1 (*<*) |
|
2 theory Paper |
|
3 imports "Quotient" |
|
4 "~~/src/HOL/Library/Quotient_Syntax" |
|
5 "~~/src/HOL/Library/LaTeXsugar" |
|
6 "~~/src/HOL/Quotient_Examples/FSet" |
|
7 begin |
|
8 |
|
9 notation (latex output) |
|
10 rel_conj ("_ \<circ>\<circ>\<circ> _" [53, 53] 52) and |
|
11 pred_comp ("_ \<circ>\<circ> _" [1, 1] 30) and |
|
12 implies (infix "\<longrightarrow>" 100) and |
|
13 "==>" (infix "\<Longrightarrow>" 100) and |
|
14 map_fun ("_ \<singlearr> _" 51) and |
|
15 fun_rel ("_ \<doublearr> _" 51) and |
|
16 list_eq (infix "\<approx>" 50) and (* Not sure if we want this notation...? *) |
|
17 empty_fset ("\<emptyset>") and |
|
18 union_fset ("_ \<union> _") and |
|
19 insert_fset ("{_} \<union> _") and |
|
20 Cons ("_::_") and |
|
21 concat ("flat") and |
|
22 concat_fset ("\<Union>") and |
|
23 Quotient ("Quot _ _ _") |
|
24 |
|
25 declare [[show_question_marks = false]] |
|
26 |
|
27 ML {* |
|
28 fun nth_conj n (_, r) = nth (HOLogic.dest_conj r) n; |
|
29 |
|
30 fun style_lhs_rhs proj = Scan.succeed (fn ctxt => fn t => |
|
31 let |
|
32 val concl = |
|
33 Object_Logic.drop_judgment (Proof_Context.theory_of ctxt) (Logic.strip_imp_concl t) |
|
34 in |
|
35 case concl of (_ $ l $ r) => proj (l, r) |
|
36 | _ => error ("Binary operator expected in term: " ^ Syntax.string_of_term ctxt concl) |
|
37 end); |
|
38 *} |
|
39 |
|
40 setup {* |
|
41 Term_Style.setup "rhs1" (style_lhs_rhs (nth_conj 0)) #> |
|
42 Term_Style.setup "rhs2" (style_lhs_rhs (nth_conj 1)) #> |
|
43 Term_Style.setup "rhs3" (style_lhs_rhs (nth_conj 2)) |
|
44 *} |
|
45 |
|
46 fun add_pair :: "(nat \<times> nat) \<Rightarrow> (nat \<times> nat) \<Rightarrow> (nat \<times> nat)" |
|
47 where "add_pair (n1, m1) (n2, m2) = (n1 + n2, m1 + m2)" |
|
48 |
|
49 fun minus_pair :: "(nat \<times> nat) \<Rightarrow> (nat \<times> nat)" |
|
50 where "minus_pair (n, m) = (m, n)" |
|
51 |
|
52 fun |
|
53 intrel :: "(nat \<times> nat) \<Rightarrow> (nat \<times> nat) \<Rightarrow> bool" ("_ \<approx> _" [50, 50] 50) |
|
54 where |
|
55 "intrel (x, y) (u, v) = (x + v = u + y)" |
|
56 |
|
57 (*>*) |
|
58 |
|
59 section {* Introduction *} |
|
60 |
|
61 text {* |
|
62 \noindent |
|
63 One might think quotients have been studied to death, but in the |
|
64 context of theorem provers a number questions concerning them are |
|
65 far from settled. In this paper we address the question of how to |
|
66 establish a convenient reasoning infrastructure for quotient |
|
67 constructions in the Isabelle/HOL theorem prover. Higher-Order Logic |
|
68 (HOL) consists of a small number of axioms and inference rules over |
|
69 a simply-typed term-language. Safe reasoning in HOL is ensured by |
|
70 two very restricted mechanisms for extending the logic: one is the |
|
71 definition of new constants in terms of existing ones; the other is |
|
72 the introduction of new types by identifying non-empty subsets in |
|
73 existing types. Previous work has shown how to use both mechanisms |
|
74 for dealing with quotient constructions in HOL (see |
|
75 \cite{Homeier05,Paulson06}). For example the integers in |
|
76 Isabelle/HOL are constructed by a quotient construction over the |
|
77 type @{typ "nat \<times> nat"} and the equivalence relation |
|
78 |
|
79 |
|
80 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
81 @{text "(n\<^isub>1, n\<^isub>2) \<approx> (m\<^isub>1, m\<^isub>2) \<equiv> n\<^isub>1 + m\<^isub>2 = m\<^isub>1 + n\<^isub>2"}\hfill\numbered{natpairequiv} |
|
82 \end{isabelle} |
|
83 |
|
84 \noindent |
|
85 This constructions yields the new type @{typ int}, and definitions for @{text |
|
86 "0"} and @{text "1"} of type @{typ int} can be given in terms of pairs of |
|
87 natural numbers (namely @{text "(0, 0)"} and @{text "(1, 0)"}). Operations |
|
88 such as @{text "add"} with type @{typ "int \<Rightarrow> int \<Rightarrow> int"} can be defined |
|
89 in terms of operations on pairs of natural numbers: |
|
90 |
|
91 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
92 @{thm add_pair.simps[where ?n1.0="n\<^isub>1" and ?n2.0="n\<^isub>2" and ?m1.0="m\<^isub>1" and ?m2.0="m\<^isub>2", THEN eq_reflection]}% |
|
93 \hfill\numbered{addpair} |
|
94 \end{isabelle} |
|
95 |
|
96 \noindent |
|
97 Negation on integers is defined in terms of swapping of pairs: |
|
98 |
|
99 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
100 @{thm minus_pair.simps[where ?n="n" and ?m="m", THEN eq_reflection]}% |
|
101 \hfill\numbered{minuspair} |
|
102 \end{isabelle} |
|
103 |
|
104 \noindent |
|
105 Similarly one can construct the type of finite sets, written @{term |
|
106 "\<alpha> fset"}, by quotienting the type @{text "\<alpha> list"} according to the |
|
107 equivalence relation |
|
108 |
|
109 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
110 @{text "xs \<approx> ys \<equiv> (\<forall>x. memb x xs \<longleftrightarrow> memb x ys)"}\hfill\numbered{listequiv} |
|
111 \end{isabelle} |
|
112 |
|
113 \noindent |
|
114 which states that two lists are equivalent if every element in one |
|
115 list is also member in the other, and vice versa. The empty finite |
|
116 set, written @{term "{||}"}, can then be defined as the empty list |
|
117 and the union of two finite sets, written @{text "\<union>"}, as list |
|
118 append. |
|
119 |
|
120 Quotients are important in a variety of areas, but they are really ubiquitous in |
|
121 the area of reasoning about programming language calculi. A simple example |
|
122 is the lambda-calculus, whose raw, or un-quotient, terms are defined as |
|
123 |
|
124 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
125 @{text "t ::= x | t t | \<lambda>x.t"}%\hfill\numbered{lambda} |
|
126 \end{isabelle} |
|
127 |
|
128 \noindent |
|
129 The problem with this definition arises from the need to reason |
|
130 modulo $\alpha$-equivalence, for instance, when one attempts to |
|
131 prove formally the substitution lemma \cite{Barendregt81} by |
|
132 induction over the structure of terms. This can be fiendishly |
|
133 complicated (see \cite[Pages 94--104]{CurryFeys58} for some |
|
134 ``rough'' sketches of a proof about raw lambda-terms). In contrast, |
|
135 if we reason about $\alpha$-equated lambda-terms, that means terms |
|
136 quotient according to $\alpha$-equivalence, then the reasoning |
|
137 infrastructure provided, for example, by Nominal Isabelle |
|
138 \cite{UrbanKaliszyk11} makes the formal proof of the substitution |
|
139 lemma almost trivial. The fundamental reason is that in case of |
|
140 $\alpha$-equated terms, equality coincides with $\alpha$-equivalence and |
|
141 we can use for reasoning HOL's built-in notion of ``replacing equals by equals''. |
|
142 |
|
143 There is also often a need to consider quotients of parial equivalence relations. For |
|
144 example the rational numbers |
|
145 can be constructed using pairs of integers and the partial equivalence relation |
|
146 |
|
147 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
148 @{text "(n\<^isub>1, n\<^isub>2) \<approx> (m\<^isub>1, m\<^isub>2) \<equiv> n\<^isub>1 * m\<^isub>2 = m\<^isub>1 * n\<^isub>2"}\hfill\numbered{ratpairequiv} |
|
149 \end{isabelle} |
|
150 |
|
151 \noindent |
|
152 where @{text "n\<^isub>2"} and @{text "m\<^isub>2"} are not allowed to be zero. |
|
153 |
|
154 The difficulty is that in order to be able to reason about integers, |
|
155 finite sets, etc.~one needs to establish a reasoning infrastructure |
|
156 by transferring, or \emph{lifting}, definitions and theorems from |
|
157 the raw type @{typ "nat \<times> nat"} to the quotient type @{typ int} |
|
158 (similarly for finite sets, $\alpha$-equated lambda-terms and |
|
159 rational numbers). This lifting usually requires a reasoning effort |
|
160 that can be rather repetitive and involves explicit conversions |
|
161 between the quotient and raw level in form of abstraction and |
|
162 representation functions \cite{Paulson06}. In principle it is feasible to do this |
|
163 work manually if one has only a few quotient constructions at |
|
164 hand. But if they have to be done over and over again, as in Nominal |
|
165 Isabelle, then manual reasoning is not an option. |
|
166 |
|
167 The purpose of a \emph{quotient package} is to ease the lifting of |
|
168 theorems and automate the reasoning as much as possible. Before we |
|
169 delve into the details, let us show how the user interacts with our |
|
170 quotient package when defining integers. We assume the definitions |
|
171 involving pairs of natural numbers shown in \eqref{natpairequiv}, |
|
172 \eqref{addpair} and \eqref{minuspair} have already been made. A |
|
173 quotient can then be introduced by declaring the new type (in this case |
|
174 @{typ int}), the raw type (that is @{typ "nat \<times> nat"}) and the |
|
175 equivalence relation (that is @{text intrel} defined in |
|
176 \eqref{natpairequiv}). |
|
177 *} |
|
178 |
|
179 quotient_type int = "nat \<times> nat" / intrel |
|
180 |
|
181 txt {* |
|
182 \noindent |
|
183 This declaration requires the user to prove that @{text intrel} is |
|
184 indeed an equivalence relation, whereby an equivalence |
|
185 relation is defined as one that is reflexive, symmetric and |
|
186 transitive. This proof obligation can thus be discharged by |
|
187 unfolding the definitions and using the standard automatic proving |
|
188 tactic in Isabelle/HOL. |
|
189 *} |
|
190 unfolding equivp_reflp_symp_transp |
|
191 unfolding reflp_def symp_def transp_def |
|
192 by auto |
|
193 (*<*) |
|
194 instantiation int :: "{zero, one, plus, uminus}" |
|
195 begin |
|
196 (*>*) |
|
197 text {* |
|
198 \noindent |
|
199 Next we can declare the constants @{text "0"} and @{text "1"} for the |
|
200 quotient type @{text int}. |
|
201 *} |
|
202 quotient_definition |
|
203 "0 \<Colon> int" is "(0\<Colon>nat, 0\<Colon>nat)" . |
|
204 |
|
205 quotient_definition |
|
206 "1 \<Colon> int" is "(1\<Colon>nat, 0\<Colon>nat)" . |
|
207 |
|
208 text {* |
|
209 \noindent |
|
210 To be useful, we can also need declare two operations for adding two |
|
211 integers (written @{text plus}) and negating an integer |
|
212 (written @{text "uminus"}). |
|
213 *} |
|
214 |
|
215 quotient_definition |
|
216 "plus \<Colon> int \<Rightarrow> int \<Rightarrow> int" is add_pair |
|
217 by auto |
|
218 |
|
219 quotient_definition |
|
220 "uminus \<Colon> int \<Rightarrow> int" is minus_pair |
|
221 by auto |
|
222 (*<*) |
|
223 instance .. |
|
224 |
|
225 end |
|
226 (*>*) |
|
227 |
|
228 text {* |
|
229 \noindent |
|
230 Isabelle/HOL can introduce some convenient short-hand notation for these |
|
231 operations allowing the user to write |
|
232 addition as infix operation, for example @{text "i + j"}, and |
|
233 negation as prefix operation, for example @{text "- i"}. In both |
|
234 cases, however, the declaration requires the user to discharge a |
|
235 proof-obligation which ensures that the operations a |
|
236 \emph{respectful}. This property ensures that the operations are |
|
237 well-defined on the quotient level (a formal definition of |
|
238 respectfulness will be given later). Both proofs can be solved by |
|
239 the automatic proving tactic in Isabelle/HOL. |
|
240 |
|
241 Besides helping with declarations of quotient types and definitions |
|
242 of constants, the point of a quotient package is to help with |
|
243 proving properties about quotient types. For example we might be |
|
244 interested in the usual property that zero is an ???. This property |
|
245 can be stated as follows: |
