1 |
|
2 > Referee no 1: |
|
3 > |
|
4 > * The paper can be accepted for Logical Methods in Computer Science |
|
5 > after minor |
|
6 > revisions |
|
7 > |
|
8 > NUMBER : LMCS-2011-675 |
|
9 > TITLE : General Bindings and Alpha-Equivalence in Nominal Isabelle |
|
10 > AUTHOR(S) : Christian Urban, Cezary Kaliszyk |
|
11 > |
|
12 > Recommendation: The paper can be accepted for Logical Methods in |
|
13 > Computer Science after minor revisions. |
|
14 > |
|
15 > The work reported is very good, but the presentation of the paper can |
|
16 > be improved. |
|
17 > |
|
18 > [...] |
|
19 > |
|
20 > However, I recommend improvement of the presentation of the paper |
|
21 > before it is accepted by LMCS. While the motivation for the work of |
|
22 > this paper is clear to anyone who has tried to formalize such |
|
23 > reasoning, it is not explained in the paper. E.g. on p.1 "However, |
|
24 > Nominal Isabelle has fared less well in a formalisation of the |
|
25 > algorithm W [...]." But there is no analysis in the paper of what was |
|
26 > hard in algorithm W coded with single binders, or explanation of how |
|
27 > it would be done in the new system reported in this paper showing why |
|
28 > the new approach works better in practice. |
|
29 |
|
30 We have expanded on the point and given details why single |
|
31 binders lead to clumsy formalisations of W. |
|
32 |
|
33 > Although this example is |
|
34 > one of the main motivations given for the work, there is apparently no |
|
35 > formalization of algorithm W in the library of examples that comes |
|
36 > with Nominal2 described in this paper. I think that should be |
|
37 > provided. Similarly for the second motivating example (on p.2 "The |
|
38 > need of iterating single binders is also one reason why Nominal |
|
39 > Isabelle and similar theorem provers that only provide mechanisms for |
|
40 > binding single variables have not fared extremely well with the more |
|
41 > advanced tasks in the POPLmark challenge [2], because also there one |
|
42 > would like to bind multiple variables at once."). |
|
43 |
|
44 We proved the main properties about type-schemes in algorithm W: |
|
45 the ones that caused problems in our earlier formalisation. Though |
|
46 the complete formalisation of W is not yet in place. |
|
47 |
|
48 > The new Isabelle package "Nominal2", described in this paper, is not |
|
49 > ready for users without a lot of hand-holding from the Nominal2 |
|
50 > developers. This paper would have more impact if interested users |
|
51 > could try the tool without so much difficulty. |
|
52 |
|
53 The plan is to have Nominal Isabelle be part of the next stable |
|
54 release of Isabelle, which should be out in Autumn 2012. |
|
55 At the moment it can be downloaded as a bundle and is ready |
|
56 to be used (there are two groups that use Nominal2 and |
|
57 only occasionally ask questions on the mailing list). |
|
58 |
|
59 > A few more specific points: |
|
60 > |
|
61 > Bottom of p.7: I don't understand the paragraph containing equations |
|
62 > (2.4) and (2.5). |
|
63 |
|
64 We reworded this paragraph. |
|
65 |
|
66 > Bottom of p.9: The parameters R and fa of the alpha equivalence |
|
67 > relation are dropped in the examples, so the examples are not clear. |
|
68 |
|
69 We have two minds with this: Keeping R and fa is more faithful to |
|
70 the definition, but it would not provide much intuition into |
|
71 the definition. We feel explaining the definition in special |
|
72 cases is more beneficial to the reader. |
|
73 |
|
74 > I think there is a typo in the first example: "It can be easily |
|
75 > checked that ({x,y},x->y) and ({y,x},y->x) are alpha-equivalent [...]" |
|
76 > Did you mean "({x,y},x->y) and ({y,x},x->y) are alpha-equivalent"? |
|
77 |
|
78 Both are equivalent since sets {x, y} and {y, x} are equal. But we made |
|
79 it clearer as you suggest. |
|
80 |
|
81 > Referee no 2: |
|
82 > |
|
83 > [...] |
|
84 > |
|
85 > My main criticisms of the paper are: |
|
86 > |
|
87 > * The definition of the "nominal signature" language is not completely clear. |
