Pearl/Paper.thy
changeset 1772 48c2eb84d5ce
child 1774 c34347ec7ab3
--- /dev/null	Thu Jan 01 00:00:00 1970 +0000
+++ b/Pearl/Paper.thy	Sat Apr 03 21:53:04 2010 +0200
@@ -0,0 +1,1232 @@
+(*<*)
+theory Paper
+imports "../Nominal/Nominal2_Base" 
+        "../Nominal/Nominal2_Atoms" 
+        "../Nominal/Nominal2_Eqvt" 
+        "../Nominal/Atoms" 
+        "LaTeXsugar"
+begin
+
+notation (latex output)
+  sort_of ("sort _" [1000] 100) and
+  Abs_perm ("_") and
+  Rep_perm ("_") and
+  swap ("'(_ _')" [1000, 1000] 1000) and
+  fresh ("_ # _" [51, 51] 50) and
+  Cons ("_::_" [78,77] 73) and
+  supp ("supp _" [78] 73) and
+  uminus ("-_" [78] 73) and
+  atom ("|_|") and
+  If  ("if _ then _ else _" 10) and
+  Rep_name ("\<lfloor>_\<rfloor>") and
+  Abs_name ("\<lceil>_\<rceil>") and
+  Rep_var ("\<lfloor>_\<rfloor>") and
+  Abs_var ("\<lceil>_\<rceil>") and
+  sort_of_ty ("sort'_ty _")
+
+(* BH: uncomment if you really prefer the dot notation
+syntax (latex output)
+  "_Collect" :: "pttrn => bool => 'a set" ("(1{_ . _})")
+*)
+
+(* sort is used in Lists for sorting *)
+hide const sort
+
+abbreviation
+  "sort \<equiv> sort_of"
+
+abbreviation
+  "sort_ty \<equiv> sort_of_ty"
+
+(*>*)
+
+section {* Introduction *}
+
+text {*
+  Nominal Isabelle is a definitional extension of the Isabelle/HOL theorem
+  prover providing a proving infrastructure for convenient reasoning about
+  programming languages. It has been used to formalise an equivalence checking
+  algorithm for LF \cite{UrbanCheneyBerghofer08}, 
+  Typed Scheme~\cite{TobinHochstadtFelleisen08}, several calculi for concurrency
+  \cite{BengtsonParrow07,BengtsonParow09} and a strong normalisation result for
+  cut-elimination in classical logic \cite{UrbanZhu08}. It has also been used
+  by Pollack for formalisations in the locally-nameless approach to binding
+  \cite{SatoPollack10}.
+
+  At its core Nominal Isabelle is based on the nominal logic work of Pitts et
+  al \cite{GabbayPitts02,Pitts03}.  The most basic notion in this work is a
+  sort-respecting permutation operation defined over a countably infinite
+  collection of sorted atoms. The atoms are used for representing variables
+  that might be bound. Multiple sorts are necessary for being
+  able to represent different kinds of variables. For example, in the language
+  Mini-ML there are bound term variables and bound type variables; each kind
+  needs to be represented by a different sort of atoms.
+
+  Unfortunately, the type system of Isabelle/HOL is not a good fit for the way
+  atoms and sorts are used in the original formulation of the nominal logic work.
+  Therefore it was decided in earlier versions of Nominal Isabelle to use a
+  separate type for each sort of atoms and let the type system enforce the
+  sort-respecting property of permutations. Inspired by the work on nominal
+  unification \cite{UrbanPittsGabbay04}, it seemed best at the time to also
+  implement permutations concretely as list of pairs of atoms. Thus Nominal
+  Isabelle used the two-place permutation operation with the generic type
+
+  @{text [display,indent=10] "_ \<bullet> _  ::  (\<alpha> \<times> \<alpha>) list \<Rightarrow> \<beta> \<Rightarrow> \<beta>"}
+
+  \noindent 
+  where @{text "\<alpha>"} stands for the type of atoms and @{text "\<beta>"} for the type
+  of the objects on which the permutation acts. For atoms of type @{text "\<alpha>"} 
+  the permutation operation is defined over the length of lists as follows
+
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}c@ {\hspace{2mm}}l}
+  @{text "[] \<bullet> c"} & @{text "="} & @{text c}\\
+  @{text "(a b)::\<pi> \<bullet> c"} & @{text "="} & 
+     $\begin{cases} @{text a} & \textrm{if}~@{text "\<pi> \<bullet> c = b"}\\ 
+                    @{text b} & \textrm{if}~@{text "\<pi> \<bullet> c = a"}\\
+                    @{text "\<pi> \<bullet> c"} & \textrm{otherwise}\end{cases}$
+  \end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{atomperm}
+  \end{isabelle}
+
+  \noindent
+  where we write @{text "(a b)"} for a swapping of atoms @{text "a"} and
+  @{text "b"}. For atoms of different type, the permutation operation
+  is defined as @{text "\<pi> \<bullet> c \<equiv> c"}.
+
+  With the list representation of permutations it is impossible to state an
+  ``ill-sorted'' permutation, since the type system excludes lists containing
+  atoms of different type. Another advantage of the list representation is that
+  the basic operations on permutations are already defined in the list library:
+  composition of two permutations (written @{text "_ @ _"}) is just list append,
+  and inversion of a permutation (written @{text "_\<^sup>-\<^sup>1"}) is just
+  list reversal. A disadvantage is that permutations do not have unique
+  representations as lists; we had to explicitly identify permutations according
+  to the relation
+  
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
+  @{text "\<pi>\<^isub>1 \<sim> \<pi>\<^isub>2  \<equiv>  \<forall>a. \<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> a = \<pi>\<^isub>2 \<bullet> a"}
+  \end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{permequ}
+  \end{isabelle}
+
+  When lifting the permutation operation to other types, for example sets,
+  functions and so on, we needed to ensure that every definition is
+  well-behaved in the sense that it satisfies the following three 
+  \emph{permutation properties}:
+
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}r@ {\hspace{4mm}}p{10cm}}
+  i) & @{text "[] \<bullet> x = x"}\\
+  ii) & @{text "(\<pi>\<^isub>1 @ \<pi>\<^isub>2) \<bullet> x = \<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> (\<pi>\<^isub>2 \<bullet> x)"}\\
+  iii) & if @{text "\<pi>\<^isub>1 \<sim> \<pi>\<^isub>2"} then @{text "\<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> x = \<pi>\<^isub>2 \<bullet> x"}
+  \end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{permprops}
+  \end{isabelle}
+
+  \noindent
+  From these properties we were able to derive most facts about permutations, and 
+  the type classes of Isabelle/HOL allowed us to reason abstractly about these
+  three properties, and then let the type system automatically enforce these
+  properties for each type.
+
+  The major problem with Isabelle/HOL's type classes, however, is that they
+  support operations with only a single type parameter and the permutation
+  operations @{text "_ \<bullet> _"} used above in the permutation properties
+  contain two! To work around this obstacle, Nominal Isabelle 
+  required from the user to
+  declare up-front the collection of \emph{all} atom types, say @{text
+  "\<alpha>\<^isub>1,\<dots>,\<alpha>\<^isub>n"}. From this collection it used custom ML-code to
+  generate @{text n} type classes corresponding to the permutation properties,
+  whereby in these type classes the permutation operation is restricted to
+
+  @{text [display,indent=10] "_ \<bullet> _ :: (\<alpha>\<^isub>i \<times> \<alpha>\<^isub>i) list \<Rightarrow> \<beta> \<Rightarrow> \<beta>"}
+
+  \noindent
+  This operation has only a single type parameter @{text "\<beta>"} (the @{text "\<alpha>\<^isub>i"} are the
+  atom types given by the user). 