|
246 *} |
|
247 |
|
248 lemma zero_add: |
|
249 shows "0 + i = (i::int)" |
|
250 proof(descending) |
|
251 txt {* |
|
252 \noindent |
|
253 The tactic @{text "descending"} automatically transfers this property of integers |
|
254 to a proof-obligation involving pairs of @{typ nat}s. (There is also |
|
255 a tactic, called @{text lifting}, which automatically transfers properties |
|
256 from the raw level to the quotient type.) In case of lemma @{text "zero_add"} |
|
257 we obtain the subgoal |
|
258 |
|
259 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
260 @{text "add_pair (0, 0) i \<approx> i"} |
|
261 \end{isabelle} |
|
262 |
|
263 \noindent |
|
264 which can be solved again by the automatic proving tactic @{text "auto"}, as follows |
|
265 *} |
|
266 qed(auto) |
|
267 |
|
268 text {* |
|
269 In this simple example the task of the user is to state the property for integers |
|
270 and use the quotient package and automatic proving tools of Isabelle/HOL to do |
|
271 the ``rest''. A more interesting example is to establish an induction principle for |
|
272 integers. For this we first establish the following induction principle where the |
|
273 induction proceeds over two natural numbers. |
|
274 *} |
|
275 |
|
276 lemma nat_induct2: |
|
277 assumes "P 0 0" |
|
278 and "\<And>n m. P n m \<Longrightarrow> P (Suc n) m" |
|
279 and "\<And>n m. P n m \<Longrightarrow> P n (Suc m)" |
|
280 shows "P n m" |
|
281 using assms |
|
282 by (induction_schema) (pat_completeness, lexicographic_order) |
|
283 |
|
284 text {* |
|
285 \noindent |
|
286 The symbol @{text "\<And>"} stands for Isabelle/HOL's universal quantifier and |
|
287 @{text "\<Longrightarrow>"} for its implication. |
|
288 As can be seen, this induction principle can be conveniently established using the |
|
289 reasoning infrastructure of the function package \cite{???}, which |
|
290 provides the tactics @{text "induction_schema"}, @{text "pat_completeness"} |
|
291 and @{text "lexicographic_order"}. These tactics enable Isabelle/HOL |
|
292 to use well-founded induction to prove @{text "nat_induct2"}. Our |
|
293 quotient package can now be used to prove the following property: |
|
294 *} |
|
295 |
|
296 lemma int_induct: |
|
297 assumes "P 0" |
|
298 and "\<And>i. P i \<Longrightarrow> P (i + 1)" |
|
299 and "\<And>i. P i \<Longrightarrow> P (i + (- 1))" |
|
300 shows "P (j::int)" |
|
301 using assms |
|
302 proof (descending) |
|
303 |
|
304 txt {* |
|
305 \noindent |
|
306 The @{text descending} tactic transfers it to the following proof |
|
307 obligation on the raw level. |
|
308 |
|
309 @{subgoals[display]} |
|
310 |
|
311 \noindent |
|
312 Note that the variable @{text "j"} in this subgoal is of type |
|
313 @{text "nat \<times> nat"}. This subgoal cannot be proved automatically by |
|
314 @{text auto}, but if we give it the hint to use @{text nat_induct2}, |
|
315 then @{text auto} can discharge it as follows. |
|
316 |
|
317 *} |
|
318 qed (auto intro: nat_induct2) |
|
319 |
|
320 text {* |
|
321 This completes the proof of the induction principle |
|
322 for integers. Isabelle/HOL would allow us to inspect the |
|
323 detailed reasoning steps involved which would confirm that |
|
324 @{text "int_induct"} has been proved from ``first-principles'' |
|
325 by transforming the property over the quotient type @{text int} |
|
326 to a corresponding property one on the raw level. |
|
327 |
|
328 |
|
329 In the |
|
330 context of HOL, there have been a few quotient packages already |
|
331 \cite{harrison-thesis,Slotosch97}. The most notable one is by Homeier |
|
332 \cite{Homeier05} implemented in HOL4. The fundamental construction these |
|
333 quotient packages perform can be illustrated by the following picture: |
|
334 |
|
335 %%% FIXME: Referee 1 says: |
|
336 %%% Diagram is unclear. Firstly, isn't an existing type a "set (not sets) of raw elements"? |
|
337 %%% Secondly, isn't the _set of_ equivalence classes mapped to and from the new type? |
|
338 %%% Thirdly, what do the words "non-empty subset" refer to ? |
|
339 |
|
340 %%% Cezary: I like the diagram, maybe 'new type' could be outside, but otherwise |
|
341 %%% I wouldn't change it. |
|
342 |
|
343 \begin{center} |
|
344 \mbox{}\hspace{20mm}\begin{tikzpicture}[scale=1.1] |
|
345 %%\draw[step=2mm] (-4,-1) grid (4,1); |
|
346 |
|
347 \draw[very thick] (0.7,0.3) circle (4.85mm); |
|
348 \draw[rounded corners=1mm, very thick] ( 0.0,-0.9) rectangle ( 1.8, 0.9); |
|
349 \draw[rounded corners=1mm, very thick] (-1.95,0.8) rectangle (-2.9,-0.195); |
|
350 |
|
351 \draw (-2.0, 0.8) -- (0.7,0.8); |
|
352 \draw (-2.0,-0.195) -- (0.7,-0.195); |
|
353 |
|
354 \draw ( 0.7, 0.23) node {\begin{tabular}{@ {}c@ {}}equiv-\\[-1mm]clas.\end{tabular}}; |
|
355 \draw (-2.45, 0.35) node {\begin{tabular}{@ {}c@ {}}new\\[-1mm]type\end{tabular}}; |
|
356 \draw (1.8, 0.35) node[right=-0.1mm] |
|
357 {\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}}existing\\[-1mm] type\\ (sets of raw elements)\end{tabular}}; |
|
358 \draw (0.9, -0.55) node {\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}}non-empty\\[-1mm]subset\end{tabular}}; |
|
359 |
|
360 \draw[->, very thick] (-1.8, 0.36) -- (-0.1,0.36); |
|
361 \draw[<-, very thick] (-1.8, 0.16) -- (-0.1,0.16); |
|
362 \draw (-0.95, 0.26) node[above=0.4mm] {@{text Rep}}; |
|
363 \draw (-0.95, 0.26) node[below=0.4mm] {@{text Abs}}; |
|
364 \end{tikzpicture} |
|
365 \end{center} |
|
366 |
|
367 \noindent |
|
368 The starting point is an existing type, to which we refer as the |
|
369 \emph{raw type} and over which an equivalence relation is given by the user. |
|
370 With this input the package introduces a new type, to which we |
|
371 refer as the \emph{quotient type}. This type comes with an |
|
372 \emph{abstraction} and a \emph{representation} function, written @{text Abs} |
|
373 and @{text Rep}.\footnote{Actually slightly more basic functions are given; |
|
374 the functions @{text Abs} and @{text Rep} need to be derived from them. We |
|
375 will show the details later. } They relate elements in the |
|
376 existing type to elements in the new type, % and vice versa, |
|
377 and can be uniquely |
|
378 identified by their quotient type. For example for the integer quotient construction |
|
379 the types of @{text Abs} and @{text Rep} are |
|
380 |
|
381 |
|
382 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
383 @{text "Abs :: nat \<times> nat \<Rightarrow> int"}\hspace{10mm}@{text "Rep :: int \<Rightarrow> nat \<times> nat"} |
|
384 \end{isabelle} |
|
385 |
|
386 \noindent |
|
387 We therefore often write @{text Abs_int} and @{text Rep_int} if the |
|
388 typing information is important. |
|
389 |
|
390 Every abstraction and representation function stands for an isomorphism |
|
391 between the non-empty subset and elements in the new type. They are |
|
392 necessary for making definitions involving the new type. For example @{text |
|
393 "0"} and @{text "1"} of type @{typ int} can be defined as |
|
394 |
|
395 |
|
396 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
397 @{text "0 \<equiv> Abs_int (0, 0)"}\hspace{10mm}@{text "1 \<equiv> Abs_int (1, 0)"} |
|
398 \end{isabelle} |
|
399 |
|
400 \noindent |
|
401 Slightly more complicated is the definition of @{text "add"} having type |
|
402 @{typ "int \<Rightarrow> int \<Rightarrow> int"}. Its definition is as follows |
|
403 |
|
404 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
405 @{text "add n m \<equiv> Abs_int (add_pair (Rep_int n) (Rep_int m))"} |
|
406 \hfill\numbered{adddef} |
|
407 \end{isabelle} |
|
408 |
|
409 \noindent |
|
410 where we take the representation of the arguments @{text n} and @{text m}, |
|
411 add them according to the function @{text "add_pair"} and then take the |
|
412 abstraction of the result. This is all straightforward and the existing |
|
413 quotient packages can deal with such definitions. But what is surprising is |
|
414 that none of them can deal with slightly more complicated definitions involving |
|
415 \emph{compositions} of quotients. Such compositions are needed for example |
|
416 in case of quotienting lists to yield finite sets and the operator that |
|
417 flattens lists of lists, defined as follows |
|
418 |
|
419 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
420 \begin{tabular}{@ {}l} |
|
421 @{thm concat.simps(1)[THEN eq_reflection]}\\ |
|
422 @{thm concat.simps(2)[THEN eq_reflection, where x1="x" and xs1="xs"]} |
|
423 \end{tabular} |
|
424 \end{isabelle} |
|
425 |
|
426 \noindent |
|
427 where @{text "@"} is the usual |
|
428 list append. We expect that the corresponding |
|
429 operator on finite sets, written @{term "fconcat"}, |
|
430 builds finite unions of finite sets: |
|
431 |
|
432 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
433 \begin{tabular}{@ {}l} |
|
434 @{thm concat_empty_fset[THEN eq_reflection]}\\ |
|
435 @{thm concat_insert_fset[THEN eq_reflection, where x1="x" and S1="S"]} |
|
436 \end{tabular} |
|
437 \end{isabelle} |
|
438 |
|
439 \noindent |
|
440 The quotient package should automatically provide us with a definition for @{text "\<Union>"} in |
|
441 terms of @{text flat}, @{text Rep_fset} and @{text Abs_fset}. The problem is |
|
442 that the method used in the existing quotient |
|
443 packages of just taking the representation of the arguments and then taking |
|
444 the abstraction of the result is \emph{not} enough. The reason is that in case |
|
445 of @{text "\<Union>"} we obtain the incorrect definition |
|
446 |
|
447 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
448 @{text "\<Union> S \<equiv> Abs_fset (flat (Rep_fset S))"} |
|
449 \end{isabelle} |
|
450 |
|
451 \noindent |
|
452 where the right-hand side is not even typable! This problem can be remedied in the |
|
453 existing quotient packages by introducing an intermediate step and reasoning |
|
454 about flattening of lists of finite sets. However, this remedy is rather |
|
455 cumbersome and inelegant in light of our work, which can deal with such |
|
456 definitions directly. The solution is that we need to build aggregate |
|
457 representation and abstraction functions, which in case of @{text "\<Union>"} |
|
458 generate the %%%following |
|
459 definition |
|
460 |
|
461 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
462 @{text "\<Union> S \<equiv> Abs_fset (flat ((map_list Rep_fset \<circ> Rep_fset) S))"} |
|
463 \end{isabelle} |
|
464 |
|
465 \noindent |
|
466 where @{term map_list} is the usual mapping function for lists. In this paper we |
|
467 will present a formal definition of our aggregate abstraction and |
|
468 representation functions (this definition was omitted in \cite{Homeier05}). |
|
469 They generate definitions, like the one above for @{text "\<Union>"}, |
|
470 according to the type of the raw constant and the type |
|
471 of the quotient constant. This means we also have to extend the notions |
|
472 of \emph{aggregate equivalence relation}, \emph{respectfulness} and \emph{preservation} |
|
473 from Homeier \cite{Homeier05}. |
|
474 |
|
475 {\bf EXAMPLE BY HUFFMAN @{thm map_concat_fset}} |
|
476 |
|
477 %%%TODO Update the contents. |
|
478 |
|
479 In addition we are able to clearly specify what is involved |
|
480 in the lifting process (this was only hinted at in \cite{Homeier05} and |
|
481 implemented as a ``rough recipe'' in ML-code). A pleasing side-result |
|
482 is that our procedure for lifting theorems is completely deterministic |
|