|
88 > The general format at the beginning of section 4 is very clear, but is in |
|
89 > fact too general: not everything that can be written in this format makes |
|
90 > sense. The authors then walk the reader through a series of |
|
91 > examples of what |
|
92 > is *forbidden* (with informal explanations why these examples are |
|
93 > forbidden), but in the end, a positive definition of what is *permitted* |
|
94 > seems to be missing. |
|
95 |
|
96 Yes, we agree very much: a positive definition would be very desirable. |
|
97 Unfortunately, this is not as easy as one would hope. Already a positive |
|
98 definition for a *datatype* in HOL is rather tricky. We would rely on this |
|
99 for nominal datatypes. Then we would need to think about what to do with |
|
100 nested datatype, before coming to nominal matters. |
|
101 |
|
102 The only real defence for not giving a positive we have is that we give a |
|
103 sensible "upper bound". To appreciate this point, you need to consider that |
|
104 systems like Ott go beyond this upper bound and give definitions which are |
|
105 not sensible in the context of (named) alpha-equated structures. |
|
106 |
|
107 > * The authors have isolated an important building block, the notion of |
|
108 > (multiple-name) abstraction (in Section 3). (Actually, there are three |
|
109 > variants of it.) This is good: it makes the whole construction modular |
|
110 > and helps simplify what follows. I don't know if this will make sense |
|
111 > for the authors, but I would like them to go further in this direction: |
|
112 > identify more elementary building blocks ("combinators", if you will), |
|
113 > study their properties in isolation, and in the end combine them to |
|
114 > obtain a very simple explanation of the "nominal signature" format |
|
115 > that is exposed to the user. In the present state of the paper, the |
|
116 > design of the "nominal signature" format seems somewhat ad hoc: the |
|
117 > format of the "binds" clauses is subject to several restrictions; |
|
118 > there seems to be a distinction between "binders" and ordinary |
|
119 > "terms"; there is a distinction between "recursive" and "non-recursive" |
|
120 > binders, and a distinction between "shallow" and "deep" binders. If |
|
121 > one could identify a small number of elementary building blocks and |
|
122 > explain/motivate the design of the surface specification language in |
|
123 > terms of these elementary notions, the paper might become all the more |
|
124 > compelling. |
|
125 |
|
126 We are not sure whether we can make progress with this. There is such a |
|
127 "combinator approach" described by Francois Pottier for C-alpha-ML. His approach |
|
128 only needs an inner and outer combinator. However, this has led to quite |
|
129 non-intuitive representations of "nominal datatypes". We attempted |
|
130 to be as close as possible to what is used in the "wild" (and in Ott). |
|
131 This led us to isolate the notions of shallow, deep and recursive binders. |
|
132 |
|
133 > In the present state of the paper, I think the *implementation* of the |
|
134 > nominal package is very useful for the end user, but the *theory* that is |
|
135 > presented in this paper is still a bit cumbersome: the definitions of free |
|
136 > atoms, alpha-equivalence, etc. presented on pages 16-20 are understandable |
|
137 > but not compelling by their simplicity. |
|
138 |
|
139 We agree - simpler would be much better. However, we refer the referee to "competing" |
|
140 definitions that are substantially more complicated. Please try to understand |
|
141 the notion of alpha-equivalence for Ott (which has been published). Taking |
|
142 tgis into account, we really think our definitions are a substantial improvement, |
|
143 as witnessed by the fact that we were actually able to code them up. |
|
144 |
|
145 > * I do not quite understand the treatment of the finiteness restriction. |
|
146 > I understand that things must have finite support so as to allow picking |
|