+
+  While the representation of permutations-as-list solved the
+  ``sort-respecting'' requirement and the declaration of all atom types
+  up-front solved the problem with Isabelle/HOL's type classes, this setup
+  caused several problems for formalising the nominal logic work: First,
+  Nominal Isabelle had to generate @{text "n\<^sup>2"} definitions for the
+  permutation operation over @{text "n"} types of atoms.  Second, whenever we
+  need to generalise induction hypotheses by quantifying over permutations, we
+  have to build cumbersome quantifications like
+
+  @{text [display,indent=10] "\<forall>\<pi>\<^isub>1 \<dots> \<forall>\<pi>\<^isub>n. \<dots>"}
+
+  \noindent
+  where the @{text "\<pi>\<^isub>i"} are of type @{text "(\<alpha>\<^isub>i \<times> \<alpha>\<^isub>i) list"}. 
+  The reason is that the permutation operation behaves differently for 
+  every @{text "\<alpha>\<^isub>i"}. Third, although the notion of support
+
+  @{text [display,indent=10] "supp _ :: \<beta> \<Rightarrow> \<alpha> set"}
+
+  \noindent
+  which we will define later, has a generic type @{text "\<alpha> set"}, it cannot be
+  used to express the support of an object over \emph{all} atoms. The reason
+  is again that support can behave differently for each @{text
+  "\<alpha>\<^isub>i"}. This problem is annoying, because if we need to know in
+  a statement that an object, say @{text "x"}, is finitely supported we end up
+  with having to state premises of the form
+
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
+  @{text "finite ((supp x) :: \<alpha>\<^isub>1 set) , \<dots>, finite ((supp x) :: \<alpha>\<^isub>n set)"}
+  \end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{fssequence}
+  \end{isabelle}
+
+  \noindent
+  Sometimes we can avoid such premises completely, if @{text x} is a member of a
+  \emph{finitely supported type}.  However, keeping track of finitely supported
+  types requires another @{text n} type classes, and for technical reasons not
+  all types can be shown to be finitely supported.
+
+  The real pain of having a separate type for each atom sort arises, however, 
+  from another permutation property
+
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}r@ {\hspace{4mm}}p{10cm}}
+  iv) & @{text "\<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> (\<pi>\<^isub>2 \<bullet> x) = (\<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> \<pi>\<^isub>2) \<bullet> (\<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> x)"}
+  \end{tabular}
+  \end{isabelle}
+
+  \noindent
+  where permutation @{text "\<pi>\<^isub>1"} has type @{text "(\<alpha> \<times> \<alpha>) list"},
+  @{text "\<pi>\<^isub>2"} type @{text "(\<alpha>' \<times> \<alpha>') list"} and @{text x} type @{text
+  "\<beta>"}. This property is needed in order to derive facts about how
+  permutations of different types interact, which is not covered by the
+  permutation properties @{text "i"}-@{text "iii"} shown in
+  \eqref{permprops}. The problem is that this property involves three type
+  parameters. In order to use again Isabelle/HOL's type class mechanism with
+  only permitting a single type parameter, we have to instantiate the atom
+  types. Consequently we end up with an additional @{text "n\<^sup>2"}
+  slightly different type classes for this permutation property.
+  
+  While the problems and pain can be almost completely hidden from the user in
+  the existing implementation of Nominal Isabelle, the work is \emph{not}
+  pretty. It requires a large amount of custom ML-code and also forces the
+  user to declare up-front all atom-types that are ever going to be used in a
+  formalisation. In this paper we set out to solve the problems with multiple
+  type parameters in the permutation operation, and in this way can dispense
+  with the large amounts of custom ML-code for generating multiple variants
+  for some basic definitions. The result is that we can implement a pleasingly
+  simple formalisation of the nominal logic work.\smallskip
+
+  \noindent
+  {\bf Contributions of the paper:} We use a single atom type for representing
+  atoms of different sorts and use functions for representing
+  permutations. This drastically reduces the number of type classes to just
+  two (permutation types and finitely supported types), which we need in order
+  reason abstractly about properties from the nominal logic work. The novel
+  technical contribution of this paper is a mechanism for dealing with
+  ``Church-style'' lambda-terms \cite{Church40} and HOL-based languages
+  \cite{PittsHOL4} where variables and variable binding depend on type
+  annotations.
+*}
+
+section {* Sorted Atoms and Sort-Respecting Permutations *}
+
+text {*
+  In the nominal logic work of Pitts, binders and bound variables are
+  represented by \emph{atoms}.  As stated above, we need to have different
+  \emph{sorts} of atoms to be able to bind different kinds of variables.  A
+  basic requirement is that there must be a countably infinite number of atoms
+  of each sort.  Unlike in our earlier work, where we identified each sort with
+  a separate type, we implement here atoms to be
+*}
+
+          datatype atom\<iota> = Atom\<iota> string nat
+
+text {*
+  \noindent
+  whereby the string argument specifies the sort of the atom.  (We use type
+  \emph{string} merely for convenience; any countably infinite type would work
+  as well.)  We have an auxiliary function @{text sort} that is defined as @{thm
+  sort_of.simps[no_vars]}, and we clearly have for every finite set @{text X} of
+  atoms and every sort @{text s} the property:
+  
+  \begin{proposition}\label{choosefresh}
+  @{text "If finite X then there exists an atom a such that
+  sort a = s and a \<notin> X"}.
+  \end{proposition}
+
+  For implementing sort-respecting permutations, we use functions of type @{typ
+  "atom => atom"} that @{text "i)"} are bijective; @{text "ii)"} are the
+  identity on all atoms, except a finite number of them; and @{text "iii)"} map
+  each atom to one of the same sort. These properties can be conveniently stated
+  for a function @{text \<pi>} as follows:
+  
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}r@ {\hspace{4mm}}p{10cm}}
+  i) & @{term "bij \<pi>"}\\
+  ii) & @{term "finite {a. \<pi> a \<noteq> a}"}\\
+  iii) & @{term "\<forall>a. sort (\<pi> a) = sort a"}
+  \end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{permtype}
+  \end{isabelle}
+
+  \noindent
+  Like all HOL-based theorem provers, Isabelle/HOL allows us to
+  introduce a new type @{typ perm} that includes just those functions
+  satisfying all three properties. For example the identity function,
+  written @{term id}, is included in @{typ perm}. Also function composition, 
+  written  \mbox{@{text "_ \<circ> _"}}, and function inversion, given by Isabelle/HOL's 
+  inverse operator and written \mbox{@{text "inv _"}}, preserve the properties 
+  @{text "i"}-@{text "iii"}. 