483 following the structure of the theorem being lifted and the theorem |
|
484 on the quotient level. {\it Space constraints, unfortunately, allow us to only |
|
485 sketch this part of our work in Section 5 and we defer the reader to a longer |
|
486 version for the details.} However, we will give in Section 3 and 4 all |
|
487 definitions that specify the input and output data of our three-step |
|
488 lifting procedure. Appendix A gives an example how our quotient |
|
489 package works in practise. |
|
490 *} |
|
491 |
|
492 section {* Preliminaries and General Quotients\label{sec:prelims} *} |
|
493 |
|
494 text {* |
|
495 \noindent |
|
496 We will give in this section a crude overview of HOL and describe the main |
|
497 definitions given by Homeier for quotients \cite{Homeier05}. |
|
498 |
|
499 At its core, HOL is based on a simply-typed term language, where types are |
|
500 recorded in Church-style fashion (that means, we can always infer the type of |
|
501 a term and its subterms without any additional information). The grammars |
|
502 for types and terms are |
|
503 |
|
504 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
505 \begin{tabular}{@ {}c@ {\hspace{10mm}}c@ {}} |
|
506 @{text "\<sigma>, \<tau> ::= \<alpha> | (\<sigma>,\<dots>, \<sigma>) \<kappa>"} & |
|
507 @{text "t, s ::= x\<^isup>\<sigma> | c\<^isup>\<sigma> | t t | \<lambda>x\<^isup>\<sigma>. t"}\\ |
|
508 \end{tabular} |
|
509 \end{isabelle} |
|
510 |
|
511 \noindent |
|
512 with types being either type variables or type constructors and terms |
|
513 being variables, constants, applications or abstractions. |
|
514 We often write just @{text \<kappa>} for @{text "() \<kappa>"}, and use @{text "\<alpha>s"} and |
|
515 @{text "\<sigma>s"} to stand for collections of type variables and types, |
|
516 respectively. The type of a term is often made explicit by writing @{text |
|
517 "t :: \<sigma>"}. HOL includes a type @{typ bool} for booleans and the function |
|
518 type, written @{text "\<sigma> \<Rightarrow> \<tau>"}. HOL also contains many primitive and defined |
|
519 constants; for example, a primitive constant is equality, with type @{text "= :: \<sigma> \<Rightarrow> \<sigma> \<Rightarrow> |
|
520 bool"}, and the identity function with type @{text "id :: \<sigma> \<Rightarrow> \<sigma>"} is |
|
521 defined as @{text "\<lambda>x\<^sup>\<sigma>. x\<^sup>\<sigma>"}. |
|
522 |
|
523 An important point to note is that theorems in HOL can be seen as a subset |
|
524 of terms that are constructed specially (namely through axioms and proof |
|
525 rules). As a result we are able to define automatic proof |
|
526 procedures showing that one theorem implies another by decomposing the term |
|
527 underlying the first theorem. |
|
528 |
|
529 Like Homeier's, our work relies on map-functions defined for every type |
|
530 constructor taking some arguments, for example @{text map_list} for lists. Homeier |
|
531 describes in \cite{Homeier05} map-functions for products, sums, options and |
|
532 also the following map for function types |
|
533 |
|
534 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
535 @{thm map_fun_def[THEN eq_reflection]} |
|
536 \end{isabelle} |
|
537 |
|
538 \noindent |
|
539 Using this map-function, we can give the following, equivalent, but more |
|
540 uniform definition for @{text add} shown in \eqref{adddef}: |
|
541 |
|
542 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
543 @{text "add \<equiv> (Rep_int \<singlearr> Rep_int \<singlearr> Abs_int) add_pair"} |
|
544 \end{isabelle} |
|
545 |
|
546 \noindent |
|
547 Using extensionality and unfolding the definition of @{text "\<singlearr>"}, |
|
548 we can get back to \eqref{adddef}. |
|
549 In what follows we shall use the convention to write @{text "map_\<kappa>"} for a map-function |
|
550 of the type-constructor @{text \<kappa>}. |
|
551 %% a general type for map all types is difficult to give (algebraic types are |
|
552 %% easy, but for example the function type is not algebraic |
|
553 %For a type @{text \<kappa>} with arguments @{text "\<alpha>\<^isub>1\<^isub>\<dots>\<^isub>n"} the |
|
554 %type of the function @{text "map_\<kappa>"} has to be @{text "\<alpha>\<^isub>1\<Rightarrow>\<dots>\<Rightarrow>\<alpha>\<^isub>n\<Rightarrow>\<alpha>\<^isub>1\<dots>\<alpha>\<^isub>n \<kappa>"}. |
|
555 %For example @{text "map_list"} |
|
556 %has to have the type @{text "\<alpha>\<Rightarrow>\<alpha> list"}. |
|
557 In our implementation we maintain |
|
558 a database of these map-functions that can be dynamically extended. |
|
559 |
|
560 It will also be necessary to have operators, referred to as @{text "rel_\<kappa>"}, |
|
561 which define equivalence relations in terms of constituent equivalence |
|
562 relations. For example given two equivalence relations @{text "R\<^isub>1"} |
|
563 and @{text "R\<^isub>2"}, we can define an equivalence relations over |
|
564 products as %% follows |
|
565 |
|
566 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
567 @{text "(R\<^isub>1 \<tripple> R\<^isub>2) (x\<^isub>1, x\<^isub>2) (y\<^isub>1, y\<^isub>2) \<equiv> R\<^isub>1 x\<^isub>1 y\<^isub>1 \<and> R\<^isub>2 x\<^isub>2 y\<^isub>2"} |
|
568 \end{isabelle} |
|
569 |
|
570 \noindent |
|
571 Homeier gives also the following operator for defining equivalence |
|
572 relations over function types |
|
573 % |
|
574 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
575 @{thm fun_rel_def[of "R\<^isub>1" "R\<^isub>2", THEN eq_reflection]} |
|
576 \hfill\numbered{relfun} |
|
577 \end{isabelle} |
|
578 |
|
579 \noindent |
|
580 In the context of quotients, the following two notions from \cite{Homeier05} |
|
581 are needed later on. |
|
582 |
|
583 \begin{definition}[Respects]\label{def:respects} |
|
584 An element @{text "x"} respects a relation @{text "R"} provided @{text "R x x"}. |
|
585 \end{definition} |
|
586 |
|
587 \begin{definition}[Bounded $\forall$ and $\lambda$]\label{def:babs} |
|
588 @{text "\<forall>x \<in> S. P x"} holds if for all @{text x}, @{text "x \<in> S"} implies @{text "P x"}; |
|
589 and @{text "(\<lambda>x \<in> S. f x) x = f x"} provided @{text "x \<in> S"}. |
|
590 \end{definition} |
|
591 |
|
592 The central definition in Homeier's work \cite{Homeier05} relates equivalence |
|
593 relations, abstraction and representation functions: |
|
594 |
|
595 \begin{definition}[Quotient Types] |
|
596 Given a relation $R$, an abstraction function $Abs$ |
|
597 and a representation function $Rep$, the predicate @{term "Quotient R Abs Rep"} |
|
598 holds if and only if |
|
599 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%%% |
|
600 \begin{tabular}{rl} |
|
601 (i) & \begin{isa}@{thm (rhs1) Quotient_def[of "R"]}\end{isa}\\ |
|
602 (ii) & \begin{isa}@{thm (rhs2) Quotient_def[of "R"]}\end{isa}\\ |
|
603 (iii) & \begin{isa}@{thm (rhs3) Quotient_def[of "R"]}\end{isa}\\ |
|
604 \end{tabular} |
|
605 \end{isabelle} |
|
606 \end{definition} |
|
607 |
|
608 \noindent |
|
609 The value of this definition lies in the fact that validity of @{term "Quotient R Abs Rep"} can |
|
610 often be proved in terms of the validity of @{term "Quot"} over the constituent |
|
611 types of @{text "R"}, @{text Abs} and @{text Rep}. |
|
612 For example Homeier proves the following property for higher-order quotient |
|
613 types: |
|
614 |
|
615 \begin{proposition}\label{funquot} |
|
616 \begin{isa} |
|
617 @{thm[mode=IfThen] fun_quotient[where ?R1.0="R\<^isub>1" and ?R2.0="R\<^isub>2" |
|
618 and ?abs1.0="Abs\<^isub>1" and ?abs2.0="Abs\<^isub>2" and ?rep1.0="Rep\<^isub>1" and ?rep2.0="Rep\<^isub>2"]} |
|
619 \end{isa} |
|
620 \end{proposition} |
|
621 |
|
622 \noindent |
|
623 As a result, Homeier is able to build an automatic prover that can nearly |
|
624 always discharge a proof obligation involving @{text "Quot"}. Our quotient |
|
625 package makes heavy |
|
626 use of this part of Homeier's work including an extension |
|
627 for dealing with \emph{conjugations} of equivalence relations\footnote{That are |
|
628 symmetric by definition.} defined as follows: |
|
629 |
|
630 %%% FIXME Referee 2 claims that composition-of-relations means OO, and this is also |
|
631 %%% what wikipedia says. Any idea for a different name? Conjugation of Relations? |
|
632 |
|
633 \begin{definition}%%[Composition of Relations] |
|
634 @{abbrev "rel_conj R\<^isub>1 R\<^isub>2"} where @{text "\<circ>\<circ>"} is the predicate |
|
635 composition defined by |
|
636 @{thm (concl) pred_compI[of "R\<^isub>1" "x" "y" "R\<^isub>2" "z"]} |
|
637 holds if and only if there exists a @{text y} such that @{thm (prem 1) pred_compI[of "R\<^isub>1" "x" "y" "R\<^isub>2" "z"]} and |
|
638 @{thm (prem 2) pred_compI[of "R\<^isub>1" "x" "y" "R\<^isub>2" "z"]}. |
|
639 \end{definition} |
|
640 |
|
641 \noindent |
|
642 Unfortunately a general quotient theorem for @{text "\<circ>\<circ>\<circ>"}, analogous to the one |
|
643 for @{text "\<singlearr>"} given in Proposition \ref{funquot}, would not be true |
|
644 in general. It cannot even be stated inside HOL, because of restrictions on types. |
|
645 However, we can prove specific instances of a |
|
646 quotient theorem for composing particular quotient relations. |
|
647 For example, to lift theorems involving @{term flat} the quotient theorem for |
|
648 composing @{text "\<approx>\<^bsub>list\<^esub>"} will be necessary: given @{term "Quotient R Abs Rep"} |
|
649 with @{text R} being an equivalence relation, then |
|
650 |
|
651 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
652 \begin{tabular}{r@ {\hspace{1mm}}l} |
|
653 @{text "Quot"} & @{text "(rel_list R \<circ>\<circ>\<circ> \<approx>\<^bsub>list\<^esub>)"}\\ |
|
654 & @{text "(Abs_fset \<circ> map_list Abs)"} @{text "(map_list Rep \<circ> Rep_fset)"}\\ |
|
655 \end{tabular} |
|
656 \end{isabelle} |
|
657 *} |
|
658 |
|
659 section {* Quotient Types and Quotient Definitions\label{sec:type} *} |
|
660 |
|
661 text {* |
|
662 \noindent |
|
663 The first step in a quotient construction is to take a name for the new |
|
664 type, say @{text "\<kappa>\<^isub>q"}, and an equivalence relation, say @{text R}, |
|
665 defined over a raw type, say @{text "\<sigma>"}. The type of the equivalence |
|
666 relation must be @{text "\<sigma> \<Rightarrow> \<sigma> \<Rightarrow> bool"}. The user-visible part of |
|
667 the quotient type declaration is therefore |
|
668 |
|
669 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
670 \isacommand{quotient\_type}~~@{text "\<alpha>s \<kappa>\<^isub>q = \<sigma> / R"}\hfill\numbered{typedecl} |
|
671 \end{isabelle} |
|
672 |
|
673 \noindent |
|
674 and a proof that @{text "R"} is indeed an equivalence relation. The @{text "\<alpha>s"} |
|
675 indicate the arity of the new type and the type-variables of @{text "\<sigma>"} can only |
|
676 be contained in @{text "\<alpha>s"}. Two concrete |
|
677 examples are |
|
678 |
|
679 |
|
680 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
681 \begin{tabular}{@ {}l} |
|
682 \isacommand{quotient\_type}~~@{text "int = nat \<times> nat / \<approx>\<^bsub>nat \<times> nat\<^esub>"}\\ |
|
683 \isacommand{quotient\_type}~~@{text "\<alpha> fset = \<alpha> list / \<approx>\<^bsub>list\<^esub>"} |
|
684 \end{tabular} |
|
685 \end{isabelle} |
|
686 |
|
687 \noindent |
|
688 which introduce the type of integers and of finite sets using the |
|
689 equivalence relations @{text "\<approx>\<^bsub>nat \<times> nat\<^esub>"} and @{text |
|
690 "\<approx>\<^bsub>list\<^esub>"} defined in \eqref{natpairequiv} and |
|