147 > atoms outside of their support. But finiteness side conditions seem to |
|
148 > appear pretty early and in unexpected places; e.g. I would expect the |
|
149 > support of a set of atoms "as" to be equal to "as", regardless of whether |
|
150 > "as" is finite or infinite. This could be clarified. |
|
151 |
|
152 This is a peculiarity of support which has been explained elsewhere in the nominal |
|
153 literature (pointers in the paper). Assume all_atoms is the set of all atoms then |
|
154 |
|
155 supp all_atoms = {} |
|
156 |
|
157 For sets of atoms the support behaves as follows: |
|
158 |
|
159 supp as = as if as is finite |
|
160 supp as = all_atoms if as and all_atoms - as are infinite |
|
161 supp as = all_atoms - as if as is co-finite |
|
162 |
|
163 As said, such properties have been described in the literature and it would be |
|
164 overkill to include them again in this paper. Since in programming language research |
|
165 nearly always considers only finitely supported structures, we often restrict |
|
166 our work to these cases. Knowing that an object of interest has only finite support |
|
167 is needed when fresh atoms need to be chosen. |
|
168 |
|
169 > * The choice of abstraction "style" is limited to three built-in forms (list, |
|
170 > set, and set+). Perhaps one could make this user-extensible. After |
|
171 > all, very few properties seem to be required of the basic abstraction forms, |
|
172 > so why not let the user define new ones? |
|
173 |
|
174 This would be nice, but we do make use of the equality properties |
|
175 of abstractions (which are different for the set, set+ and list cases). |
|
176 So we have yet to find a unifying framework. |
|
177 |
|
178 > * One may argue that the set-abstractions are an attempt to kill two birds |
|
179 > with one stone. On the one hand, we take the quotient raw terms modulo a |
|
180 > standard notion of alpha-equivalence; on the other hand, at the same time, |
|
181 > we take the quotient modulo a notion of structural equivalence (permutation |
|
182 > of binders, removal or introduction of vacuous binders). One could argue |
|
183 > that dealing with structural equivalence should be left to the user, because |
|
184 > in general the structural equivalence axioms that the user needs can be |
|
185 > arbitrarily complex and application-specific. |
|
186 |
|
187 Yes, we can actually only deal with *one* non-trivial structural equivalence, |
|
188 namely set+ (introduction of vacuous binders). For us, it seems this is an application |
|
189 that occurs more often than not. Type-schemes are one example; the Psi-calculus |
|
190 from the group around Joachim Parrow are another; in the paper we also point to |
|
191 work by Altenkirch that uses set+. Therefore we like to give automated support |
|
192 for set+. Doing this without automatic support would be quite painful for the user. |
|
193 |
|
194 > There are object languages, |
|
195 > for instance, where abstractions commute with pairs: binding a name in a |
|
196 > pair is the same as binding a name within each of the pair components. |
|
197 > (This is the case in first-order logic where forall distributes over |
|
198 > conjunction.) Thus, one may fear that in many cases, the set and set+ |
|
199 > abstractions will not be sufficiently powerful to encode the desired |
|
200 > structural equivalence, and the user will need to explicitly define |
|
201 > a notion |
|
202 > of structural equivalence anyway. I don't think that the paper provides |
|
203 > convincing evidence that set and set+ abstractions are useful. (That said, |
|
204 > they don't cost much, so why not include them? Sure.) |
|
205 |
|
206 From our experience, once a feature is included, applications will |
|
207 be found. Case in point, the set+ binder arises naturally in the |
|
208 psi-calculus and is used in work by Altenkirch. |
|
209 |
|
210 > * Here is little challenge related to set-abstractions. Could you explain how |
|
211 > to define the syntax of an object language with a construct like this: |
|
212 > |
|
213 > let x1 = t1 and ... and xn = tn in t |