+
+  However, a moment of thought is needed about how to construct non-trivial
+  permutations? In the nominal logic work it turned out to be most convenient
+  to work with swappings, written @{text "(a b)"}.  In our setting the
+  type of swappings must be
+
+  @{text [display,indent=10] "(_ _) :: atom \<Rightarrow> atom \<Rightarrow> perm"}
+
+  \noindent
+  but since permutations are required to respect sorts, we must carefully
+  consider what happens if a user states a swapping of atoms with different
+  sorts.  In earlier versions of Nominal Isabelle, we avoided this problem by
+  using different types for different sorts; the type system prevented users
+  from stating ill-sorted swappings.  Here, however, definitions such 
+  as\footnote{To increase legibility, we omit here and in what follows the
+  @{term Rep_perm} and @{term "Abs_perm"} wrappers that are needed in our
+  implementation since we defined permutation not to be the full function space,
+  but only those functions of type @{typ perm} satisfying properties @{text
+  i}-@{text "iii"}.}
+
+  @{text [display,indent=10] "(a b) \<equiv> \<lambda>c. if a = c then b else (if b = c then a else c)"}
+
+  \noindent
+  do not work in general, because the type system does not prevent @{text a}
+  and @{text b} from having different sorts---in which case the function would
+  violate property @{text iii}.  We could make the definition of swappings
+  partial by adding the precondition @{term "sort a = sort b"},
+  which would mean that in case @{text a} and @{text b} have different sorts,
+  the value of @{text "(a b)"} is unspecified.  However, this looked like a
+  cumbersome solution, since sort-related side conditions would be required
+  everywhere, even to unfold the definition.  It turned out to be more
+  convenient to actually allow the user to state ``ill-sorted'' swappings but
+  limit their ``damage'' by defaulting to the identity permutation in the
+  ill-sorted case:
+
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}rl}
+  @{text "(a b) \<equiv>"} & @{text "if (sort a = sort b)"}\\ 
+   & \hspace{3mm}@{text "then \<lambda>c. if a = c then b else (if b = c then a else c)"}\\ 
+   & \hspace{3mm}@{text "else id"}
+  \end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{swapdef}
+  \end{isabelle}
+
+  \noindent
+  This function is bijective, the identity on all atoms except
+  @{text a} and @{text b}, and sort respecting. Therefore it is 
+  a function in @{typ perm}. 
+
+  One advantage of using functions instead of lists as a representation for
+  permutations is that for example the swappings
+
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
+  @{thm swap_commute[no_vars]}\hspace{10mm}
+  @{text "(a a) = id"}
+  \end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{swapeqs}
+  \end{isabelle}
+
+  \noindent
+  are \emph{equal}.  We do not have to use the equivalence relation shown
+  in~\eqref{permequ} to identify them, as we would if they had been represented
+  as lists of pairs.  Another advantage of the function representation is that
+  they form an (additive) group provided we define
+
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
+  @{thm zero_perm_def[no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]} \hspace{4mm}
+  @{thm plus_perm_def[where p="\<pi>\<^isub>1" and q="\<pi>\<^isub>2", THEN eq_reflection]} \hspace{4mm}
+  @{thm uminus_perm_def[where p="\<pi>", THEN eq_reflection]} \hspace{4mm}
+  @{thm diff_def[where x="\<pi>\<^isub>1" and y="\<pi>\<^isub>2"]} 
+  \end{tabular}
+  \end{isabelle}
+
+  \noindent
+  and verify the simple properties
+
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
+  @{thm add_assoc[where a="\<pi>\<^isub>1" and b="\<pi>\<^isub>2" and c="\<pi>\<^isub>3"]} \hspace{3mm}
+  @{thm monoid_add_class.add_0_left[where a="\<pi>::perm"]} \hspace{3mm}
+  @{thm monoid_add_class.add_0_right[where a="\<pi>::perm"]} \hspace{3mm}
+  @{thm group_add_class.left_minus[where a="\<pi>::perm"]} 
+  \end{tabular}
+  \end{isabelle}
+
+  \noindent
+  Again this is in contrast to the list-of-pairs representation which does not
+  form a group. The technical importance of this fact is that for groups we can
+  rely on Isabelle/HOL's rich simplification infrastructure.  This will come in
+  handy when we have to do calculations with permutations.
+
+  By formalising permutations abstractly as functions, and using a single type
+  for all atoms, we can now restate the \emph{permutation properties} from
+  \eqref{permprops} as just the two equations
+  
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}r@ {\hspace{4mm}}p{10cm}}
+  i) & @{thm permute_zero[no_vars]}\\
+  ii) & @{thm permute_plus[where p="\<pi>\<^isub>1" and q="\<pi>\<^isub>2",no_vars]}
+  \end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{newpermprops}
+  \end{isabelle} 
+
+  \noindent
+  in which the permutation operations are of type @{text "perm \<Rightarrow> \<beta> \<Rightarrow> \<beta>"} and so
+  have only a single type parameter.  Consequently, these properties are
+  compatible with the one-parameter restriction of Isabelle/HOL's type classes.
+  There is no need to introduce a separate type class instantiated for each
+  sort, like in the old approach.
+
+  We call type @{text "\<beta>"} a \emph{permutation type} if the permutation
+  properties in \eqref{newpermprops} are satisfied for every @{text "x"} of type
+  @{text "\<beta>"}.  This notion allows us to establish generic lemmas, which are
+  applicable to any permutation type.  First, it follows from the laws governing
+  groups that a permutation and its inverse cancel each other.  That is, for any
+  @{text "x"} of a permutation type:
+
+  
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
+  @{thm permute_minus_cancel(1)[where p="\<pi>", no_vars]}\hspace{10mm}
+  @{thm permute_minus_cancel(2)[where p="\<pi>", no_vars]}
+  \end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{cancel}
+  \end{isabelle} 
+  
+  \noindent
+  Consequently, in a permutation type the permutation operation @{text "\<pi> \<bullet> _"} is bijective, 
+  which in turn implies the property
+
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
+  @{thm (lhs) permute_eq_iff[where p="\<pi>", no_vars]}
+  $\;$if and only if$\;$
+  @{thm (rhs) permute_eq_iff[where p="\<pi>", no_vars]}.
+  \end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{permuteequ}
+  \end{isabelle} 
+  
+  \noindent
+  In order to lift the permutation operation to other types, we can define for:
+
+  \begin{isabelle}
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}c@ {\hspace{-1mm}}c@ {}}
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l@ {}}
+  atoms: & @{thm permute_atom_def[where p="\<pi>",no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]}\\
+  functions: &  @{text "\<pi> \<bullet> f \<equiv> \<lambda>x. \<pi> \<bullet> (f ((-\<pi>) \<bullet> x))"}\\
+  permutations: & @{thm permute_perm_def[where p="\<pi>" and q="\<pi>'", THEN eq_reflection]}\\
+  sets: & @{thm permute_set_eq[where p="\<pi>", no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]}\\
+   booleans: & @{thm permute_bool_def[where p="\<pi>", no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]}\\
+  \end{tabular} &
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l@ {}}
+  lists: & @{thm permute_list.simps(1)[where p="\<pi>", no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]}\\
+         & @{thm permute_list.simps(2)[where p="\<pi>", no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]}\\[2mm]
+  products: & @{thm permute_prod.simps[where p="\<pi>", no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]}\\
+  nats: & @{thm permute_nat_def[where p="\<pi>", no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]}\\
+  \end{tabular}
+  \end{tabular}
+  \end{isabelle}
+
+  \noindent
+  and then establish:
+
+  \begin{theorem}
+  If @{text \<beta>}, @{text "\<beta>\<^isub>1"} and @{text "\<beta>\<^isub>2"} are permutation types, 
+  then so are: @{text "atom"}, @{text "\<beta>\<^isub>1 \<Rightarrow> \<beta>\<^isub>2"}, 
+  @{text perm}, @{term "\<beta> set"}, @{term "\<beta> list"}, @{term "\<beta>\<^isub>1 \<times> \<beta>\<^isub>2"},
+  @{text bool} and @{text "nat"}.