691 \eqref{listequiv}, respectively (the proofs about being equivalence |
|
692 relations are omitted). Given this data, we define for declarations shown in |
|
693 \eqref{typedecl} the quotient types internally as |
|
694 |
|
695 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
696 \isacommand{typedef}~~@{text "\<alpha>s \<kappa>\<^isub>q = {c. \<exists>x. c = R x}"} |
|
697 \end{isabelle} |
|
698 |
|
699 \noindent |
|
700 where the right-hand side is the (non-empty) set of equivalence classes of |
|
701 @{text "R"}. The constraint in this declaration is that the type variables |
|
702 in the raw type @{text "\<sigma>"} must be included in the type variables @{text |
|
703 "\<alpha>s"} declared for @{text "\<kappa>\<^isub>q"}. HOL will then provide us with the following |
|
704 abstraction and representation functions |
|
705 |
|
706 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
707 @{text "abs_\<kappa>\<^isub>q :: \<sigma> set \<Rightarrow> \<alpha>s \<kappa>\<^isub>q"}\hspace{10mm}@{text "rep_\<kappa>\<^isub>q :: \<alpha>s \<kappa>\<^isub>q \<Rightarrow> \<sigma> set"} |
|
708 \end{isabelle} |
|
709 |
|
710 \noindent |
|
711 As can be seen from the type, they relate the new quotient type and equivalence classes of the raw |
|
712 type. However, as Homeier \cite{Homeier05} noted, it is much more convenient |
|
713 to work with the following derived abstraction and representation functions |
|
714 |
|
715 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
716 @{text "Abs_\<kappa>\<^isub>q x \<equiv> abs_\<kappa>\<^isub>q (R x)"}\hspace{10mm}@{text "Rep_\<kappa>\<^isub>q x \<equiv> \<epsilon> (rep_\<kappa>\<^isub>q x)"} |
|
717 \end{isabelle} |
|
718 |
|
719 \noindent |
|
720 on the expense of having to use Hilbert's choice operator @{text "\<epsilon>"} in the |
|
721 definition of @{text "Rep_\<kappa>\<^isub>q"}. These derived notions relate the |
|
722 quotient type and the raw type directly, as can be seen from their type, |
|
723 namely @{text "\<sigma> \<Rightarrow> \<alpha>s \<kappa>\<^isub>q"} and @{text "\<alpha>s \<kappa>\<^isub>q \<Rightarrow> \<sigma>"}, |
|
724 respectively. Given that @{text "R"} is an equivalence relation, the |
|
725 following property holds for every quotient type |
|
726 (for the proof see \cite{Homeier05}). |
|
727 |
|
728 \begin{proposition} |
|
729 \begin{isa}@{term "Quotient R Abs_\<kappa>\<^isub>q Rep_\<kappa>\<^isub>q"}.\end{isa} |
|
730 \end{proposition} |
|
731 |
|
732 The next step in a quotient construction is to introduce definitions of new constants |
|
733 involving the quotient type. These definitions need to be given in terms of concepts |
|
734 of the raw type (remember this is the only way how to extend HOL |
|
735 with new definitions). For the user the visible part of such definitions is the declaration |
|
736 |
|
737 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
738 \isacommand{quotient\_definition}~~@{text "c :: \<tau>"}~~\isacommand{is}~~@{text "t :: \<sigma>"} |
|
739 \end{isabelle} |
|
740 |
|
741 \noindent |
|
742 where @{text t} is the definiens (its type @{text \<sigma>} can always be inferred) |
|
743 and @{text "c"} is the name of definiendum, whose type @{text "\<tau>"} needs to be |
|
744 given explicitly (the point is that @{text "\<tau>"} and @{text "\<sigma>"} can only differ |
|
745 in places where a quotient and raw type is involved). Two concrete examples are |
|
746 |
|
747 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
748 \begin{tabular}{@ {}l} |
|
749 \isacommand{quotient\_definition}~~@{text "0 :: int"}~~\isacommand{is}~~@{text "(0::nat, 0::nat)"}\\ |
|
750 \isacommand{quotient\_definition}~~@{text "\<Union> :: (\<alpha> fset) fset \<Rightarrow> \<alpha> fset"}~~% |
|
751 \isacommand{is}~~@{text "flat"} |
|
752 \end{tabular} |
|
753 \end{isabelle} |
|
754 |
|
755 \noindent |
|
756 The first one declares zero for integers and the second the operator for |
|
757 building unions of finite sets (@{text "flat"} having the type |
|
758 @{text "(\<alpha> list) list \<Rightarrow> \<alpha> list"}). |
|
759 |
|
760 From such declarations given by the user, the quotient package needs to derive proper |
|
761 definitions using @{text "Abs"} and @{text "Rep"}. The data we rely on is the given quotient type |
|
762 @{text "\<tau>"} and the raw type @{text "\<sigma>"}. They allow us to define \emph{aggregate |
|
763 abstraction} and \emph{representation functions} using the functions @{text "ABS (\<sigma>, |
|
764 \<tau>)"} and @{text "REP (\<sigma>, \<tau>)"} whose clauses we shall give below. The idea behind |
|
765 these two functions is to simultaneously descend into the raw types @{text \<sigma>} and |
|
766 quotient types @{text \<tau>}, and generate the appropriate |
|
767 @{text "Abs"} and @{text "Rep"} in places where the types differ. Therefore |
|
768 we generate just the identity whenever the types are equal. On the ``way'' down, |
|
769 however we might have to use map-functions to let @{text Abs} and @{text Rep} act |
|
770 over the appropriate types. In what follows we use the short-hand notation |
|
771 @{text "ABS (\<sigma>s, \<tau>s)"} to mean @{text "ABS (\<sigma>\<^isub>1, \<tau>\<^isub>1)\<dots>ABS (\<sigma>\<^isub>n, \<tau>\<^isub>n)"}; similarly |
|
772 for @{text REP}. |
|
773 % |
|
774 \begin{center} |
|
775 \hfill |
|
776 \begin{tabular}{@ {\hspace{2mm}}l@ {}} |
|
777 \multicolumn{1}{@ {}l}{equal types:}\\ |
|
778 @{text "ABS (\<sigma>, \<sigma>)"} $\dn$ @{text "id :: \<sigma> \<Rightarrow> \<sigma>"}\hspace{5mm}%\\ |
|
779 @{text "REP (\<sigma>, \<sigma>)"} $\dn$ @{text "id :: \<sigma> \<Rightarrow> \<sigma>"}\smallskip\\ |
|
780 \multicolumn{1}{@ {}l}{function types:}\\ |
|
781 @{text "ABS (\<sigma>\<^isub>1 \<Rightarrow> \<sigma>\<^isub>2, \<tau>\<^isub>1 \<Rightarrow> \<tau>\<^isub>2)"} $\dn$ @{text "REP (\<sigma>\<^isub>1, \<tau>\<^isub>1) \<singlearr> ABS (\<sigma>\<^isub>2, \<tau>\<^isub>2)"}\\ |
|
782 @{text "REP (\<sigma>\<^isub>1 \<Rightarrow> \<sigma>\<^isub>2, \<tau>\<^isub>1 \<Rightarrow> \<tau>\<^isub>2)"} $\dn$ @{text "ABS (\<sigma>\<^isub>1, \<tau>\<^isub>1) \<singlearr> REP (\<sigma>\<^isub>2, \<tau>\<^isub>2)"}\smallskip\\ |
|
783 \multicolumn{1}{@ {}l}{equal type constructors:}\\ |
|
784 @{text "ABS (\<sigma>s \<kappa>, \<tau>s \<kappa>)"} $\dn$ @{text "map_\<kappa> (ABS (\<sigma>s, \<tau>s))"}\\ |
|
785 @{text "REP (\<sigma>s \<kappa>, \<tau>s \<kappa>)"} $\dn$ @{text "map_\<kappa> (REP (\<sigma>s, \<tau>s))"}\smallskip\\ |
|
786 \multicolumn{1}{@ {}l}{unequal type constructors:}\\ |
|
787 @{text "ABS (\<sigma>s \<kappa>, \<tau>s \<kappa>\<^isub>q)"} $\dn$ @{text "Abs_\<kappa>\<^isub>q \<circ> (MAP(\<rho>s \<kappa>) (ABS (\<sigma>s', \<tau>s)))"}\\ |
|
788 @{text "REP (\<sigma>s \<kappa>, \<tau>s \<kappa>\<^isub>q)"} $\dn$ @{text "(MAP(\<rho>s \<kappa>) (REP (\<sigma>s', \<tau>s))) \<circ> Rep_\<kappa>\<^isub>q"} |
|
789 \end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{ABSREP} |
|
790 \end{center} |
|
791 % |
|
792 \noindent |
|
793 In the last two clauses are subtle. We rely in them on the fact that the type @{text "\<alpha>s |
|
794 \<kappa>\<^isub>q"} is the quotient of the raw type @{text "\<rho>s \<kappa>"} (for example |
|
795 @{text "int"} and @{text "nat \<times> nat"}, or @{text "\<alpha> fset"} and @{text "\<alpha> |
|
796 list"}). This data is given by declarations shown in \eqref{typedecl}. |
|
797 The quotient construction ensures that the type variables in @{text |
|
798 "\<rho>s \<kappa>"} must be among the @{text "\<alpha>s"}. The @{text "\<sigma>s'"} are given by the |
|
799 substitutions for the @{text "\<alpha>s"} when matching @{text "\<sigma>s \<kappa>"} against |
|
800 @{text "\<rho>s \<kappa>"}. This calculation determines what are the types in place |
|
801 of the type variables @{text "\<alpha>s"} in the instance of |
|
802 quotient type @{text "\<alpha>s \<kappa>\<^isub>q"}---namely @{text "\<tau>s"}, and the corresponding |
|
803 types in place of the @{text "\<alpha>s"} in the raw type @{text "\<rho>s \<kappa>"}---namely @{text "\<sigma>s'"}. The |
|
804 function @{text "MAP"} calculates an \emph{aggregate map-function} for a raw |
|
805 type as follows: |
|
806 % |
|
807 \begin{center} |
|
808 \begin{tabular}{r@ {\hspace{1mm}}c@ {\hspace{1mm}}l} |
|
809 @{text "MAP' (\<alpha>)"} & $\dn$ & @{text "a\<^sup>\<alpha>"}\\ |
|
810 @{text "MAP' (\<kappa>)"} & $\dn$ & @{text "id :: \<kappa> \<Rightarrow> \<kappa>"}\\ |
|
811 @{text "MAP' (\<sigma>s \<kappa>)"} & $\dn$ & @{text "map_\<kappa> (MAP'(\<sigma>s))"}\smallskip\\ |
|
812 @{text "MAP (\<sigma>)"} & $\dn$ & @{text "\<lambda>as. MAP'(\<sigma>)"} |
|
813 \end{tabular} |
|
814 \end{center} |
|
815 % |
|
816 \noindent |
|
817 In this definition we rely on the fact that in the first clause we can interpret type-variables @{text \<alpha>} as |
|
818 term variables @{text a}. In the last clause we build an abstraction over all |
|
819 term-variables of the map-function generated by the auxiliary function |
|
820 @{text "MAP'"}. |
|
821 The need for aggregate map-functions can be seen in cases where we build quotients, |
|
822 say @{text "(\<alpha>, \<beta>) \<kappa>\<^isub>q"}, out of compound raw types, say @{text "(\<alpha> list) \<times> \<beta>"}. |
|
823 In this case @{text MAP} generates the |
|
824 aggregate map-function: |
|
825 |
|
826 %%% FIXME: Reviewer 2 asks: last two lines defining ABS and REP for |
|
827 %%% unequal type constructors: How are the $\varrho$s defined? The |
|
828 %%% following paragraph mentions them, but this paragraph is unclear, |
|
829 %%% since it then mentions $\alpha$s, which do not seem to be defined |
|
830 %%% either. As a result, I do not understand the first two sentences |
|
831 %%% in this paragraph. I can imagine roughly what the following |
|
832 %%% sentence `The $\sigma$s' are given by the matchers for the |
|
833 %%% $\alpha$s$ when matching $\varrho$s $\kappa$ against $\sigma$s |
|
834 %%% $\kappa$.' means, but also think that it is too vague. |
|
835 |
|
836 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
837 @{text "\<lambda>a b. map_prod (map_list a) b"} |
|
838 \end{isabelle} |
|
839 |
|
840 \noindent |
|
841 which is essential in order to define the corresponding aggregate |
|
842 abstraction and representation functions. |
|
843 |
|
844 To see how these definitions pan out in practise, let us return to our |
|
845 example about @{term "concat"} and @{term "fconcat"}, where we have the raw type |
|
846 @{text "(\<alpha> list) list \<Rightarrow> \<alpha> list"} and the quotient type @{text "(\<alpha> fset) fset \<Rightarrow> \<alpha> |
|
847 fset"}. Feeding these types into @{text ABS} gives us (after some @{text "\<beta>"}-simplifications) |
|
848 the abstraction function |
|
849 |
|
850 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ %%% |
|
851 \begin{tabular}{l} |
|
852 @{text "(map_list (map_list id \<circ> Rep_fset) \<circ> Rep_fset) \<singlearr>"}\\ |
|
853 \mbox{}\hspace{4.5cm}@{text " Abs_fset \<circ> map_list id"} |
|
854 \end{tabular} |
|
855 \end{isabelle} |
|
856 |
|
857 \noindent |
|
858 In our implementation we further |
|
859 simplify this function by rewriting with the usual laws about @{text |
|
860 "map"}s and @{text "id"}, for example @{term "map_list id = id"} and @{text "f \<circ> id = |
|
861 id \<circ> f = f"}. This gives us the simpler abstraction function |
|
862 |
|
863 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
864 @{text "(map_list Rep_fset \<circ> Rep_fset) \<singlearr> Abs_fset"} |
|
865 \end{isabelle} |