|
214 > |
|
215 > where the xi's are bound in t (this is a non-recursive multiple-let form) |
|
216 > and the order of the definitions does not matter (that is, "let x1 = t1 |
|
217 > and x2 = t2 in t" is alpha-equivalent to "let x2 = t2 and x1 = t1 in t")? |
|
218 > Can you use a set-abstraction to achieve this? I am guessing that this |
|
219 > might be possible, if one represents the definitions "x1 = t1 and ..." |
|
220 > using a set of pairs (or a map of names to terms) as opposed to a list |
|
221 > of pairs. I think that the system should at the very least allow encoding |
|
222 > this example, otherwise set-abstractions will not be very useful in |
|
223 > practice. |
|
224 |
|
225 We can. We added this as an example in the conclusion section. |
|
226 |
|
227 > p.2, "this leads to a rather clumsy formalisation of W". Could you explain |
|
228 > why? Although I can understand why in some circumstances it is desirable to |
|
229 > have a notion of alpha-equivalence that includes re-ordering binders, |
|
230 > I am not |
|
231 > sure that the ML type system (or its inference algorithm) is a good |
|
232 > illustration. If one examines the typing rules of Core ML, one finds that |
|
233 > their premises involve a notion of equality between *types* (for |
|
234 > instance, the |
|
235 > function application rule requires that the types of the formal and actual |
|
236 > arguments match) but do not involve any notion of equality between *type |
|
237 > schemes*. Type schemes are constructed and eliminated; they are never |
|
238 > compared |
|
239 > with one another. For this reason, it is not clear that a notion of |
|
240 > alpha-equivalence for type schemes is required at all, let alone that it must |
|
241 > allow re-ordering binders and/or disregarding vacuous binders. |
|
242 |
|
243 In the correctness *proof* of W, the notion of capture-avoiding |
|
244 substitution plays a crucial role. The notion of capture-avoiding |
|
245 substitution without the notion of alpha-equivalence does not make |
|
246 much sense. This is different from *implementations* of W. They |
|
247 might get away with concrete representations of type-schemes. |
|
248 |
|
249 > p.3, "let the user chose" -> "choose" |
|
250 |
|
251 Fixed. |
|
252 |
|
253 > p.5, I am not sure what you mean by "automatic proofs". Do you mean |
|
254 > automatically-generated proof scripts, or proofs performed automatically by a |
|
255 > decision procedure, or ... ? |
|
256 |
|
257 Fixed. |
|
258 |
|
259 > p.5, "adaption" |
|
260 |
|
261 Fixed. |
|
262 |
|
263 > p.5, it seems strange to use the symbol "+" for composition, a |
|
264 > non-commutative |
|
265 > operation. |
|
266 |
|
267 Yes. This is a "flaw" in the type-class setup. If we want to reuse libraries |
|
268 from Isabelle, we have to bite into this "sour" apple. |
|
269 |
|
270 > Equation (2.2) is unfamiliar to me. I am used to seeing "supp x" defined as |
|
271 > the least set L such that for every permutation pi, if pi fixes L, then pi |
|
272 > fixes x. I assume that the two definitions are equivalent? Is there a reason |
|
273 > why you prefer this one? |
|
274 |
|
275 Our definition is equivalent to yours for finitely supported x. |
|
276 The advantage of our definition is that can be easily stated |
|
277 in a theorem prover since it fits into the scheme |
|
278 |
|
279 constant args = term |
|
280 |
|
281 Your definition as the least set...does not fit into this simple |
|
282 scheme. Our definition has been described extensively elsewhere, |
|
283 to which we refer the reader. |
|
284 |
|
285 > Proposition 2.3, item (i) is not very easy to read, because text and math |
|
286 > are mixed and "as" happens to be an English word. |
|
287 |
|
288 Replaced by bs. |
|
289 |
|
290 > More importantly, could |
|
291 > you explain why the hypothesis "finite as" is needed? The proposition seems |
|
292 > intuitively true if we remove this hypothesis: it states exactly that |
|
293 > "supp x" |
|
294 > is the least set that supports x (this is actually the definition of "supp" |
|