+  \end{theorem}
+
+  \begin{proof}
+  All statements are by unfolding the definitions of the permutation operations and simple 
+  calculations involving addition and minus. With permutations for example we 
+  have
+
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}[b]{@ {}rcl}
+  @{text "0 \<bullet> \<pi>'"} & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{text "0 + \<pi>' - 0 = \<pi>'"}\\
+  @{text "(\<pi>\<^isub>1 + \<pi>\<^isub>2) \<bullet> \<pi>'"} & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{text "(\<pi>\<^isub>1 + \<pi>\<^isub>2) + \<pi>' - (\<pi>\<^isub>1 + \<pi>\<^isub>2)"}\\
+  & @{text "="} & @{text "(\<pi>\<^isub>1 + \<pi>\<^isub>2) + \<pi>' - \<pi>\<^isub>2 - \<pi>\<^isub>1"}\\
+  & @{text "="} & @{text "\<pi>\<^isub>1 + (\<pi>\<^isub>2 + \<pi>' - \<pi>\<^isub>2) - \<pi>\<^isub>1"}\\
+  & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{text "\<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> \<pi>\<^isub>2 \<bullet> \<pi>'"} 
+  \end{tabular}\hfill\qed
+  \end{isabelle}
+  \end{proof}
+
+  \noindent
+  The main point is that the above reasoning blends smoothly with the reasoning
+  infrastructure of Isabelle/HOL; no custom ML-code is necessary and a single
+  type class suffices. We can also show once and for all that the following
+  property---which caused so many headaches in our earlier setup---holds for any
+  permutation type.
+
+  \begin{lemma}\label{permutecompose} 
+  Given @{term x} is of permutation type, then 
+  @{text "\<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> (\<pi>\<^isub>2 \<bullet> x) = (\<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> \<pi>\<^isub>2) \<bullet> (\<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> x)"}.
+  \end{lemma}
+
+  \begin{proof} The proof is as follows:
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}[b]{@ {}rcl@ {\hspace{8mm}}l}
+  @{text "\<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> \<pi>\<^isub>2 \<bullet> x"}
+  & @{text "="} & @{text "\<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> \<pi>\<^isub>2 \<bullet> (-\<pi>\<^isub>1) \<bullet> \<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> x"} & by \eqref{cancel}\\
+  & @{text "="} & @{text "(\<pi>\<^isub>1 + \<pi>\<^isub>2 - \<pi>\<^isub>1) \<bullet> \<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> x"}  & by {\rm(\ref{newpermprops}.@{text "ii"})}\\
+  & @{text "\<equiv>"} & @{text "(\<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> \<pi>\<^isub>2) \<bullet> (\<pi>\<^isub>1 \<bullet> x)"}\\
+  \end{tabular}\hfill\qed
+  \end{isabelle}
+  \end{proof}
+
+%* }
+%
+%section { * Equivariance * }
+%
+%text { *
+
+  One huge advantage of using bijective permutation functions (as opposed to
+  non-bijective renaming substitutions) is the property of \emph{equivariance}
+  and the fact that most HOL-functions (this includes constants) whose argument
+  and result types are permutation types satisfy this property:
+
+  \begin{definition}\label{equivariance}
+  A function @{text f} is \emph{equivariant} if @{term "\<forall>\<pi>. \<pi> \<bullet> f = f"}.
+  \end{definition}
+
+  \noindent
+  There are a number of equivalent formulations for the equivariance property. 
+  For example, assuming @{text f} is of type @{text "\<alpha> \<Rightarrow> \<beta>"}, then equivariance 
+  can also be stated as 
+
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
+  @{text "\<forall>\<pi> x.  \<pi> \<bullet> (f x) = f (\<pi> \<bullet> x)"}
+  \end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{altequivariance}
+  \end{isabelle} 
+
+  \noindent
+  To see that this formulation implies the definition, we just unfold the
+  definition of the permutation operation for functions and simplify with the equation
+  and the cancellation property shown in \eqref{cancel}. To see the other direction, we use 
+  the fact 
+  
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
+  @{text "\<pi> \<bullet> (f x) = (\<pi> \<bullet> f) (\<pi> \<bullet> x)"}
+  \end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{permutefunapp}
+  \end{isabelle} 
+
+  \noindent
+  which follows again directly 
+  from the definition of the permutation operation for functions and the cancellation 
+  property. Similarly for functions with more than one argument. 
+
+  Both formulations of equivariance have their advantages and disadvantages:
+  \eqref{altequivariance} is often easier to establish. For example we 
+  can easily show that equality is equivariant
+
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
+  @{thm eq_eqvt[where p="\<pi>", no_vars]}
+  \end{tabular}
+  \end{isabelle} 
+
+  \noindent
+  using the permutation operation on booleans and property \eqref{permuteequ}. 
+  Lemma~\ref{permutecompose} establishes that the permutation operation is 
+  equivariant. It is also easy to see that the boolean operators, like 
+  @{text "\<and>"}, @{text "\<or>"} and @{text "\<longrightarrow>"} are all equivariant. Furthermore 
+  a simple calculation will show that our swapping functions are equivariant, that is
+  
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
+  @{thm swap_eqvt[where p="\<pi>", no_vars]}
+  \end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{swapeqvt}
+  \end{isabelle} 
+
+  \noindent
+  for all @{text a}, @{text b} and @{text \<pi>}.  These equivariance properties
+  are tremendously helpful later on when we have to push permutations inside
+  terms.
+*}
+
+
+section {* Support and Freshness *}
+
+text {*
+  The most original aspect of the nominal logic work of Pitts et al is a general
+  definition for ``the set of free variables of an object @{text "x"}''.  This
+  definition is general in the sense that it applies not only to lambda-terms,
+  but also to lists, products, sets and even functions. The definition depends
+  only on the permutation operation and on the notion of equality defined for
+  the type of @{text x}, namely:
+
+  @{thm [display,indent=10] supp_def[no_vars, THEN eq_reflection]}
+
+  \noindent
+  (Note that due to the definition of swapping in \eqref{swapdef}, we do not
+  need to explicitly restrict @{text a} and @{text b} to have the same sort.)
+  There is also the derived notion for when an atom @{text a} is \emph{fresh}
+  for an @{text x}, defined as
+  
+  @{thm [display,indent=10] fresh_def[no_vars]}
+
+  \noindent
+  A striking consequence of these definitions is that we can prove
+  without knowing anything about the structure of @{term x} that
+  swapping two fresh atoms, say @{text a} and @{text b}, leave 
+  @{text x} unchanged. For the proof we use the following lemma 
+  about swappings applied to an @{text x}:
+
+  \begin{lemma}\label{swaptriple}
+  Assuming @{text x} is of permutation type, and @{text a}, @{text b} and @{text c} 
+  have the same sort, then @{thm (prem 3) swap_rel_trans[no_vars]} and 
+  @{thm (prem 4) swap_rel_trans[no_vars]} imply @{thm (concl) swap_rel_trans[no_vars]}.
+  \end{lemma}
+
+  \begin{proof}
+  The cases where @{text "a = c"} and @{text "b = c"} are immediate.
+  For the remaining case it is, given our assumptions, easy to calculate 
+  that the permutations
+
+  @{thm [display,indent=10] (concl) swap_triple[no_vars]}
+  
+  \noindent
+  are equal. The lemma is then by application of the second permutation 
+  property shown in \eqref{newpermprops}.\hfill\qed
+  \end{proof}
+
+  \begin{theorem}\label{swapfreshfresh}
+  Let @{text x} be of permutation type.
+  @{thm [mode=IfThen] swap_fresh_fresh[no_vars]}
+  \end{theorem}
+
+  \begin{proof}
+  If @{text a} and @{text b} have different sort, then the swapping is the identity.