|
866 |
|
867 \noindent |
|
868 which we can use for defining @{term "fconcat"} as follows |
|
869 |
|
870 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
871 @{text "\<Union> \<equiv> ((map_list Rep_fset \<circ> Rep_fset) \<singlearr> Abs_fset) flat"} |
|
872 \end{isabelle} |
|
873 |
|
874 \noindent |
|
875 Note that by using the operator @{text "\<singlearr>"} and special clauses |
|
876 for function types in \eqref{ABSREP}, we do not have to |
|
877 distinguish between arguments and results, but can deal with them uniformly. |
|
878 Consequently, all definitions in the quotient package |
|
879 are of the general form |
|
880 |
|
881 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
882 \mbox{@{text "c \<equiv> ABS (\<sigma>, \<tau>) t"}} |
|
883 \end{isabelle} |
|
884 |
|
885 \noindent |
|
886 where @{text \<sigma>} is the type of the definiens @{text "t"} and @{text "\<tau>"} the |
|
887 type of the defined quotient constant @{text "c"}. This data can be easily |
|
888 generated from the declaration given by the user. |
|
889 To increase the confidence in this way of making definitions, we can prove |
|
890 that the terms involved are all typable. |
|
891 |
|
892 \begin{lemma} |
|
893 If @{text "ABS (\<sigma>, \<tau>)"} returns some abstraction function @{text "Abs"} |
|
894 and @{text "REP (\<sigma>, \<tau>)"} some representation function @{text "Rep"}, |
|
895 then @{text "Abs"} is of type @{text "\<sigma> \<Rightarrow> \<tau>"} and @{text "Rep"} of type |
|
896 @{text "\<tau> \<Rightarrow> \<sigma>"}. |
|
897 \end{lemma} |
|
898 |
|
899 \begin{proof} |
|
900 By mutual induction and analysing the definitions of @{text "ABS"} and @{text "REP"}. |
|
901 The cases of equal types and function types are |
|
902 straightforward (the latter follows from @{text "\<singlearr>"} having the |
|
903 type @{text "(\<alpha> \<Rightarrow> \<beta>) \<Rightarrow> (\<gamma> \<Rightarrow> \<delta>) \<Rightarrow> (\<beta> \<Rightarrow> \<gamma>) \<Rightarrow> (\<alpha> \<Rightarrow> \<delta>)"}). In case of equal type |
|
904 constructors we can observe that a map-function after applying the functions |
|
905 @{text "ABS (\<sigma>s, \<tau>s)"} produces a term of type @{text "\<sigma>s \<kappa> \<Rightarrow> \<tau>s \<kappa>"}. The |
|
906 interesting case is the one with unequal type constructors. Since we know |
|
907 the quotient is between @{text "\<alpha>s \<kappa>\<^isub>q"} and @{text "\<rho>s \<kappa>"}, we have |
|
908 that @{text "Abs_\<kappa>\<^isub>q"} is of type @{text "\<rho>s \<kappa> \<Rightarrow> \<alpha>s |
|
909 \<kappa>\<^isub>q"}. This type can be more specialised to @{text "\<rho>s[\<tau>s] \<kappa> \<Rightarrow> \<tau>s |
|
910 \<kappa>\<^isub>q"} where the type variables @{text "\<alpha>s"} are instantiated with the |
|
911 @{text "\<tau>s"}. The complete type can be calculated by observing that @{text |
|
912 "MAP (\<rho>s \<kappa>)"}, after applying the functions @{text "ABS (\<sigma>s', \<tau>s)"} to it, |
|
913 returns a term of type @{text "\<rho>s[\<sigma>s'] \<kappa> \<Rightarrow> \<rho>s[\<tau>s] \<kappa>"}. This type is |
|
914 equivalent to @{text "\<sigma>s \<kappa> \<Rightarrow> \<rho>s[\<tau>s] \<kappa>"}, which we just have to compose with |
|
915 @{text "\<rho>s[\<tau>s] \<kappa> \<Rightarrow> \<tau>s \<kappa>\<^isub>q"} according to the type of @{text "\<circ>"}.\qed |
|
916 \end{proof} |
|
917 *} |
|
918 |
|
919 section {* Respectfulness and Preservation \label{sec:resp} *} |
|
920 |
|
921 text {* |
|
922 \noindent |
|
923 The main point of the quotient package is to automatically ``lift'' theorems |
|
924 involving constants over the raw type to theorems involving constants over |
|
925 the quotient type. Before we can describe this lifting process, we need to impose |
|
926 two restrictions in form of proof obligations that arise during the |
|
927 lifting. The reason is that even if definitions for all raw constants |
|
928 can be given, \emph{not} all theorems can be lifted to the quotient type. Most |
|
929 notable is the bound variable function, that is the constant @{text bn}, |
|
930 defined |
|
931 for raw lambda-terms as follows |
|
932 |
|
933 \begin{isabelle} |
|
934 \begin{center} |
|
935 @{text "bn (x) \<equiv> \<emptyset>"}\hspace{4mm} |
|
936 @{text "bn (t\<^isub>1 t\<^isub>2) \<equiv> bn (t\<^isub>1) \<union> bn (t\<^isub>2)"}\smallskip\\ |
|
937 @{text "bn (\<lambda>x. t) \<equiv> {x} \<union> bn (t)"} |
|
938 \end{center} |
|
939 \end{isabelle} |
|
940 |
|
941 \noindent |
|
942 We can generate a definition for this constant using @{text ABS} and @{text REP}. |
|
943 But this constant does \emph{not} respect @{text "\<alpha>"}-equivalence and |
|
944 consequently no theorem involving this constant can be lifted to @{text |
|
945 "\<alpha>"}-equated lambda terms. Homeier formulates the restrictions in terms of |
|
946 the properties of \emph{respectfulness} and \emph{preservation}. We have |
|
947 to slightly extend Homeier's definitions in order to deal with quotient |
|
948 compositions. |
|
949 |
|
950 %%% FIXME: Reviewer 3 asks why are the definitions that follow enough to deal |
|
951 %%% with quotient composition. |
|
952 |
|
953 To formally define what respectfulness is, we have to first define |
|
954 the notion of \emph{aggregate equivalence relations} using the function @{text "REL(\<sigma>, \<tau>)"} |
|
955 The idea behind this function is to simultaneously descend into the raw types |
|
956 @{text \<sigma>} and quotient types @{text \<tau>}, and generate the appropriate |
|
957 quotient equivalence relations in places where the types differ and equalities |
|
958 elsewhere. |
|
959 |
|
960 \begin{center} |
|
961 \hfill |
|
962 \begin{tabular}{l} |
|
963 \multicolumn{1}{@ {}l}{equal types:} |
|
964 @{text "REL (\<sigma>, \<sigma>)"} $\dn$ @{text "= :: \<sigma> \<Rightarrow> \<sigma> \<Rightarrow> bool"}\smallskip\\ |
|
965 \multicolumn{1}{@ {}l}{equal type constructors:}\\ |
|
966 @{text "REL (\<sigma>s \<kappa>, \<tau>s \<kappa>)"} $\dn$ @{text "rel_\<kappa> (REL (\<sigma>s, \<tau>s))"}\smallskip\\ |
|
967 \multicolumn{1}{@ {}l}{unequal type constructors:}\\ |
|
968 @{text "REL (\<sigma>s \<kappa>, \<tau>s \<kappa>\<^isub>q)"} $\dn$ @{text "rel_\<kappa>\<^isub>q (REL (\<sigma>s', \<tau>s))"}\\ |
|
969 \end{tabular}\hfill\numbered{REL} |
|
970 \end{center} |
|
971 |
|
972 \noindent |
|
973 The @{text "\<sigma>s'"} in the last clause are calculated as in \eqref{ABSREP}: |
|
974 again we know that type @{text "\<alpha>s \<kappa>\<^isub>q"} is the quotient of the raw type |
|
975 @{text "\<rho>s \<kappa>"}. The @{text "\<sigma>s'"} are the substitutions for @{text "\<alpha>s"} obtained by matching |
|
976 @{text "\<rho>s \<kappa>"} and @{text "\<sigma>s \<kappa>"}. |
|
977 |
|
978 Let us return to the lifting procedure of theorems. Assume we have a theorem |
|
979 that contains the raw constant @{text "c\<^isub>r :: \<sigma>"} and which we want to |
|
980 lift to a theorem where @{text "c\<^isub>r"} is replaced by the corresponding |
|
981 constant @{text "c\<^isub>q :: \<tau>"} defined over a quotient type. In this situation |
|
982 we generate the following proof obligation |
|
983 |
|
984 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
985 @{text "REL (\<sigma>, \<tau>) c\<^isub>r c\<^isub>r"}. |
|
986 \end{isabelle} |
|
987 |
|
988 \noindent |
|
989 Homeier calls these proof obligations \emph{respectfulness |
|
990 theorems}. However, unlike his quotient package, we might have several |
|
991 respectfulness theorems for one constant---he has at most one. |
|
992 The reason is that because of our quotient compositions, the types |
|
993 @{text \<sigma>} and @{text \<tau>} are not completely determined by @{text "c\<^bsub>r\<^esub>"}. |
|
994 And for every instantiation of the types, a corresponding |
|
995 respectfulness theorem is necessary. |
|
996 |
|
997 Before lifting a theorem, we require the user to discharge |
|
998 respectfulness proof obligations. In case of @{text bn} |
|
999 this obligation is %%as follows |
|
1000 |
|
1001 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
1002 @{text "(\<approx>\<^isub>\<alpha> \<doublearr> =) bn bn"} |
|
1003 \end{isabelle} |
|
1004 |
|
1005 \noindent |
|
1006 and the point is that the user cannot discharge it: because it is not true. To see this, |
|
1007 we can just unfold the definition of @{text "\<doublearr>"} \eqref{relfun} |
|
1008 using extensionality to obtain the false statement |
|
1009 |
|
1010 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
1011 @{text "\<forall>t\<^isub>1 t\<^isub>2. if t\<^isub>1 \<approx>\<^isub>\<alpha> t\<^isub>2 then bn(t\<^isub>1) = bn(t\<^isub>2)"} |
|
1012 \end{isabelle} |
|
1013 |
|
1014 \noindent |
|
1015 In contrast, lifting a theorem about @{text "append"} to a theorem describing |
|
1016 the union of finite sets will mean to discharge the proof obligation |
|
1017 |
|
1018 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
1019 @{text "(\<approx>\<^bsub>list\<^esub> \<doublearr> \<approx>\<^bsub>list\<^esub> \<doublearr> \<approx>\<^bsub>list\<^esub>) append append"} |
|
1020 \end{isabelle} |
|
1021 |
|
1022 \noindent |
|
1023 To do so, we have to establish |
|
1024 |
|
1025 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
1026 if @{text "xs \<approx>\<^bsub>list\<^esub> ys"} and @{text "us \<approx>\<^bsub>list\<^esub> vs"} |
|
1027 then @{text "xs @ us \<approx>\<^bsub>list\<^esub> ys @ vs"} |
|
1028 \end{isabelle} |
|
1029 |
|
1030 \noindent |
|
1031 which is straightforward given the definition shown in \eqref{listequiv}. |
|
1032 |
|
1033 The second restriction we have to impose arises from non-lifted polymorphic |
|
1034 constants, which are instantiated to a type being quotient. For example, |
|
1035 take the @{term "cons"}-constructor to add a pair of natural numbers to a |
|
1036 list, whereby we assume the pair of natural numbers turns into an integer in |
|
1037 the quotient construction. The point is that we still want to use @{text |
|
1038 cons} for adding integers to lists---just with a different type. To be able |
|
1039 to lift such theorems, we need a \emph{preservation property} for @{text |
|
1040 cons}. Assuming we have a polymorphic raw constant @{text "c\<^isub>r :: \<sigma>"} |
|
1041 and a corresponding quotient constant @{text "c\<^isub>q :: \<tau>"}, then a |
|
1042 preservation property is as follows |
|
1043 |
|
1044 %%% FIXME: Reviewer 2 asks: You say what a preservation theorem is, |
|
1045 %%% but not which preservation theorems you assume. Do you generate a |
|
1046 %%% proof obligation for a preservation theorem for each raw constant |
|
1047 %%% and its corresponding lifted constant? |
|
1048 |
|
1049 %%% Cezary: I think this would be a nice thing to do but we have not |
|
1050 %%% done it, the theorems need to be 'guessed' from the remaining obligations |
|
1051 |
|
1052 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
1053 @{text "Quot R\<^bsub>\<alpha>s\<^esub> Abs\<^bsub>\<alpha>s\<^esub> Rep\<^bsub>\<alpha>s\<^esub> implies ABS (\<sigma>, \<tau>) c\<^isub>r = c\<^isub>r"} |
|
1054 \end{isabelle} |
|
1055 |
|
1056 \noindent |
|
1057 where the @{text "\<alpha>s"} stand for the type variables in the type of @{text "c\<^isub>r"}. |
|
1058 In case of @{text cons} (which has type @{text "\<alpha> \<Rightarrow> \<alpha> list \<Rightarrow> \<alpha> list"}) we have |
|
1059 |
|
1060 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
1061 @{text "(Rep \<singlearr> map_list Rep \<singlearr> map_list Abs) cons = cons"} |