295 > that I expected, as mentioned above). |
|
296 |
|
297 It does *not* work for non-finitely supported sets of atoms. Imagine |
|
298 bs is the set of "even" atoms (a set that is not finite nor co-finite). |
|
299 |
|
300 bs supports bs |
|
301 |
|
302 but |
|
303 |
|
304 supp bs = all_atoms !<= bs |
|
305 |
|
306 > p.8, "equivariant functions have empty support". I suppose the converse is |
|
307 > true, i.e. "functions that have empty support are equivariant". If this is |
|
308 > correct, please say so. |
|
309 |
|
310 We have reworded this paragraph. |
|
311 |
|
312 > p.8, "we used extensively Property 2.1". You mean "Proposition 2.1". |
|
313 |
|
314 Fixed. |
|
315 |
|
316 > p.8, "we identify four conditions: (i) [...] x and y need to have the same |
|
317 > set of free atoms". You seem to be saying that fa(x) and fa(y) should be |
|
318 > equal. But this is too strong; I suppose you mean fa(x) \ as = fa(y) \ bs. |
|
319 > Please clarify. (Definition 3.1 indeed clarifies this, but I believe that |
|
320 > the text that precedes it is a bit confusing.) |
|
321 |
|
322 Fixed. |
|
323 |
|
324 > p.9, it seems to me that alpha-equivalence for Set+ bindings (Definition 3.3) |
|
325 > is in a sense the most general of the three notions presented here. Indeed, |
|
326 > alpha-equivalence for Set bindings can be defined in terms of it, as follows: |
|
327 > |
|
328 > (as, x) =_{Set} (bs, y) |
|
329 > if and only if |
|
330 > (as, (as, x)) =_{Set+} (bs, (bs, y)) |
|
331 > |
|
332 > That is, I am comparing abstractions whose body has type "atom set * beta". |
|
333 > The comparison of the set components forces condition (iv) of Definition 3.1. |
|
334 > Similarly, alpha-equivalence for List bindings can be defined in terms of it, |
|
335 > as follows: |
|
336 > |
|
337 > (as, x) =_{List} (bs, y) |
|
338 > if and only if |
|
339 > (set as, (as, x)) =_{Set+} (set bs, (bs, y)) |
|
340 > |
|
341 > That is, I am comparing abstractions whose body has type "atom list * beta". |
|
342 > Am I correct to think that one can do this? If so, could this help eliminate |
|
343 > some redundancy in the paper or in the implementation? And, for a |
|
344 > more radical |
|
345 > suggestion, could one decide to expose only Set+ equality to the programmer, |
|
346 > and let him/her explicitly encode Set/List equality where desired? |
|
347 |
|
348 The second property holds outright. The first holds provided as and bs |
|
349 are finite sets of atoms. However, we seem to not gain much code reduction |
|
350 from these properties, except for defining the modes set and list in terms |
|
351 of set+. Also often proving properties for set+ is harder than for the |
|
352 other modes. |
|
353 |
|
354 Since these modes behave differently as alpha-equivalence, the encoding would, |
|
355 in our opinion, blurr this difference. We however noted these facts in the conclusion. |
|
356 |
|
357 > p.10, "in these relation" |
|
358 |
|
359 Fixed. |
|
360 |
|
361 > p.10, isn't equation (3.3) a *definition* of the action of permutations |
|
362 > on the newly defined quotient type "beta abs_{set}"? |
|
363 |
|
364 Yes, we have this now as the definition. Earlier we really had |
|
365 derived this. Both methods need equal work (the definition |
|
366 needs a proof to be proper). Having it as definition is clearer. |
|
367 |
|
368 > p.11, why do you need to "assume that x has finite support" in order to |
|
369 > obtain property 3.4? It seems to me that this fact should also hold for |
|
370 > an x with infinite support. |
|
371 |
|
372 Fixed. |
|
373 |
|
374 > Same remark in a couple of places further |
|
375 > down on this page. You note that "supp bs = bs" holds "for every finite |
|
376 > set of atoms bs". Is it *not* the case that this also holds for infinite |
|
377 > sets? If so, what *is* the support of an infinite set of atoms? |
|
378 |
|
379 This property only holds for finite sets bs. See above. |
|
380 |
|
381 > Why not |
|
382 > adopt a definition of support that validates "supp bs = bs" for *every* |
|
383 > set of atoms bs? Is there a difficulty due to the fact that what you |