+  If they have the same sort, we know by definition of support that both
+  @{term "finite {c. (a \<rightleftharpoons> c) \<bullet> x \<noteq> x}"} and  @{term "finite {c. (b \<rightleftharpoons> c) \<bullet> x \<noteq> x}"}
+  hold. So the union of these sets is finite too, and we know by Proposition~\ref{choosefresh} 
+  that there is an atom @{term c}, with the same sort as @{term a} and @{term b}, 
+  that satisfies \mbox{@{term "(a \<rightleftharpoons> c) \<bullet> x = x"}} and @{term "(b \<rightleftharpoons> c) \<bullet> x = x"}. 
+  Now the theorem follows from Lemma~\ref{swaptriple}.\hfill\qed
+  \end{proof}
+  
+  \noindent
+  Two important properties that need to be established for later calculations is 
+  that @{text "supp"} and freshness are equivariant. For this we first show that:
+
+  \begin{lemma}\label{half}
+  If @{term x} is a permutation type, then @{thm (lhs) fresh_permute_iff[where p="\<pi>",no_vars]} 
+  if and only if @{thm (rhs) fresh_permute_iff[where p="\<pi>",no_vars]}.
+  \end{lemma}
+
+  \begin{proof}
+  \begin{isabelle}
+  \begin{tabular}[t]{c@ {\hspace{2mm}}l@ {\hspace{5mm}}l}
+  & @{thm (lhs) fresh_permute_iff[where p="\<pi>",no_vars]}
+  & \\
+  @{text "\<Leftrightarrow>"}
+  & @{term "finite {b. (\<pi> \<bullet> a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> \<pi> \<bullet> x \<noteq> \<pi> \<bullet> x}"}
+  & by definition\\
+  @{text "\<Leftrightarrow>"}
+  & @{term "finite {b. (\<pi> \<bullet> a \<rightleftharpoons> \<pi> \<bullet> b) \<bullet> \<pi> \<bullet> x \<noteq> \<pi> \<bullet> x}"} 
+  & since @{text "\<pi> \<bullet> _"} is bijective\\ 
+  @{text "\<Leftrightarrow>"}
+  & @{term "finite {b. \<pi> \<bullet> (a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> x \<noteq> \<pi> \<bullet> x}"}
+  & by \eqref{permutecompose} and \eqref{swapeqvt}\\
+  @{text "\<Leftrightarrow>"}
+  & @{term "finite {b. (a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> x \<noteq> x}"}
+  & by \eqref{permuteequ}\\
+  @{text "\<Leftrightarrow>"}
+  & @{thm (rhs) fresh_permute_iff[where p="\<pi>",no_vars]}
+  & by definition\\
+  \end{tabular}
+  \end{isabelle}\hfill\qed
+  \end{proof}
+
+  \noindent
+  Together with the definition of the permutation operation on booleans,
+  we can immediately infer equivariance of freshness: 
+
+  @{thm [display,indent=10] fresh_eqvt[where p="\<pi>",no_vars]}
+
+  \noindent
+  Now equivariance of @{text "supp"}, namely
+  
+  @{thm [display,indent=10] supp_eqvt[where p="\<pi>",no_vars]}
+  
+  \noindent
+  is by noting that @{thm supp_conv_fresh[no_vars]} and that freshness and 
+  the logical connectives are equivariant.
+
+  While the abstract properties of support and freshness, particularly 
+  Theorem~\ref{swapfreshfresh}, are useful for developing Nominal Isabelle, 
+  one often has to calculate the support of some concrete object. This is 
+  straightforward for example for booleans, nats, products and lists:
+
+  \begin{center}
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}c@ {\hspace{2mm}}c@ {}}
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l}
+  @{text "booleans"}: & @{term "supp b = {}"}\\
+  @{text "nats"}:     & @{term "supp n = {}"}\\
+  @{text "products"}: & @{thm supp_Pair[no_vars]}\\
+  \end{tabular} &
+  \begin{tabular}{r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l@ {}}
+  @{text "lists:"} & @{thm supp_Nil[no_vars]}\\
+                   & @{thm supp_Cons[no_vars]}\\
+  \end{tabular}
+  \end{tabular}
+  \end{center}
+
+  \noindent
+  But establishing the support of atoms and permutations in our setup here is a bit 
+  trickier. To do so we will use the following notion about a \emph{supporting set}.
+  
+  \begin{definition}
+  A set @{text S} \emph{supports} @{text x} if for all atoms @{text a} and @{text b}
+  not in @{text S} we have @{term "(a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> x = x"}.
+  \end{definition}
+
+  \noindent
+  The main motivation for this notion is that we can characterise @{text "supp x"} 
+  as the smallest finite set that supports @{text "x"}. For this we prove:
+
+  \begin{lemma}\label{supports} Let @{text x} be of permutation type.
+  \begin{isabelle}
+  \begin{tabular}{r@ {\hspace{4mm}}p{10cm}}
+  i)    & @{thm[mode=IfThen] supp_is_subset[no_vars]}\\
+  ii)   & @{thm[mode=IfThen] supp_supports[no_vars]}\\
+  iii)  & @{thm (concl) supp_is_least_supports[no_vars]}
+         provided @{thm (prem 1) supp_is_least_supports[no_vars]},
+         @{thm (prem 2) supp_is_least_supports[no_vars]}
+         and @{text "S"} is the least such set, that means formally:\\[2mm]
+
+        & \multicolumn{1}{c}{for all @{text "S'"}, if @{term "finite S'"} and 
+           @{term "S' supports x"} then @{text "S \<subseteq> S'"}.}
+  \end{tabular}
+  \end{isabelle} 
+  \end{lemma}
+
+  \begin{proof}
+  For @{text "i)"} we derive a contradiction by assuming there is an atom @{text a}
+  with @{term "a \<in> supp x"} and @{text "a \<notin> S"}. Using the second fact, the 
+  assumption that @{term "S supports x"} gives us that @{text S} is a superset of 
+  @{term "{b. (a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> x \<noteq> x}"}, which is finite by the assumption of @{text S}
+  being finite. But this means @{term "a \<notin> supp x"}, contradicting our assumption.
+  Property @{text "ii)"} is by a direct application of 
+  Theorem~\ref{swapfreshfresh}. For the last property, part @{text "i)"} proves
+  one ``half'' of the claimed equation. The other ``half'' is by property 
+  @{text "ii)"} and the fact that @{term "supp x"} is finite by @{text "i)"}.\hfill\qed  
+  \end{proof}
+
+  \noindent
+  These are all relatively straightforward proofs adapted from the existing 
+  nominal logic work. However for establishing the support of atoms and 
+  permutations we found  the following ``optimised'' variant of @{text "iii)"} 
+  more useful:
+
+  \begin{lemma}\label{optimised} Let @{text x} be of permutation type.