|
1062 \end{isabelle} |
|
1063 |
|
1064 \noindent |
|
1065 under the assumption @{term "Quotient R Abs Rep"}. The point is that if we have |
|
1066 an instance of @{text cons} where the type variable @{text \<alpha>} is instantiated |
|
1067 with @{text "nat \<times> nat"} and we also quotient this type to yield integers, |
|
1068 then we need to show this preservation property. |
|
1069 |
|
1070 %%%@ {thm [display, indent=10] Cons_prs2} |
|
1071 |
|
1072 %Given two quotients, one of which quotients a container, and the |
|
1073 %other quotients the type in the container, we can write the |
|
1074 %composition of those quotients. To compose two quotient theorems |
|
1075 %we compose the relations with relation composition as defined above |
|
1076 %and the abstraction and relation functions are the ones of the sub |
|
1077 %quotients composed with the usual function composition. |
|
1078 %The @ {term "Rep"} and @ {term "Abs"} functions that we obtain agree |
|
1079 %with the definition of aggregate Abs/Rep functions and the |
|
1080 %relation is the same as the one given by aggregate relations. |
|
1081 %This becomes especially interesting |
|
1082 %when we compose the quotient with itself, as there is no simple |
|
1083 %intermediate step. |
|
1084 % |
|
1085 %Lets take again the example of @ {term flat}. To be able to lift |
|
1086 %theorems that talk about it we provide the composition quotient |
|
1087 %theorem which allows quotienting inside the container: |
|
1088 % |
|
1089 %If @ {term R} is an equivalence relation and @ {term "Quotient R Abs Rep"} |
|
1090 %then |
|
1091 % |
|
1092 %@ {text [display, indent=10] "Quotient (list_rel R \<circ>\<circ>\<circ> \<approx>\<^bsub>list\<^esub>) (abs_fset \<circ> map_list Abs) (map_list Rep o rep_fset)"} |
|
1093 %%% |
|
1094 %%%\noindent |
|
1095 %%%this theorem will then instantiate the quotients needed in the |
|
1096 %%%injection and cleaning proofs allowing the lifting procedure to |
|
1097 %%%proceed in an unchanged way. |
|
1098 *} |
|
1099 |
|
1100 section {* Lifting of Theorems\label{sec:lift} *} |
|
1101 |
|
1102 text {* |
|
1103 |
|
1104 %%% FIXME Reviewer 3 asks: Section 5 shows the technicalities of |
|
1105 %%% lifting theorems. But there is no clarification about the |
|
1106 %%% correctness. A reader would also be interested in seeing some |
|
1107 %%% discussions about the generality and limitation of the approach |
|
1108 %%% proposed there |
|
1109 |
|
1110 %%% TODO: This introduction is same as the introduction to the previous section. |
|
1111 |
|
1112 \noindent |
|
1113 The main benefit of a quotient package is to lift automatically theorems over raw |
|
1114 types to theorems over quotient types. We will perform this lifting in |
|
1115 three phases, called \emph{regularization}, |
|
1116 \emph{injection} and \emph{cleaning} according to procedures in Homeier's ML-code. |
|
1117 Space restrictions, unfortunately, prevent us from giving anything but a sketch of these three |
|
1118 phases. However, we will precisely define the input and output data of these phases |
|
1119 (this was omitted in \cite{Homeier05}). |
|
1120 |
|
1121 The purpose of regularization is to change the quantifiers and abstractions |
|
1122 in a ``raw'' theorem to quantifiers over variables that respect their respective relations |
|
1123 (Definition \ref{def:respects} states what respects means). The purpose of injection is to add @{term Rep} |
|
1124 and @{term Abs} of appropriate types in front of constants and variables |
|
1125 of the raw type so that they can be replaced by the corresponding constants from the |
|
1126 quotient type. The purpose of cleaning is to bring the theorem derived in the |
|
1127 first two phases into the form the user has specified. Abstractly, our |
|
1128 package establishes the following three proof steps: |
|
1129 |
|
1130 %%% FIXME: Reviewer 1 complains that the reader needs to guess the |
|
1131 %%% meaning of reg_thm and inj_thm, as well as the arguments of REG |
|
1132 %%% which are given above. I wouldn't change it. |
|
1133 |
|
1134 \begin{center} |
|
1135 \begin{tabular}{l@ {\hspace{4mm}}l} |
|
1136 1.) Regularization & @{text "raw_thm \<longrightarrow> reg_thm"}\\ |
|
1137 2.) Injection & @{text "reg_thm \<longleftrightarrow> inj_thm"}\\ |
|
1138 3.) Cleaning & @{text "inj_thm \<longleftrightarrow> quot_thm"}\\ |
|
1139 \end{tabular} |
|
1140 \end{center} |
|
1141 |
|
1142 \noindent |
|
1143 which means, stringed together, the raw theorem implies the quotient theorem. |
|
1144 The core of the quotient package requires both the @{text "raw_thm"} (as a |
|
1145 theorem) and the \emph{term} of the @{text "quot_thm"}. This lets the user |
|
1146 have a finer control over which parts of a raw theorem should be lifted. |
|
1147 We also provide more automated modes where either the @{text "quot_thm"} |
|
1148 is guessed from the form of @{text "raw_thm"} or the @{text "raw_thm"} is |
|
1149 guessed from the current goal and these are described in Section \ref{sec:descending}. |
|
1150 |
|
1151 The second and third proof step performed in package will always succeed if the appropriate |
|
1152 respectfulness and preservation theorems are given. In contrast, the first |
|
1153 proof step can fail: a theorem given by the user does not always |
|
1154 imply a regularized version and a stronger one needs to be proved. An example |
|
1155 for this kind of failure is the simple statement for integers @{text "0 \<noteq> 1"}. |
|
1156 One might hope that it can be proved by lifting @{text "(0, 0) \<noteq> (1, 0)"}, |
|
1157 but this raw theorem only shows that two particular elements in the |
|
1158 equivalence classes are not equal. In order to obtain @{text "0 \<noteq> 1"}, a |
|
1159 more general statement stipulating that the equivalence classes are not |
|
1160 equal is necessary. This kind of failure is beyond the scope where the |
|
1161 quotient package can help: the user has to provide a raw theorem that |
|
1162 can be regularized automatically, or has to provide an explicit proof |
|
1163 for the first proof step. Homeier gives more details about this issue |
|
1164 in the long version of \cite{Homeier05}. |
|
1165 |
|
1166 In the following we will first define the statement of the |
|
1167 regularized theorem based on @{text "raw_thm"} and |
|
1168 @{text "quot_thm"}. Then we define the statement of the injected theorem, based |
|
1169 on @{text "reg_thm"} and @{text "quot_thm"}. We then show the three proof steps, |
|
1170 which can all be performed independently from each other. |
|
1171 |
|
1172 We first define the function @{text REG}, which takes the terms of the |
|
1173 @{text "raw_thm"} and @{text "quot_thm"} as input and returns |
|
1174 @{text "reg_thm"}. The idea |
|
1175 behind this function is that it replaces quantifiers and |
|
1176 abstractions involving raw types by bounded ones, and equalities |
|
1177 involving raw types by appropriate aggregate |
|
1178 equivalence relations. It is defined by simultaneous recursion on |
|
1179 the structure of the terms of @{text "raw_thm"} and @{text "quot_thm"} as follows: |
|
1180 % |
|
1181 \begin{center} |
|
1182 \begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}} |
|
1183 \multicolumn{1}{@ {}l@ {}}{abstractions:}\\%%\smallskip\\ |
|
1184 @{text "REG (\<lambda>x\<^sup>\<sigma>. t, \<lambda>x\<^sup>\<tau>. s)"} $\dn$ |
|
1185 $\begin{cases} |
|
1186 @{text "\<lambda>x\<^sup>\<sigma>. REG (t, s)"} \quad\mbox{provided @{text "\<sigma> = \<tau>"}}\\ |
|
1187 @{text "\<lambda>x\<^sup>\<sigma> \<in> Resp (REL (\<sigma>, \<tau>)). REG (t, s)"} |
|
1188 \end{cases}$\\%%\smallskip\\ |
|
1189 \multicolumn{1}{@ {}l@ {}}{universal quantifiers:}\\ |
|
1190 @{text "REG (\<forall>x\<^sup>\<sigma>. t, \<forall>x\<^sup>\<tau>. s)"} $\dn$ |
|
1191 $\begin{cases} |
|
1192 @{text "\<forall>x\<^sup>\<sigma>. REG (t, s)"} \quad\mbox{provided @{text "\<sigma> = \<tau>"}}\\ |
|
1193 @{text "\<forall>x\<^sup>\<sigma> \<in> Resp (REL (\<sigma>, \<tau>)). REG (t, s)"} |
|
1194 \end{cases}$\\%%\smallskip\\ |
|
1195 \multicolumn{1}{@ {}l@ {}}{equality: \hspace{3mm}%%}\smallskip\\ |
|
1196 %% REL of two equal types is the equality so we do not need a separate case |
|
1197 @{text "REG (=\<^bsup>\<sigma>\<Rightarrow>\<sigma>\<Rightarrow>bool\<^esup>, =\<^bsup>\<tau>\<Rightarrow>\<tau>\<Rightarrow>bool\<^esup>)"} $\dn$ @{text "REL (\<sigma>, \<tau>)"}}\smallskip\\ |
|
1198 \multicolumn{1}{@ {}l@ {}}{applications, variables and constants:}\\ |
|
1199 @{text "REG (t\<^isub>1 t\<^isub>2, s\<^isub>1 s\<^isub>2)"} $\dn$ @{text "REG (t\<^isub>1, s\<^isub>1) REG (t\<^isub>2, s\<^isub>2)"}\\ |
|
1200 @{text "REG (x\<^isub>1, x\<^isub>2)"} $\dn$ @{text "x\<^isub>1"}\\ |
|
1201 @{text "REG (c\<^isub>1, c\<^isub>2)"} $\dn$ @{text "c\<^isub>1"}\\ |
|
1202 \end{tabular} |
|
1203 \end{center} |
|
1204 % |
|
1205 \noindent |
|
1206 In the above definition we omitted the cases for existential quantifiers |
|
1207 and unique existential quantifiers, as they are very similar to the cases |
|
1208 for the universal quantifier. |
|
1209 |
|
1210 Next we define the function @{text INJ} which takes as argument |
|
1211 @{text "reg_thm"} and @{text "quot_thm"} (both as |
|
1212 terms) and returns @{text "inj_thm"}: |
|
1213 |
|
1214 \begin{center} |
|
1215 \begin{tabular}{l} |
|
1216 \multicolumn{1}{@ {}l}{abstractions:}\\ |
|
1217 @{text "INJ (\<lambda>x. t :: \<sigma>, \<lambda>x. s :: \<tau>) "} $\dn$\\ |
|
1218 \hspace{18mm}$\begin{cases} |
|
1219 @{text "\<lambda>x. INJ (t, s)"} \quad\mbox{provided @{text "\<sigma> = \<tau>"}}\\ |
|
1220 @{text "REP (\<sigma>, \<tau>) (ABS (\<sigma>, \<tau>) (\<lambda>x. INJ (t, s)))"} |
|
1221 \end{cases}$\smallskip\\ |
|
1222 @{text "INJ (\<lambda>x \<in> R. t :: \<sigma>, \<lambda>x. s :: \<tau>) "} $\dn$\\ |
|
1223 \hspace{18mm}@{text "REP (\<sigma>, \<tau>) (ABS (\<sigma>, \<tau>) (\<lambda>x \<in> R. INJ (t, s)))"}\smallskip\\ |
|
1224 \multicolumn{1}{@ {}l}{universal quantifiers:}\\ |
|
1225 @{text "INJ (\<forall> t, \<forall> s) "} $\dn$ @{text "\<forall> INJ (t, s)"}\\ |
|
1226 @{text "INJ (\<forall> t \<in> R, \<forall> s) "} $\dn$ @{text "\<forall> INJ (t, s) \<in> R"}\smallskip\\ |
|
1227 \multicolumn{1}{@ {}l}{applications, variables and constants:}\smallskip\\ |
|
1228 @{text "INJ (t\<^isub>1 t\<^isub>2, s\<^isub>1 s\<^isub>2) "} $\dn$ @{text " INJ (t\<^isub>1, s\<^isub>1) INJ (t\<^isub>2, s\<^isub>2)"}\\ |
|
1229 @{text "INJ (x\<^isub>1\<^sup>\<sigma>, x\<^isub>2\<^sup>\<tau>) "} $\dn$ |
|
1230 $\begin{cases} |
|
1231 @{text "x\<^isub>1"} \quad\mbox{provided @{text "\<sigma> = \<tau>"}}\\ |
|
1232 @{text "REP (\<sigma>, \<tau>) (ABS (\<sigma>, \<tau>) x\<^isub>1)"}\\ |
|
1233 \end{cases}$\\ |
|
1234 @{text "INJ (c\<^isub>1\<^sup>\<sigma>, c\<^isub>2\<^sup>\<tau>) "} $\dn$ |
|
1235 $\begin{cases} |
|
1236 @{text "c\<^isub>1"} \quad\mbox{provided @{text "\<sigma> = \<tau>"}}\\ |
|
1237 @{text "REP (\<sigma>, \<tau>) (ABS (\<sigma>, \<tau>) c\<^isub>1)"}\\ |
|
1238 \end{cases}$\\ |
|
1239 \end{tabular} |
|
1240 \end{center} |
|
1241 |
|
1242 \noindent |
|
1243 In this definition we again omitted the cases for existential and unique existential |
|
1244 quantifiers. |
|
1245 |
|
1246 %%% FIXME: Reviewer2 citing following sentence: You mention earlier |
|
1247 %%% that this implication may fail to be true. Does that meant that |
|
1248 %%% the `first proof step' is a heuristic that proves the implication |
|