|
384 > call a "permutation" is in a fact "a permutation with finite support"? |
|
385 > I think it would be good to motivate your technical choices and clarify |
|
386 > exactly where/why a finite support assumption is required. |
|
387 |
|
388 This cannot be made as it is very natural to have the property |
|
389 that the set of all atoms has empty support. There is no permutation |
|
390 that does not fix that set. We cannot see how this can be made |
|
391 to work so that |
|
392 |
|
393 supp bs = bs |
|
394 |
|
395 for all sets. |
|
396 |
|
397 > p.11, "The other half is a bit more involved." I would suggest removing |
|
398 > this rather scary sentence. The proof actually appears very simple and |
|
399 > elegant to me. |
|
400 |
|
401 Fixed. |
|
402 |
|
403 > p.12, "mutual recursive" -> "mutually recursive" |
|
404 |
|
405 Fixed. |
|
406 |
|
407 > p.12, does the tool support parameterized data type definitions? If so, |
|
408 > please mention it, otherwise explain whether there is a difficulty (e.g. |
|
409 > the parameters would need to come with a notion of permutation). |
|
410 |
|
411 Yes. Note added. |
|
412 |
|
413 > p.12, "Interestingly, [...] will make a difference [...]". At this |
|
414 > point, upon |
|
415 > first reading, this is not "interesting" but rather frustrating, because it |
|
416 > does not sound natural: my understanding would be very much simplified if |
|
417 > "binds ... in t u" was equivalent to "binds ... in t, binds ... in |
|
418 > u". Because |
|
419 > a forward pointer is missing, I cannot find immediately where this is |
|
420 > explained, and this problem hinders my reading of the beginning of section 5. |
|
421 |
|
422 We have given a forward pointer. |
|
423 |
|
424 > p.13, the type of atoms now seems to be "name", whereas it was previously |
|
425 > "atom". The remark on the last line of page 13 leads me to understand that |
|
426 > "name" refers to one specific sort of atoms, whereas "atom" refers to an |
|
427 > atom of any sort (right?). The function "atom" converts one to the other; |
|
428 > but what is its type (is it overloaded?). |
|
429 |
|
430 Yes, atom is overloaded. |
|
431 |
|
432 > p.13, you distinguish shallow binders (binds x in ...) and deep binders |
|
433 > (binds bn(x) in ...). I would hope that a shallow binder is just syntactic |
|
434 > sugar for a deep binder where "bn" is the "singleton list" or "singleton |
|
435 > set" function. Is this the case? If not, why not? If yes, perhaps you could |
|
436 > remove all mentions to shallow binders in section 5. |
|
437 |
|
438 Not quite. A deep binder can be recursive, which is a notion |
|
439 that does not make sense for shallow binders. |
|
440 |
|
441 > p.14, "we cannot have more than one binding function for a deep binder". You |
|
442 > exclude "binds bn_1(p) bn_2(p) in t". Couldn't this be accepted and |
|
443 > interpreted as "binds bn_1(p) \cup bn_2(p) in t"? (I guess it does not matter |
|
444 > much either way.) |
|
445 |
|
446 That would make the definition of fa-function more complicated. |
|
447 |
|
448 > p.14, you also exclude "binds bn1(p) in t1, binds bn2(p) in t2". Two |
|
449 > questions. First, a clarification: if bn1 and bn2 are the same function, is |
|
450 > this allowed or excluded? |
|
451 |
|
452 For practical purposes, this is excluded. But the theory would |
|
453 support this case. I added a comment in the paper. |
|
454 |
|
455 > Second, I don't understand why you need this |
|
456 > restriction, that is, why you are trying to prevent an atom to be "bound and |
|
457 > free at the same time" (bound in one sub-term and free in another). I |
|
458 > mean, in |
|
459 > the case of single binders, you seem to allow "binds x y in t1, binds |
|
460 > y in t2" |
|
461 > (at least, you have not stated that you disallow this). There, occurrences of |
|
462 > x in t1 are considered bound, whereas occurrences of x in t2 are considered |
|
463 > free; is this correct? If so, why not allow "binds bn1(p) in t1, binds bn2(p) |
|
464 > in t2", which seems to be of a similar nature? |