+  Then @{thm (concl) finite_supp_unique[no_vars]}
+  provided @{thm (prem 1) finite_supp_unique[no_vars]},
+  @{thm (prem 2) finite_supp_unique[no_vars]}, and for
+  all @{text "a \<in> S"} and all @{text "b \<notin> S"}, with @{text a}
+  and @{text b} having the same sort, then @{term "(a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> x \<noteq> x"}
+  \end{lemma}
+
+  \begin{proof}
+  By Lemma \ref{supports}@{text ".iii)"} we have to show that for every finite
+  set @{text S'} that supports @{text x}, \mbox{@{text "S \<subseteq> S'"}} holds. We will
+  assume that there is an atom @{text "a"} that is element of @{text S}, but
+  not @{text "S'"} and derive a contradiction.  Since both @{text S} and
+  @{text S'} are finite, we can by Proposition \ref{choosefresh} obtain an atom
+  @{text b}, which has the same sort as @{text "a"} and for which we know
+  @{text "b \<notin> S"} and @{text "b \<notin> S'"}. Since we assumed @{text "a \<notin> S'"} and
+  we have that @{text "S' supports x"}, we have on one hand @{term "(a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> x
+  = x"}. On the other hand, the fact @{text "a \<in> S"} and @{text "b \<notin> S"} imply
+  @{term "(a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> x \<noteq> x"} using the assumed implication. This gives us the
+  contradiction.\hfill\qed
+  \end{proof}
+
+  \noindent
+  Using this lemma we only have to show the following three proof-obligations
+
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}r@ {\hspace{4mm}}l}
+  i)   & @{term "{c} supports c"}\\
+  ii)  & @{term "finite {c}"}\\
+  iii) & @{text "\<forall>a \<in> {c} b \<notin> {c}. sort a = sort b \<longrightarrow> (a b) \<bullet> c \<noteq> c"}
+  \end{tabular}
+  \end{isabelle} 
+
+  \noindent
+  in order to establish that @{thm supp_atom[where a="c", no_vars]} holds.  In
+  Isabelle/HOL these proof-obligations can be discharged by easy
+  simplifications. Similar proof-obligations arise for the support of
+  permutations, which is
+
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
+  @{thm supp_perm[where p="\<pi>", no_vars]}
+  \end{tabular}
+  \end{isabelle}
+
+  \noindent
+  The only proof-obligation that is 
+  interesting is the one where we have to show that
+
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
+  @{text "If \<pi> \<bullet> a \<noteq> a, \<pi> \<bullet> b = b and sort a = sort b, then (a b) \<bullet> \<pi> \<noteq> \<pi>"}.
+  \end{tabular}
+  \end{isabelle}
+
+  \noindent
+  For this we observe that 
+
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}rcl}
+  @{thm (lhs) perm_swap_eq[where p="\<pi>", no_vars]} &
+  if and only if &
+  @{thm (rhs) perm_swap_eq[where p="\<pi>", no_vars]}
+  \end{tabular}
+  \end{isabelle}
+
+  \noindent
+  holds by a simple calculation using the group properties of permutations.
+  The proof-obligation can then be discharged by analysing the inequality
+  between the permutations @{term "(p \<bullet> a \<rightleftharpoons> b)"} and @{term "(a \<rightleftharpoons> b)"}.
+
+  The main point about support is that whenever an object @{text x} has finite
+  support, then Proposition~\ref{choosefresh} allows us to choose for @{text x} a 
+  fresh atom with arbitrary sort. This is an important operation in Nominal
+  Isabelle in situations where, for example, a bound variable needs to be
+  renamed. To allow such a choice, we only have to assume \emph{one} premise
+  of the form
+
+  @{text [display,indent=10] "finite (supp x)"}
+
+  \noindent
+  for each @{text x}. Compare that with the sequence of premises in our earlier
+  version of Nominal Isabelle (see~\eqref{fssequence}). For more convenience we
+  can define a type class for types where every element has finite support, and
+  prove that the types @{term "atom"}, @{term "perm"}, lists, products and
+  booleans are instances of this type class. Then \emph{no} premise is needed,
+  as the type system of Isabelle/HOL can figure out automatically when an object
+  is finitely supported.
+
+  Unfortunately, this does not work for sets or Isabelle/HOL's function type.
+  There are functions and sets definable in Isabelle/HOL for which the finite
+  support property does not hold.  A simple example of a function with
+  infinite support is the function that returns the natural number of an atom
+  
+  @{text [display, indent=10] "nat_of (Atom s i) \<equiv> i"}
+
+  \noindent
+  This function's support is the set of \emph{all} atoms. To establish this we show @{term "\<not> a \<sharp> nat_of"}. 
+  This is equivalent to assuming the set @{term "{b. (a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> nat_of \<noteq> nat_of}"} is finite
+  and deriving a contradiction. From the assumption we also know that 
+  @{term "{a} \<union> {b. (a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> nat_of \<noteq> nat_of}"} is finite. Then we can use 
+  Proposition~\ref{choosefresh} to choose an atom @{text c} such that
+  @{term "c \<noteq> a"}, @{term "sort_of c = sort_of a"} and @{term "(a \<rightleftharpoons> c) \<bullet> nat_of = nat_of"}.
+  Now we can reason as follows:
+
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}[b]{@ {}rcl@ {\hspace{5mm}}l}
+  @{text "nat_of a"} & @{text "="} & @{text "(a \<rightleftharpoons> c) \<bullet> (nat_of a)"} & by def.~of permutations on nats\\
+  & @{text "="} & @{term "((a \<rightleftharpoons> c) \<bullet> nat_of) ((a \<rightleftharpoons> c) \<bullet> a)"} & by \eqref{permutefunapp}\\
+  & @{text "="} & @{term "nat_of c"} & by assumptions on @{text c}\\
+  \end{tabular}\hfill\qed
+  \end{isabelle}
+  
+
+  \noindent
+  But this means we have that @{term "nat_of a = nat_of c"} and @{term "sort_of a = sort_of c"}.
+  This implies that atoms @{term a} and @{term c} must be equal, which clashes with our
+  assumption @{term "c \<noteq> a"} about how we chose @{text c}. Similar examples for 
+  constructions that have infinite support are given in~\cite{Cheney06}.
+*}
+
+section {* Concrete Atom Types *}
+
+text {*
+
+  So far, we have presented a system that uses only a single multi-sorted atom
+  type.  This design gives us the flexibility to define operations and prove
+  theorems that are generic with respect to atom sorts.  For example, as
+  illustrated above the @{term supp} function returns a set that includes the
+  free atoms of \emph{all} sorts together; the flexibility offered by the new
+  atom type makes this possible.  
+
+  However, the single multi-sorted atom type does not make an ideal interface
+  for end-users of Nominal Isabelle.  If sorts are not distinguished by
+  Isabelle's type system, users must reason about atom sorts manually.  That
+  means subgoals involving sorts must be discharged explicitly within proof
+  scripts, instead of being inferred by Isabelle/HOL's type checker.  In other
+  cases, lemmas might require additional side conditions about sorts to be true.
+  For example, swapping @{text a} and @{text b} in the pair \mbox{@{term "(a,
+  b)"}} will only produce the expected result if we state the lemma in
+  Isabelle/HOL as:
+*}
+
+          lemma
+	    fixes a b :: "atom"
+	    assumes asm: "sort a = sort b"
+	    shows "(a \<rightleftharpoons> b) \<bullet> (a, b) = (b, a)" 
+          using asm by simp
+
+text {*
+  \noindent
+  Fortunately, it is possible to regain most of the type-checking automation
+  that is lost by moving to a single atom type.  We accomplish this by defining
+  \emph{subtypes} of the generic atom type that only include atoms of a single
+  specific sort.  We call such subtypes \emph{concrete atom types}.
+
+  The following Isabelle/HOL command defines a concrete atom type called
+  \emph{name}, which consists of atoms whose sort equals the string @{term
+  "''name''"}.
+
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \isacommand{typedef}\ \ @{typ name} = @{term "{a. sort\<iota> a = ''name''}"}
+  \end{isabelle}
+
+  \noindent
+  This command automatically generates injective functions that map from the
+  concrete atom type into the generic atom type and back, called
+  representation and abstraction functions, respectively. We will write these
+  functions as follows:
+
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {\hspace{10mm}}l}
+  @{text "\<lfloor>_\<rfloor> :: name \<Rightarrow> atom"} & 
+  @{text "\<lceil>_\<rceil> :: atom \<Rightarrow> name"}
+  \end{tabular}
+  \end{isabelle}
+
+  \noindent
+  With the definition @{thm permute_name_def [where p="\<pi>", THEN
+  eq_reflection, no_vars]}, it is straightforward to verify that the type 
+  @{typ name} is a permutation type.