1249 %%% raw_thm \implies reg_thm in some instances, but fails in others? |
|
1250 %%% You should clarify under which circumstances the implication is |
|
1251 %%% being proved here. |
|
1252 %%% Cezary: It would be nice to cite Homeiers discussions in the |
|
1253 %%% Quotient Package manual from HOL (the longer paper), do you agree? |
|
1254 |
|
1255 In the first phase, establishing @{text "raw_thm \<longrightarrow> reg_thm"}, we always |
|
1256 start with an implication. Isabelle provides \emph{mono} rules that can split up |
|
1257 the implications into simpler implicational subgoals. This succeeds for every |
|
1258 monotone connective, except in places where the function @{text REG} replaced, |
|
1259 for instance, a quantifier by a bounded quantifier. To decompose them, we have |
|
1260 to prove that the relations involved are aggregate equivalence relations. |
|
1261 |
|
1262 |
|
1263 %In this case we have |
|
1264 %rules of the form |
|
1265 % |
|
1266 % \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
1267 %@{text "(\<forall>x. R x \<longrightarrow> (P x \<longrightarrow> Q x)) \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>x. P x \<longrightarrow> \<forall>x \<in> R. Q x)"} |
|
1268 %\end{isabelle} |
|
1269 |
|
1270 %\noindent |
|
1271 %They decompose a bounded quantifier on the right-hand side. We can decompose a |
|
1272 %bounded quantifier anywhere if R is an equivalence relation or |
|
1273 %if it is a relation over function types with the range being an equivalence |
|
1274 %relation. If @{text R} is an equivalence relation we can prove that |
|
1275 |
|
1276 %\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
1277 %@{text "\<forall>x \<in> Resp R. P x = \<forall>x. P x"} |
|
1278 %\end{isabelle} |
|
1279 |
|
1280 %\noindent |
|
1281 %If @{term R\<^isub>2} is an equivalence relation, we can prove that for any predicate @{term P} |
|
1282 |
|
1283 %%% FIXME Reviewer 1 claims the theorem is obviously false so maybe we |
|
1284 %%% should include a proof sketch? |
|
1285 |
|
1286 %\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
1287 %@{thm (concl) ball_reg_eqv_range[of R\<^isub>1 R\<^isub>2]} |
|
1288 %\end{isabelle} |
|
1289 |
|
1290 %\noindent |
|
1291 %The last theorem is new in comparison with Homeier's package. There the |
|
1292 %injection procedure would be used to prove such goals and |
|
1293 %the assumption about the equivalence relation would be used. We use the above theorem directly, |
|
1294 %because this allows us to completely separate the first and the second |
|
1295 %proof step into two independent ``units''. |
|
1296 |
|
1297 The second phase, establishing @{text "reg_thm \<longleftrightarrow> inj_thm"}, starts with an equality |
|
1298 between the terms of the regularized theorem and the injected theorem. |
|
1299 The proof again follows the structure of the |
|
1300 two underlying terms taking respectfulness theorems into account. |
|
1301 |
|
1302 %\begin{itemize} |
|
1303 %\item For two constants an appropriate respectfulness theorem is applied. |
|
1304 %\item For two variables, we use the assumptions proved in the regularization step. |
|
1305 %\item For two abstractions, we @{text "\<eta>"}-expand and @{text "\<beta>"}-reduce them. |
|
1306 %\item For two applications, we check that the right-hand side is an application of |
|
1307 % @{term Rep} to an @{term Abs} and @{term "Quotient R Rep Abs"} holds. If yes then we |
|
1308 % can apply the theorem: |
|
1309 |
|
1310 %\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
1311 % @{term "R x y \<longrightarrow> R x (Rep (Abs y))"} |
|
1312 %\end{isabelle} |
|
1313 |
|
1314 % Otherwise we introduce an appropriate relation between the subterms |
|
1315 % and continue with two subgoals using the lemma: |
|
1316 |
|
1317 %\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
1318 % @{text "(R\<^isub>1 \<doublearr> R\<^isub>2) f g \<longrightarrow> R\<^isub>1 x y \<longrightarrow> R\<^isub>2 (f x) (g y)"} |
|
1319 %\end{isabelle} |
|
1320 %\end{itemize} |
|
1321 |
|
1322 We defined the theorem @{text "inj_thm"} in such a way that |
|
1323 establishing in the third phase the equivalence @{text "inj_thm \<longleftrightarrow> quot_thm"} can be |
|
1324 achieved by rewriting @{text "inj_thm"} with the preservation theorems and quotient |
|
1325 definitions. This step also requires that the definitions of all lifted constants |
|
1326 are used to fold the @{term Rep} with the raw constants. We will give more details |
|
1327 about our lifting procedure in a longer version of this paper. |
|
1328 |
|
1329 %Next for |
|
1330 %all abstractions and quantifiers the lambda and |
|
1331 %quantifier preservation theorems are used to replace the |
|
1332 %variables that include raw types with respects by quantifiers |
|
1333 %over variables that include quotient types. We show here only |
|
1334 %the lambda preservation theorem. Given |
|
1335 %@{term "Quotient R\<^isub>1 Abs\<^isub>1 Rep\<^isub>1"} and @{term "Quotient R\<^isub>2 Abs\<^isub>2 Rep\<^isub>2"}, we have: |
|
1336 |
|
1337 %\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
1338 %@{thm (concl) lambda_prs[of _ "Abs\<^isub>1" "Rep\<^isub>1" _ "Abs\<^isub>2" "Rep\<^isub>2"]} |
|
1339 %\end{isabelle} |
|
1340 |
|
1341 %\noindent |
|
1342 %Next, relations over lifted types can be rewritten to equalities |
|
1343 %over lifted type. Rewriting is performed with the following theorem, |
|
1344 %which has been shown by Homeier~\cite{Homeier05}: |
|
1345 |
|
1346 %\begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
1347 %@{thm (concl) Quotient_rel_rep} |
|
1348 %\end{isabelle} |
|
1349 |
|
1350 |
|
1351 %Finally, we rewrite with the preservation theorems. This will result |
|
1352 %in two equal terms that can be solved by reflexivity. |
|
1353 *} |
|
1354 |
|
1355 section {* Derivation of the shape of lifted and raw theorems\label{sec:descending} *} |
|
1356 |
|
1357 text {* |
|
1358 In the previous sections we have assumed, that the user specifies |
|
1359 both the raw theorem and the statement of the quotient one. |
|
1360 This allows complete flexibility, as to which parts of the statement |
|
1361 are lifted to the quotient level and which are intact. In |
|
1362 other implementations of automatic quotients (for example Homeier's |
|
1363 package) only the raw theorem is given to the quotient package and |
|
1364 the package is able to guess the quotient one. In this |
|
1365 section we give examples where there are multiple possible valid lifted |
|
1366 theorems starting from a raw one. We also show a heuristic for |
|
1367 computing the quotient theorem from a raw one, and a mechanism for |
|
1368 guessing a raw theorem starting with a quotient one. |
|
1369 *} |
|
1370 |
|
1371 subsection {* Multiple lifted theorems *} |
|
1372 |
|
1373 text {* |
|
1374 There are multiple reasons why multiple valid lifted theorems can arize. |
|
1375 Below we describe three possible scenarios: multiple raw variable, |
|
1376 multiple quotients for the same raw type and multiple quotients. |
|
1377 |
|
1378 Given a raw theorem there are often several variables that include |
|
1379 a raw type. It this case, one can choose which of the variables to |
|
1380 lift. In certain cases this can lead to a number of valid theorem |
|
1381 statements, however type constraints may disallow certain combinations. |
|
1382 Lets see an example where multiple variables can have different types. |
|
1383 The Isabelle/HOL induction principle for two lists is: |
|
1384 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
1385 @{thm list_induct2'} |
|
1386 \end{isabelle} |
|
1387 |
|
1388 the conclusion is a predicate of the form @{text "P xs ys"}, where |
|
1389 the two variables are lists. When lifting such theorem to the quotient |
|
1390 type one can choose if one want to quotient @{text "xs"} or @{text "ys"}, or |
|
1391 both. All these give rise to valid quotiented theorems, however the |
|
1392 automatic mode (or other quotient packages) would derive only the version |
|
1393 with both being quotiented, namely: |
|
1394 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ %%% |
|
1395 @{thm list_induct2'[quot_lifted]} |
|
1396 \end{isabelle} |
|
1397 |
|
1398 A second scenario, where multiple possible quotient theorems arise is |
|
1399 when a single raw type is used in two quotients. Consider three quotients |
|
1400 of the list type: finite sets, finite multisets and lists with distinct |
|
1401 elements. We have developed all three types with the help of the quotient |
|
1402 package. Given a theorem that talks about lists --- for example the regular |
|
1403 induction principle --- one can lift it to three possible theorems: the |
|
1404 induction principle for finite sets, induction principle for finite |
|
1405 multisets or the induction principle for distinct lists. Again given an |
|
1406 induction principle for two lists this gives rise to 15 possible valid |
|
1407 lifted theorems. |
|
1408 |
|
1409 In our developments using the quotient package we also encountered a |
|
1410 scenario where multiple valid theorem statements arise, but the raw |
|
1411 types are not identical. Consider the type of lambda terms, where the |
|
1412 variables are indexed with strings. Quotienting lambda terms by alpha |
|
1413 equivalence gives rise to a Nominal construction~\cite{Nominal}. However |
|
1414 at the same time the type of strings being a list of characters can |
|
1415 lift to theorems about finite sets of characters. |
|
1416 *} |
|
1417 |
|
1418 subsection {* Derivation of the shape of theorems *} |
|
1419 |
|
1420 text {* |
|
1421 To derive a the shape of a lifted or raw theorem the quotient package |
|
1422 first builds a type and term substitution. |
|
1423 |
|
1424 The list of type substitution is created by taking the pairs |
|
1425 @{text "(raw_type, quotient_type)"} for every user defined quotient. |
|
1426 The term substitutions are of two types: First for every user-defined |
|
1427 quotient constant, the pair @{text "(raw_term, quotient_constant)"} |
|
1428 is included in the substitution. Second, for every quotient relation |
|
1429 @{text "\<approx>"} the pair @{text "(\<approx>, =)"} with the equality being the |
|
1430 equality on the defined quotient type is included in the substitution. |
|
1431 |
|
1432 The derivation function next traverses the theorem statement expressed |
|
1433 as a term and replaces the types of all free variables and of all |
|
1434 lambda-abstractions using the type substitution. For every constant |
|
1435 is not matched by the term substitution and we perform the type substitution |
|
1436 on the type of the constant (this is necessary for quotienting theorems |
|
1437 with polymorphic constants) or the type of the substitution is matched |
|
1438 and the match is returned. |
|
1439 |
|
1440 The heuristic defined above is greedy and according to our experience |
|
1441 this is what the user wants. The procedure may in some cases produce |
|
1442 theorem statements that do not type-check. However verifying all |
|
1443 possible theorem statements is too costly in general. |
|
1444 *} |
|
1445 |
|
1446 subsection {* Interaction modes and derivation of the the shape of theorems *} |
|
1447 |
|
1448 text {* |
|
1449 In the quotient package we provide three interaction modes, that use |
|
1450 can the procedure procedure defined in the previous subsection. |
|
1451 |
|
1452 First, the completely manual mode which we implemented as the |