|
465 |
|
466 The problem is that bn1 and bn2 can pick out different atoms to |
|
467 be free and bound in p. Therefore we have to exclude this case. |
|
468 |
|
469 > p.14, example 4.4, the restriction that you impose here seems to rule out |
|
470 > an interesting and potentially useful pattern, namely telescopes. A telescope |
|
471 > is a list of binders, where each binder scopes over the rest of the |
|
472 > telescope, |
|
473 > and in addition all of the names introduced by the telescope are considered |
|
474 > bound by the telescope in some separate term. I am thinking of |
|
475 > something along |
|
476 > the following lines: |
|
477 > |
|
478 > nominal_datatype trm = |
|
479 > | Var name |
|
480 > | Let tele::telescope body::trm binds bn(tele) in body |
|
481 > | ... |
|
482 > |
|
483 > and telescope = |
|
484 > | TNil |
|
485 > | TCons x::name rhs::trm rest::telescope binds x in rest |
|
486 > |
|
487 > binder bn::telescope => atom list |
|
488 > where bn (TNil) = [] |
|
489 > | bn (TCons x rhs rest) = [ atom x ] @ bn(rest) |
|
490 > |
|
491 > You write that "if we would permit bn to return y, then it would not be |
|
492 > respectful and therefore cannot be lifted to alpha-equated lambda-terms". I |
|
493 > can see why there is a problem: if "x" is considered bound (therefore |
|
494 > anonymous) in the telescope "TCons x rhs rest", then it cannot possibly be |
|
495 > returned by a (well-behaved) function "bn". I think that the answer to this |
|
496 > problem should be: we must pick an appropriate notion of alpha-equivalence |
|
497 > for telescopes, and this notion of alpha-equivalence must *not* consider x |
|
498 > as anonymous in "TCons x rhs rest". Instead, x must be considered free in |
|
499 > this telescope. The telescopes "TCons x rhs TNil" and "TCons y rhs TNil" |
|
500 > must be considered distinct. Of course we could achieve this effect just by |
|
501 > removing the clause "binds x in rest", but this would lead to a notion of |
|
502 > alpha-equivalence for "Let" terms which is not the desired one: when writing |
|
503 > "let (x1 = t1; x2 = t2) in t", we would like x1 to be bound in t2, and this |
|
504 > will not be the case if we omit "binds x in rest" in the above definition. |
|
505 > I conclude that your design (which seems very reasonable) cannot currently |
|
506 > express telescopes. It would be nice if you could explicitly discuss this |
|
507 > issue. Is it conceivable that an extension of your system could deal with |
|
508 > telescopes? Other researchers have proposed approaches that can deal with |
|
509 > them (I am thinking e.g. of ``Binders Unbound'' by Weirich et al.). |
|
510 |
|
511 Yes, we cannot deal with telescopes. We added a comment. |
|
512 |
|
513 > Here is another general question. How would you declare a nominal data type |
|
514 > for ML patterns? Informally, the syntax of patterns is: |
|
515 > |
|
516 > p ::= |
|
517 > x (variable) |
|
518 > | (p, p) where bn(p1) and bn(p2) are disjoint (pair) |
|
519 > | (p | p) where bn(p1) = bn(p2) (disjunction) |
|
520 > | ... |
|
521 > |
|
522 > In the case of a pair (or conjunction) pattern, one usually requires that the |
|
523 > two components bind disjoint sets of names, whereas in the case of a |
|
524 > disjunction pattern, one requires that the two components bind exactly the |
|
525 > same sets of names. How would you deal with this? I imagine that one could |
|
526 > just omit these two side conditions in the definition of the nominal data |
|
527 > type, and deal with them separately by defining a well-formedness predicate. |
|
528 |
|
529 Yes, that is how we would exclude non-linear patterns. |
|
530 |
|
531 > One question: in the definition of the "term" data type, at the point where |
|
532 > one writes "binds bn(p) in t", which variant of the "binds" keyword would one |
|
533 > use: "binds", "binds(set)", or "binds(set+)"? Does it make any difference, |
|
534 > considering that a pattern can have multiple occurrences of a name in binding |
|