+
+  In order to reason uniformly about arbitrary concrete atom types, we define a
+  type class that characterises type @{typ name} and other similarly-defined
+  types.  The definition of the concrete atom type class is as follows: First,
+  every concrete atom type must be a permutation type.  In addition, the class
+  defines an overloaded function that maps from the concrete type into the
+  generic atom type, which we will write @{text "|_|"}.  For each class
+  instance, this function must be injective and equivariant, and its outputs
+  must all have the same sort.
+
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}r@ {\hspace{4mm}}p{10cm}}
+  i) & if @{thm (lhs) atom_eq_iff [no_vars]} then @{thm (rhs) atom_eq_iff [no_vars]}\\
+  ii) & @{thm atom_eqvt[where p="\<pi>", no_vars]}\\
+  iii) & @{thm sort_of_atom_eq [no_vars]}
+  \end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{atomprops}
+  \end{isabelle}
+
+  \noindent
+  With the definition @{thm atom_name_def [THEN eq_reflection, no_vars]} we can
+  show that @{typ name} satisfies all the above requirements of a concrete atom
+  type.
+
+  The whole point of defining the concrete atom type class was to let users
+  avoid explicit reasoning about sorts.  This benefit is realised by defining a
+  special swapping operation of type @{text "\<alpha> \<Rightarrow> \<alpha>
+  \<Rightarrow> perm"}, where @{text "\<alpha>"} is a concrete atom type:
+
+  @{thm [display,indent=10] flip_def [THEN eq_reflection, no_vars]}
+
+  \noindent
+  As a consequence of its type, the @{text "\<leftrightarrow>"}-swapping
+  operation works just like the generic swapping operation, but it does not
+  require any sort-checking side conditions---the sort-correctness is ensured by
+  the types!  For @{text "\<leftrightarrow>"} we can establish the following
+  simplification rule:
+
+  @{thm [display,indent=10] permute_flip_at[no_vars]} 
+
+  \noindent
+  If we now want to swap the \emph{concrete} atoms @{text a} and @{text b}
+  in the pair @{term "(a, b)"} we can establish the lemma as follows:
+*}
+
+          lemma
+	    fixes a b :: "name"
+	    shows "(a \<leftrightarrow> b) \<bullet> (a, b) = (b, a)" 
+	  by simp
+
+text {*
+  \noindent
+  There is no need to state an explicit premise involving sorts.
+
+  We can automate the process of creating concrete atom types, so that users 
+  can define a new one simply by issuing the command 
+
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
+  \isacommand{atom\_decl}~~@{text "name"}
+  \end{tabular}
+  \end{isabelle}
+
+  \noindent
+  This command can be implemented using less than 100 lines of custom ML-code.
+  In comparison, the old version of Nominal Isabelle included more than 1000
+  lines of ML-code for creating concrete atom types, and for defining various
+  type classes and instantiating generic lemmas for them.  In addition to
+  simplifying the ML-code, the setup here also offers user-visible improvements:
+  Now concrete atoms can be declared at any point of a formalisation, and
+  theories that separately declare different atom types can be merged
+  together---it is no longer required to collect all atom declarations in one
+  place.
+*}
+
+
+section {* Multi-Sorted Concrete Atoms *}
+
+(*<*)
+datatype ty = TVar string | Fun ty ty ("_ \<rightarrow> _") 
+(*>*)
+
+text {*
+  The formalisation presented so far allows us to streamline proofs and reduce
+  the amount of custom ML-code in the existing implementation of Nominal
+  Isabelle. In this section we describe a mechanism that extends the
+  capabilities of Nominal Isabelle. This mechanism is about variables with 
+  additional information, for example typing constraints.
+  While we leave a detailed treatment of binders and binding of variables for a 
+  later paper, we will have a look here at how such variables can be 
+  represented by concrete atoms.
+  
+  In the previous section we considered concrete atoms that can be used in
+  simple binders like \emph{@{text "\<lambda>x. x"}}.  Such concrete atoms do
+  not carry any information beyond their identities---comparing for equality
+  is really the only way to analyse ordinary concrete atoms.
+  However, in ``Church-style'' lambda-terms \cite{Church40} and in the terms
+  underlying HOL-systems \cite{PittsHOL4} binders and bound variables have a
+  more complicated structure. For example in the ``Church-style'' lambda-term
+
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
+  @{text "\<lambda>x\<^isub>\<alpha>. x\<^isub>\<alpha> x\<^isub>\<beta>"}
+  \end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{church}
+  \end{isabelle}
+
+  \noindent
+  both variables and binders include typing information indicated by @{text
+  \<alpha>} and @{text \<beta>}. In this setting, we treat @{text
+  "x\<^isub>\<alpha>"} and @{text "x\<^isub>\<beta>"} as distinct variables
+  (assuming @{term "\<alpha>\<noteq>\<beta>"}) so that the variable @{text
+  "x\<^isub>\<alpha>"} is bound by the lambda-abstraction, but not @{text
+  "x\<^isub>\<beta>"}.
+
+  To illustrate how we can deal with this phenomenon, let us represent object
+  types like @{text \<alpha>} and @{text \<beta>} by the datatype
+
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
+  \isacommand{datatype}~~@{text "ty = TVar string | ty \<rightarrow> ty"}
+  \end{tabular}
+  \end{isabelle}
+
+  \noindent
+  If we attempt to encode a variable naively as a pair of a @{text name} and a @{text ty}, we have the 
+  problem that a swapping, say @{term "(x \<leftrightarrow> y)"}, applied to the pair
+
+  @{text [display,indent=10] "((x, \<alpha>), (x, \<beta>))"}
+
+  \noindent
+  will always permute \emph{both} occurrences of @{text x}, even if the types
+  @{text "\<alpha>"} and @{text "\<beta>"} are different. This is unwanted, because it will
+  eventually mean that both occurrences of @{text x} will become bound by a
+  corresponding binder. 
+
+  Another attempt might be to define variables as an instance of the concrete
+  atom type class, where a @{text ty} is somehow encoded within each variable.
+  Remember we defined atoms as the datatype:
+*}
+
+          datatype  atom\<iota>\<iota> = Atom\<iota>\<iota> string nat
+  
+text {*
+  \noindent
+  Considering our method of defining concrete atom types, the usage of a string
+  for the sort of atoms seems a natural choice.  However, none of the results so
+  far depend on this choice and we are free to change it.
+  One possibility is to encode types or any other information by making the sort
+  argument parametric as follows:
+*}
+
+          datatype  'a \<iota>atom\<iota>\<iota>\<iota> = \<iota>Atom\<iota>\<iota> 'a nat
+
+text {*
+  \noindent
+  The problem with this possibility is that we are then back in the old
+  situation where our permutation operation is parametric in two types and
+  this would require to work around Isabelle/HOL's restriction on type
+  classes. Fortunately, encoding the types in a separate parameter is not
+  necessary for what we want to achieve, as we only have to know when two
+  types are equal or not. The solution is to use a different sort for each
+  object type.  Then we can use the fact that permutations respect \emph{sorts} to
+  ensure that permutations also respect \emph{object types}.  In order to do
+  this, we must define an injective function @{text "sort_ty"} mapping from
+  object types to sorts.  For defining functions like @{text "sort_ty"}, it is
+  more convenient to use a tree datatype for sorts. Therefore we define
+*}
+
+          datatype  sort = Sort string "(sort list)"
+          datatype  atom\<iota>\<iota>\<iota>\<iota> = Atom\<iota>\<iota>\<iota>\<iota> sort nat
+
+text {*
+  \noindent
+  With this definition,
+  the sorts we considered so far can be encoded just as \mbox{@{text "Sort s []"}}.
