuous binders, then we keep sets of binders, but drop the fourth 
   condition in \eqref{alphaset}:
   %
   \begin{equation}\label{alphares}
   \begin{array}{@ {\hspace{10mm}}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l}
-  \multicolumn{2}{l}{(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}_{res}^{\fv, R, p} (bs, y) \;\dn\hspace{30mm}\;}\\[1mm]
-             & @{text "fv(x) - as = fv(y) - bs"}\\
-  \wedge     & @{text "(fv(x) - as) #* p"}\\
+  \multicolumn{2}{l}{@{term "(as, x) \<approx>res R fv p (bs, y)"} @{text "\<equiv>"}\hspace{30mm}}\\[1mm]
+             & @{term "fv(x) - as = fv(y) - bs"}\\
+  \wedge     & @{term "(fv(x) - as) \<sharp>* p"}\\
   \wedge     & @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"}\\
   \end{array}
   \end{equation}
@@ -473,52 +504,116 @@
   \begin{exmple}\rm
   It might be useful to consider some examples for how these definitions pan out in practise.
   For this consider the case of abstracting a set of variables over types (as in type-schemes). 
-  We set $R$ to be the equality and for $\fv(T)$ we define
+  We set @{text R} to be the equality and for @{text "fv(T)"} we define
 
   \begin{center}
-  $\fv(x) = \{x\}  \qquad \fv(T_1 \rightarrow T_2) = \fv(T_1) \cup \fv(T_2)$
+  @{text "fv(x) = {x}"}  \hspace{5mm} @{text "fv(T\<^isub>1 \<rightarrow> T\<^isub>2) = fv(T\<^isub>1) \<union> fv(T\<^isub>2)"}
   \end{center}
 
   \noindent
-  Now recall the examples shown in \eqref{ex1}, \eqref{ex2} and \eqref{ex3}. It can be easily 
-  checked that @{text "({x, y}, x \<rightarrow> y)"} and
-  @{text "({y, x}, y \<rightarrow> x)"} are equal according to $\approx_{set}$ and $\approx_{res}$ by taking $p$ to
-  be the swapping @{term "(x \<rightleftharpoons> y)"}. In case of @{text "x \<noteq> y"}, then 
-  $([x, y], x \rightarrow y) \not\approx_{list} ([y,x], x \rightarrow y)$ since there is no permutation that 
-  makes the lists @{text "[x, y]"} and @{text "[y, x]"} equal, and also leaves the 
-  type \mbox{@{text "x \<rightarrow> y"}} unchanged. Another examples is 
-   $(\{x\}, x) \approx_{res} (\{x,y\}, x)$ which holds by taking $p$ to be the identity permutation.
-  However, if @{text "x \<noteq> y"}, then  
-  $(\{x\}, x) \not\approx_{set} (\{x,y\}, x)$ since there is no permutation that makes
-  the sets $\{x\}$ and $\{x,y\}$ equal (similarly for $\approx_{list}$).
+  Now recall the examples shown in \eqref{ex1}, \eqref{ex2} and
+  \eqref{ex3}. It can be easily checked that @{text "({x,y}, x \<rightarrow> y)"} and
+  @{text "({y,x}, y \<rightarrow> x)"} are equal according to $\approx_{\textit{set}}$ and
+  $\approx_{\textit{res}}$ by taking @{text p} to be the swapping @{term "(x \<rightleftharpoons>
+  y)"}. In case of @{text "x \<noteq> y"}, then @{text "([x, y], x \<rightarrow> y)"}
+  $\not\approx_{\textit{list}}$ @{text "([y,x], x \<rightarrow> y)"} since there is no permutation
+  that makes the lists @{text "[x, y]"} and @{text "[y, x]"} equal, and also
+  leaves the type \mbox{@{text "x \<rightarrow> y"}} unchanged. Another example is
+  @{text "({x}, x)"} $\approx_{\textit{res}}$ @{text "({x,y}, x)"} which holds by 
+  taking @{text p} to be the
+  identity permutation.  However, if @{text "x \<noteq> y"}, then @{text "({x}, x)"}
+  $\not\approx_{\textit{set}}$ @{text "({x,y}, x)"} since there is no permutation 
+  that makes the
+  sets @{text "{x}"} and @{text "{x,y}"} equal (similarly for $\approx_{\textit{list}}$).
   \end{exmple}
 