535 > position? It would be interesting if you could explain how you would handle |
|
536 > this example. |
|
537 |
|
538 You can write |
|
539 |
|
540 binds bn(p) in t, |
|
541 binds(set) bn(p) in t, |
|
542 binds(set+) bn(p) in t |
|
543 |
|
544 |
|
545 > p.15, just before section 5, I note that the completion process does *not* |
|
546 > produce any clause of the form "binds ... in x" (in the Lam case). One could |
|
547 > have expected it to produce "binds x in x", for instance. One could imagine |
|
548 > that, for *every* constructor argument t, there is a clause of the |
|
549 > form "binds |
|
550 > .. in t". Here, you adopt a different approach: you seem to be partitioning |
|
551 > the constructor arguments in two categories, the "terms" (which after |
|
552 > completion appear in the right-hand side of exactly one "binds" clause) and |
|
553 > the "binders" (which appear in the left-hand side of at least one "binds" |
|
554 > clause). Please clarify whether this is indeed the case. (You have |
|
555 > presented a |
|
556 > series of data type definitions that you forbid, but in the end, you should |
|
557 > present a succinct summary of what is allowed.) Also, I seem to understand |
|
558 > that the following definition is forbidden: |
|
559 > |
|
560 > nominal_datatype trm = |
|
561 > | Foo t1::trm t2::trm binds bn(t1) in t2, binds bn(t2) in t1 |
|
562 > |
|
563 > (for some definition of "bn"). This would be forbidden because t1 and t2 are |
|
564 > used both as "terms" and as "binders" (both on the left-hand and right-hand |
|
565 > side of a "binds" clause). As far as I can see, however, you have not |
|
566 > explicitly forbidden this situation. So, is it forbidden or allowed? Please |
|
567 > clarify. |
|
568 |
|
569 It is disallowed. We clarified the text. |
|
570 |
|
571 > p.17, "for each of the arguments we calculate the free atoms as |
|
572 > follows": this |
|
573 > definition relies on the fact that "rhs" must be of a specific *syntactic* |
|
574 > form (unions of expressions of the form "constant set" or "recursive call"). |
|
575 > For instance, "rhs" cannot contain the expression "my_empty_set z_i", where |
|
576 > "my_empty_set" is a user-defined function that always returns the empty set; |
|
577 > otherwise the third bullet would apply and we would end up considering "z_i" |
|
578 > as neither free nor bound. You have mentioned near the top of page 15 that |
|
579 > binding functions "can only return" certain results. You should clarify that |
|
580 > you are not restricting just *the values* that these functions can |
|
581 > return, but |
|
582 > the *syntactic form* of these functions. |
|
583 |
|
584 Fixed. |
|
585 |
|
586 > p.23, "We call these conditions as": not really grammatical. |
|
587 |
|
588 Fixed. |
|
589 |
|
590 > p.23, "cases lemmas": I suppose this means an elimination principle? |
|
591 |
|
592 Yes. |
|
593 |
|
594 > p.23, "Note that for the term constructors" -> "constructor" |
|
595 |
|
596 Fixed. |
|
597 |
|
598 > p.26, "avoid, or being fresh for" -> "avoid, or are fresh for" |
|
599 |
|
600 Fixed. |
|
601 |
|
602 > p.30, "Second, it covers cases of binders depending on other binders, |
|
603 > which just do no not make sense [...]". I am curious why the designers |
|
604 > of Ott thought that these cases make sense and you don't. Perhaps this |
|
605 > point would deserve an example and a deeper discussion? |
|
606 |
|
607 We have added more comments why such binders would not make sense |
|
608 for alpha-equated terms (fa-functions would not lift). We do not |
|
609 know why Ott allows them - probably because they do not establish |
|
610 a reasoning infrastructure for alpha-equated terms. |
|
611 |
|
612 > p.32, "It remains to be seen whether properties like [...] allow us |
|
613 > to support more interesting binding functions." Could you clarify |
|
614 > what you mean? Do you mean (perhaps) that fa_bn(x) could be defined |
|
615 > as fa_ty(x) \ bn(x), regardless of the definition of bn(x), instead |
|
616 > of by induction over x? Do you mean something else? |
|
617 |
|
618 Yes. |
|
619 |
|