|
1453 Isabelle method @{text lifting}. In this mode the user first |
|
1454 proves the raw theorem. Then the lifted theorem can be proved |
|
1455 by the method lifting, that takes the reference to the raw theorem |
|
1456 (or theorem list) as an argument. Such completely manual mode is |
|
1457 necessary for theorems where the specification of the lifted theorem |
|
1458 from the raw one is not unique, which we discussed in the previous |
|
1459 subsection. |
|
1460 |
|
1461 Next, we provide a mode for automatically lifting a given |
|
1462 raw theorem. We implemented this mode as an isabelle attribute, |
|
1463 so given the raw theorem @{text thm}, the user can refer to the |
|
1464 theorem @{text "thm[quot_lifted]"}. |
|
1465 |
|
1466 Finally we provie a method for translating a given quotient |
|
1467 level theorem to a raw one. We implemented this as an Isabelle |
|
1468 method @{text descending}. The user starts with expressing a |
|
1469 quotient level theorem statement and applies this method. |
|
1470 The quotient package derives a raw level statement and assumes |
|
1471 it as a subgoal. Given that this subgoal is proved, the quotient |
|
1472 package can lift the raw theorem fulfilling the proof of the |
|
1473 original lifted theorem statement. |
|
1474 *} |
|
1475 |
|
1476 section {* Conclusion and Related Work\label{sec:conc}*} |
|
1477 |
|
1478 text {* |
|
1479 |
|
1480 \noindent |
|
1481 The code of the quotient package and the examples described here are already |
|
1482 included in the standard distribution of Isabelle. |
|
1483 \footnote{Available from \href{http://isabelle.in.tum.de/}{http://isabelle.in.tum.de/}.} |
|
1484 The package is |
|
1485 heavily used in the new version of Nominal Isabelle, which provides a |
|
1486 convenient reasoning infrastructure for programming language calculi |
|
1487 involving general binders. To achieve this, it builds types representing |
|
1488 @{text \<alpha>}-equivalent terms. Earlier versions of Nominal Isabelle have been |
|
1489 used successfully in formalisations of an equivalence checking algorithm for |
|
1490 LF \cite{UrbanCheneyBerghofer08}, Typed |
|
1491 Scheme~\cite{TobinHochstadtFelleisen08}, several calculi for concurrency |
|
1492 \cite{BengtsonParow09} and a strong normalisation result for cut-elimination |
|
1493 in classical logic \cite{UrbanZhu08}. |
|
1494 |
|
1495 {\bf INSTEAD OF NOMINAL WORK, GIVE WORK BY BULWAHN ET AL?} |
|
1496 |
|
1497 There is a wide range of existing literature for dealing with quotients |
|
1498 in theorem provers. Slotosch~\cite{Slotosch97} implemented a mechanism that |
|
1499 automatically defines quotient types for Isabelle/HOL. But he did not |
|
1500 include theorem lifting. Harrison's quotient package~\cite{harrison-thesis} |
|
1501 is the first one that is able to automatically lift theorems, however only |
|
1502 first-order theorems (that is theorems where abstractions, quantifiers and |
|
1503 variables do not involve functions that include the quotient type). There is |
|
1504 also some work on quotient types in non-HOL based systems and logical |
|
1505 frameworks, including theory interpretations in |
|
1506 PVS~\cite{PVS:Interpretations}, new types in MetaPRL~\cite{Nogin02}, and |
|
1507 setoids in Coq \cite{ChicliPS02}. Paulson showed a construction of |
|
1508 quotients that does not require the Hilbert Choice operator, but also only |
|
1509 first-order theorems can be lifted~\cite{Paulson06}. The most related work |
|
1510 to our package is the package for HOL4 by Homeier~\cite{Homeier05}. He |
|
1511 introduced most of the abstract notions about quotients and also deals with |
|
1512 lifting of higher-order theorems. However, he cannot deal with quotient |
|
1513 compositions (needed for lifting theorems about @{text flat}). Also, a |
|
1514 number of his definitions, like @{text ABS}, @{text REP} and @{text INJ} etc |
|
1515 only exist in \cite{Homeier05} as ML-code, not included in the paper. |
|
1516 Like Homeier's, our quotient package can deal with partial equivalence |
|
1517 relations, but for lack of space we do not describe the mechanisms |
|
1518 needed for this kind of quotient constructions. |
|
1519 |
|
1520 %%% FIXME Reviewer 3 would like to know more about the lifting in Coq and PVS, |
|
1521 %%% and some comparison. I don't think we have the space for any additions... |
|
1522 |
|
1523 One feature of our quotient package is that when lifting theorems, the user |
|
1524 can precisely specify what the lifted theorem should look like. This feature |
|
1525 is necessary, for example, when lifting an induction principle for two |
|
1526 lists. Assuming this principle has as the conclusion a predicate of the |
|
1527 form @{text "P xs ys"}, then we can precisely specify whether we want to |
|
1528 quotient @{text "xs"} or @{text "ys"}, or both. We found this feature very |
|
1529 useful in the new version of Nominal Isabelle, where such a choice is |
|
1530 required to generate a reasoning infrastructure for alpha-equated terms. |
|
1531 %% |
|
1532 %% give an example for this |
|
1533 %% |
|
1534 \smallskip |
|
1535 |
|
1536 \noindent |
|
1537 {\bf Acknowledgements:} We would like to thank Peter Homeier for the many |
|
1538 discussions about his HOL4 quotient package and explaining to us |
|
1539 some of its finer points in the implementation. Without his patient |
|
1540 help, this work would have been impossible. We would like to thank |
|
1541 Andreas Lochbiler for his comments on the first version of the quotient |
|
1542 package, in particular for the suggestions about the descending method. |
|
1543 |
|
1544 *} |
|
1545 |
|
1546 text_raw {* |
|
1547 %%\bibliographystyle{abbrv} |
|
1548 \bibliography{root} |
|
1549 |
|
1550 \appendix |
|
1551 |
|
1552 *} |
|
1553 |
|
1554 section {* Examples \label{sec:examples} *} |
|
1555 |
|
1556 text {* |
|
1557 |
|
1558 %%% FIXME Reviewer 1 would like an example of regularized and injected |
|
1559 %%% statements. He asks for the examples twice, but I would still ignore |
|
1560 %%% it due to lack of space... |
|
1561 |
|
1562 \noindent |
|
1563 In this appendix we will show a sequence of declarations for defining the |
|
1564 type of integers by quotienting pairs of natural numbers, and |
|
1565 lifting one theorem. |
|
1566 |
|
1567 A user of our quotient package first needs to define a relation on |
|
1568 the raw type with which the quotienting will be performed. We give |
|
1569 the same integer relation as the one presented in \eqref{natpairequiv}: |
|
1570 |
|
1571 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ % |
|
1572 \begin{tabular}{@ {}l} |
|
1573 \isacommand{fun}~~@{text "int_rel :: (nat \<times> nat) \<Rightarrow> (nat \<times> nat) \<Rightarrow> bool"}\\ |
|
1574 \isacommand{where}~~@{text "int_rel (m, n) (p, q) = (m + q = n + p)"} |
|
1575 \end{tabular} |
|
1576 \end{isabelle} |
|
1577 |
|
1578 \noindent |
|
1579 Next the quotient type must be defined. This generates a proof obligation that the |
|
1580 relation is an equivalence relation, which is solved automatically using the |
|
1581 definition of equivalence and extensionality: |
|
1582 |
|
1583 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ % |
|
1584 \begin{tabular}{@ {}l} |
|
1585 \isacommand{quotient\_type}~~@{text "int"}~~\isacommand{=}~~@{text "(nat \<times> nat)"}~~\isacommand{/}~~@{text "int_rel"}\\ |
|
1586 \hspace{5mm}@{text "by (auto simp add: equivp_def expand_fun_eq)"} |
|
1587 \end{tabular} |
|
1588 \end{isabelle} |
|
1589 |
|
1590 \noindent |
|
1591 The user can then specify the constants on the quotient type: |
|
1592 |
|
1593 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ % |
|
1594 \begin{tabular}{@ {}l} |
|
1595 \isacommand{quotient\_definition}~~@{text "0 :: int"}~~\isacommand{is}~~@{text "(0 :: nat, 0 :: nat)"}\\[3mm] |
|
1596 \isacommand{fun}~~@{text "add_pair"}\\ |
|
1597 \isacommand{where}~~% |
|
1598 @{text "add_pair (m, n) (p, q) \<equiv> (m + p :: nat, n + q :: nat)"}\\ |
|
1599 \isacommand{quotient\_definition}~~@{text "+ :: int \<Rightarrow> int \<Rightarrow> int"}~~% |
|
1600 \isacommand{is}~~@{text "add_pair"}\\ |
|
1601 \end{tabular} |
|
1602 \end{isabelle} |
|
1603 |
|
1604 \noindent |
|
1605 The following theorem about addition on the raw level can be proved. |
|
1606 |
|
1607 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ % |
|
1608 \isacommand{lemma}~~@{text "add_pair_zero: int_rel (add_pair (0, 0) x) x"} |
|
1609 \end{isabelle} |
|
1610 |
|
1611 \noindent |
|
1612 If the user lifts this theorem, the quotient package performs all the lifting |
|
1613 automatically leaving the respectfulness proof for the constant @{text "add_pair"} |
|
1614 as the only remaining proof obligation. This property needs to be proved by the user: |
|
1615 |
|
1616 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ % |
|
1617 \begin{tabular}{@ {}l} |
|
1618 \isacommand{lemma}~~@{text "[quot_respect]:"}\\ |
|
1619 @{text "(int_rel \<doublearr> int_rel \<doublearr> int_rel) add_pair add_pair"} |
|
1620 \end{tabular} |
|
1621 \end{isabelle} |
|
1622 |
|
1623 \noindent |
|
1624 It can be discharged automatically by Isabelle when hinting to unfold the definition |
|
1625 of @{text "\<doublearr>"}. |
|
1626 After this, the user can prove the lifted lemma as follows: |
|
1627 |
|
1628 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ % |
|
1629 \isacommand{lemma}~~@{text "0 + (x :: int) = x"}~~\isacommand{by}~~@{text "lifting add_pair_zero"} |
|
1630 \end{isabelle} |
|
1631 |
|
1632 \noindent |
|
1633 or by using the completely automated mode stating just: |
|
1634 |
|
1635 \begin{isabelle}\ \ \ \ \ % |
|
1636 \isacommand{thm}~~@{text "add_pair_zero[quot_lifted]"} |
|
1637 \end{isabelle} |
|
1638 |
|
1639 \noindent |
|
1640 Both methods give the same result, namely @{text "0 + x = x"} |
|
1641 where @{text x} is of type integer. |
|
1642 Although seemingly simple, arriving at this result without the help of a quotient |
|
1643 package requires a substantial reasoning effort (see \cite{Paulson06}). |
|
1644 |
|
1645 {\bf \begin{itemize} |
|
1646 \item explain how Quotient R Abs Rep is proved |
|
1647 \item Type maps and Relation maps (show the case for functions) |
|
1648 \item Quotient extensions (quot\_thms) |
|
1649 \item Respectfulness and preservation |
|
1650 - Show special cases for quantifiers and lambda |
|
1651 - How do prs theorems look like for quotient compositions |
|
1652 \item Quotient-type locale |
|
1653 - Show the proof as much simpler than Homeier's one |
|
1654 \item ??? Infrastructure for storing theorems (rsp, prs, eqv, quot and idsimp) |
|
1655 \item Lifting vs Descending vs quot\_lifted |
|
1656 - automatic theorem translation heuristic |
|
1657 \item Partial equivalence quotients |
|
1658 - Bounded abstraction |
|
1659 - Respects |
|
1660 - partial descending |
|
1661 \item The heuristics for automatic regularization, injection and cleaning. |
|
1662 \item A complete example of a lifted theorem together with the regularized |
|
1663 injected and cleaned statement |
|
1664 \item Examples of quotients and properties that we used the package for. |
|
1665 \item co/contra-variance from Ondrej should be taken into account |
|
1666 \item give an example where precise specification of goal is necessary |
|
1667 \item mention multiple map\_prs2 theorems for compositional quotients |
|
1668 \end{itemize}} |
|
1669 *} |
|
1670 |
|
1671 |
|
1672 |
|
1673 (*<*) |
|
1674 end |
|
1675 (*>*) |
|