+  % looks too ugly
+  %\noindent
+  %Let $\star$ range over $\{set, res, list\}$. We prove next under which 
+  %conditions the $\approx\hspace{0.05mm}_\star^{\fv, R, p}$ are equivalence 
+  %relations and equivariant:
+  %
+  %\begin{lemma}
+  %{\it i)} Given the fact that $x\;R\;x$ holds, then 
+  %$(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, 0}_\star (as, x)$. {\it ii)} Given
+  %that @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"} implies @{text "(-p \<bullet> y) R x"}, then
+  %$(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, p}_\star (bs, y)$ implies
+  %$(bs, y) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, - p}_\star (as, x)$. {\it iii)} Given
+  %that @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"} and @{text "(q \<bullet> y) R z"} implies 
+  %@{text "((q + p) \<bullet> x) R z"}, then $(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, p}_\star (bs, y)$
+  %and $(bs, y) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, q}_\star (cs, z)$ implies
+  %$(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, q + p}_\star (cs, z)$. Given
+  %@{text "(q \<bullet> x) R y"} implies @{text "(p \<bullet> (q \<bullet> x)) R (p \<bullet> y)"} and
+  %@{text "p \<bullet> (fv x) = fv (p \<bullet> x)"} then @{text "p \<bullet> (fv y) = fv (p \<bullet> y)"}, then
+  %$(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, q}_\star (bs, y)$ implies
+  %$(p \;\isasymbullet\; as, p \;\isasymbullet\; x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, q}_\star 
+  %(p \;\isasymbullet\; bs, p \;\isasymbullet\; y)$.
+  %\end{lemma}
+  
+  %\begin{proof}
+  %All properties are by unfolding the definitions and simple calculations. 
+  %\end{proof}
+
+
+  In the rest of this section we are going to introduce a type- and term-constructor 
+  for abstractions. For this we define 
+  %
+  \begin{equation}
+  @{term "abs_set (as, x) (bs, x) \<equiv> \<exists>p. alpha_gen (as, x) equal supp p (bs, x)"}
+  \end{equation}
+  
   \noindent
-  Let $\star$ range over $\{set, res, list\}$. We prove next under which 
-  conditions the $\approx\hspace{0.05mm}_\star^{\fv, R, p}$ are equivalence 
-  relations and equivariant:
+  Similarly for @{text "abs_list"} and @{text "abs_res"}. We can show that these 
+  relations are equivalence relations and equivariant 
+  (we only show the $\approx_{\textit{abs\_set}}$-case).
 
   \begin{lemma}
-  {\it i)} Given the fact that $x\;R\;x$ holds, then 
-  $(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, 0}_\star (as, x)$. {\it ii)} Given
-  that @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"} implies @{text "(-p \<bullet> y) R x"}, then
-  $(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, p}_\star (bs, y)$ implies
-  $(bs, y) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, - p}_\star (as, x)$. {\it iii)} Given
-  that @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"} and @{text "(q \<bullet> y) R z"} implies 
-  @{text "((q + p) \<bullet> x) R z"}, then $(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, p}_\star (bs, y)$
-  and $(bs, y) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, q}_\star (cs, z)$ implies
-  $(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, q + p}_\star (cs, z)$. Given
-  @{text "(q \<bullet> x) R y"} implies @{text "(p \<bullet> (q \<bullet> x)) R (p \<bullet> y)"} and
-  @{text "p \<bullet> (fv x) = fv (p \<bullet> x)"} then @{text "p \<bullet> (fv y) = fv (p \<bullet> y)"}, then
-  $(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, q}_\star (bs, y)$ implies
-  $(p \;\isasymbullet\; as, p \;\isasymbullet\; x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, q}_\star 
-  (p \;\isasymbullet\; bs, p \;\isasymbullet\; y)$.
+  $\approx_{\textit{abs\_set}}$ is an equivalence
+  relations, and if @{term "abs_set (as, x) (bs, x)"} then also
+  @{term "abs_set (p \<bullet> as, p \<bullet> x) (p \<bullet> bs, p \<bullet> x)"}.
+  \end{lemma}
+
+  \begin{proof}
+  Reflexivity is by taking @{text "p"} to be @{text "0"}. For symmetry we have
+  a permutation @{text p} and for the proof obligation take @{term "-p"}. In case 
+  of transitivity we have two permutations @{text p} and @{text q}, and for the
+  proof obligation use @{text "q + p"}. All the conditions are then by simple
+  calculations. 
+  \end{proof}
+
+  \noindent
+  The following lemma (and similar ones for $\approx_{\textit{abs\_list}}$ and 
+  $\approx_{\textit{abs\_res}}$) will be crucial below: 
+
+  \begin{lemma}
+  @{thm[mode=IfThen] alpha_abs_swap[no_vars]}
   \end{lemma}
-  
+
   \begin{proof}
-  All properties are by unfolding the definitions and simple calculations. 
+  This lemma is straightforward by observing that the assumptions give us
+  @{term "(a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> (supp x - bs) = (supp x - bs)"} and that @{text supp}
+  is equivariant.
   \end{proof}
 
+  \noindent 
+  We are also define the following  
+
+  @{text "aux (as, x) \<equiv> supp x - as"}
+
+  
+
+  \noindent
+  This allows us to use our quotient package and introduce new types
+  @{text "\<beta> abs_set"}, @{text "\<beta> abs_res"} and @{text "\<beta> abs_list"}
+  representing the alpha-equivalence classes. Elements in these types 
+  we will, respectively, write as:
+
+  \begin{center}
+  @{term "Abs as x"} \hspace{5mm} 
+  @{term "Abs_lst as x"} \hspace{5mm}
+  @{term "Abs_res as x"}
+  \end{center}
+
 
   \begin{lemma}
   $supp ([as]set. x) = supp x - as$ 
@@ -834,7 +929,7 @@
   \begin{tabular}{cp{7cm}}
   $\bullet$ & @{text "{atom x\<^isub>i} - bnds"} provided @{term "x\<^isub>i"} is an atom\\
   $\bullet$ & @{text "(atoms x\<^isub>i) - bnds"} provided @{term "x\<^isub>i"} is a set of atoms\\
-  $\bullet$ & @{text "(atoml x\<^isub>i) - bnds"} provided @{term "x\<^isub>i"} is a list of atoms\\
+  $\bullet$ & @{text "(atoms (set x\<^isub>i)) - bnds"} provided @{term "x\<^isub>i"} is a list of atoms\\
   $\bullet$ & @{text "(fv_ty\<^isub>i x\<^isub>i) - bnds"} provided @{term "ty\<^isub>i"} is a nominal datatype\\
   $\bullet$ & @{term "{}"} otherwise 
   \end{tabular}