+  The point, however, is that we can now define the function @{text sort_ty} simply as
+
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
+  @{text "sort_ty (TVar s) = Sort ''TVar'' [Sort s []]"}\\
+  @{text "sort_ty (\<tau>\<^isub>1 \<rightarrow> \<tau>\<^isub>2) = Sort ''Fun''  [sort_ty \<tau>\<^isub>1, sort_ty \<tau>\<^isub>2]"}
+  \end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{sortty}
+  \end{isabelle}
+
+  \noindent
+  which can easily be shown to be injective.  
+  
+  Having settled on what the the sorts should be for ``Church-like'' atoms, we have to
+  give a subtype definition for concrete atoms. Previously we identified a subtype consisting 
+  of atoms of only one specified sort. This must be generalised to all sorts the
+  function @{text "sort_ty"} might produce, i.e.~the
+  range of @{text "sort_ty"}. Therefore we define
+
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \isacommand{typedef}\ \ @{text var} = @{term "{a. sort a : range sort_ty}"}
+  \end{isabelle}
+
+  \noindent
+  This command gives us again injective representation and abstraction
+  functions. We will write them also as \mbox{@{text "\<lfloor>_\<rfloor> :: var \<Rightarrow> atom"}} and
+  @{text "\<lceil>_\<rceil> :: atom \<Rightarrow> var"}, respectively. 
+
+  We can define the permutation operation for @{text var} as @{thm
+  permute_var_def[where p="\<pi>", THEN eq_reflection, no_vars]} and the
+  injective function to type @{typ atom} as @{thm atom_var_def[THEN
+  eq_reflection, no_vars]}. Finally, we can define a constructor function that
+  makes a @{text var} from a variable name and an object type:
+
+  @{thm [display,indent=10] Var_def[where t="\<alpha>", THEN eq_reflection, no_vars]}
+
+  \noindent
+  With these definitions we can verify all the properties for concrete atom
+  types except Property \ref{atomprops}@{text ".iii)"}, which requires every
+  atom to have the same sort.  This last property is clearly not true for type
+  @{text "var"}.
+  This fact is slightly unfortunate since this
+  property allowed us to use the type-checker in order to shield the user from
+  all sort-constraints.  But this failure is expected here, because we cannot
+  burden the type-system of Isabelle/HOL with the task of deciding when two
+  object types are equal.  This means we sometimes need to explicitly state sort
+  constraints or explicitly discharge them, but as we will see in the lemma
+  below this seems a natural price to pay in these circumstances.
+
+  To sum up this section, the encoding of type-information into atoms allows us 
+  to form the swapping @{term "(Var x \<alpha> \<leftrightarrow> Var y \<alpha>)"} and to prove the following 
+  lemma
+*}
+
+          lemma
+	    assumes asm: "\<alpha> \<noteq> \<beta>" 
+	    shows "(Var x \<alpha> \<leftrightarrow> Var y \<alpha>) \<bullet> (Var x \<alpha>, Var x \<beta>) = (Var y \<alpha>, Var x \<beta>)"
+	    using asm by simp
+
+text {*
+  \noindent 
+  As we expect, the atom @{term "Var x \<beta>"} is left unchanged by the
+  swapping. With this we can faithfully represent bindings in languages
+  involving ``Church-style'' terms and bindings as shown in \eqref{church}. We
+  expect that the creation of such atoms can be easily automated so that the
+  user just needs to specify
+
+  \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ %%%
+  \begin{tabular}{@ {}l}
+  \isacommand{atom\_decl}~~@{text "var (ty)"}
+  \end{tabular}
+  \end{isabelle}
+  
+  \noindent
+  where the argument, or arguments, are datatypes for which we can automatically
+  define an injective function like @{text "sort_ty"} (see \eqref{sortty}).
+  Our hope is that with this approach the authors of \cite{PaulsonBenzmueller} 
+  can make headway with formalising their results about simple type theory.  
+  Because of its limitations, they did not attempt this with the old version 
+  of Nominal Isabelle. We also hope we can make progress with formalisations of
+  HOL-based languages.
+*}
+
+
+section {* Conclusion *}
+
+text {*
+  This proof pearl describes a new formalisation of the nominal logic work by
+  Pitts et al. With the definitions we presented here, the formal reasoning blends 
+  smoothly with the infrastructure of the Isabelle/HOL theorem prover. 
+  Therefore the formalisation will be the underlying theory for a 
+  new version of Nominal Isabelle.
+
+  The main difference of this paper with respect to existing work on Nominal
+  Isabelle is the representation of atoms and permutations. First, we used a
+  single type for sorted atoms. This design choice means for a term @{term t},
+  say, that its support is completely characterised by @{term "supp t"}, even
+  if the term contains different kinds of atoms. Also, whenever we have to
+  generalise an induction so that a property @{text P} is not just established
+  for all @{text t}, but for all @{text t} \emph{and} under all permutations
+  @{text \<pi>}, then we only have to state @{term "\<forall>\<pi>. P (\<pi> \<bullet> t)"}. The reason is
+  that permutations can now consist of multiple swapping each of which can
+  swap different kinds of atoms. This simplifies considerably the reasoning
+  involved in building Nominal Isabelle.
+
+  Second, we represented permutation as functions so that the associated
+  permutation operation has only a single type parameter. From this we derive
+  most benefits because the abstract reasoning about permutations fits cleanly
+  with Isabelle/HOL's type classes. No custom ML-code is required to work
+  around rough edges. Moreover, by establishing that our permutations-as-functions
+  representation satisfy the group properties, we were able to use extensively 
+  Isabelle/HOL's reasoning infrastructure for groups. This often reduced proofs 
+  to simple calculations over @{text "+"}, @{text "-"} and @{text "0"}.
+  An interesting point is that we defined the swapping operation so that a 
+  swapping of two atoms with different sorts is \emph{not} excluded, like 
+  in our older work on Nominal Isabelle, but there is no ``effect'' of such 
+  a swapping (it is defined as the identity). This is a crucial insight
+  in order to make the approach based on a single type of sorted atoms to work.
+
+  We noticed only one disadvantage of the permutations-as-functions: Over
+  lists we can easily perform inductions. For permutation made up from
+  functions, we have to manually derive an appropriate induction principle. We
+  can establish such a principle, but we have no experience yet whether ours
+  is the most useful principle: such an induction principle was not needed in
+  any of the reasoning we ported from the old Nominal Isabelle.
+
+  Finally, our implementation of sorted atoms turned out powerful enough to
+  use it for representing variables that carry additional information, for
+  example typing annotations. This information is encoded into the sorts. With
+  this we can represent conveniently binding in ``Church-style'' lambda-terms
+  and HOL-based languages. We are not aware of any other approach proposed for
+  language formalisations that can deal conveniently with such binders.
+ 
+  The formalisation presented here will eventually become part of the Isabelle 
+  distribution, but for the moment it can be downloaded from the 
+  Mercurial repository linked at 
+  \href{http://isabelle.in.tum.de/nominal/download}
+  {http://isabelle.in.tum.de/nominal/download}.\medskip
+
+  \noindent
+  {\bf Acknowledgements:} We are very grateful to Jesper Bengtson, Stefan 
+  Berghofer and Cezary Kaliszyk for their comments on earlier versions 
+  of this paper.
+  
+*}
+
+
+(*<*)
+end
+(*>*)
\ No newline at end of file