383 |
383 |
384 |
384 |
385 section {* General Binders *} |
385 section {* General Binders *} |
386 |
386 |
387 text {* |
387 text {* |
388 In order to keep our work manageable we give need to give definitions |
388 In Nominal Isabelle the user is expected to write down a specification of a |
389 and perform proofs inside Isabelle wherever possible, as opposed to write |
389 term-calculus and a reasoning infrastructure is then automatically derived |
390 custom ML-code that generates them for each |
390 from this specifcation (remember that Nominal Isabelle is a definitional |
391 instance of a term-calculus. To this end we will first consider pairs |
391 extension of Isabelle/HOL and cannot introduce new axioms). |
392 |
392 |
393 \begin{equation}\label{three} |
393 |
394 \mbox{@{text "(as, x) :: (atom set) \<times> \<beta>"}} |
394 In order to keep our work manageable, we will wherever possible state |
395 \end{equation} |
395 definitions and perform proofs inside Isabelle, as opposed to write custom |
396 |
396 ML-code that generates them for each instance of a term-calculus. To that |
397 \noindent |
397 end, we will consider pairs @{text "(as, x)"} of type @{text "(atom set) \<times> \<beta>"}. |
398 consisting of a set of atoms and an object of generic type. These pairs |
398 These pairs are intended to represent the abstraction, or binding, of the set $as$ |
399 are intended to represent the abstraction or binding of the set $as$ |
399 in the body $x$. |
400 in the body $x$ (similarly to type-schemes given in \eqref{tysch}). |
400 |
401 |
401 The first question we have to answer is when the pairs $(as, x)$ and $(bs, y)$ are |
402 The first question we have to answer is when we should consider pairs such as |
402 alpha-equivalent? (At the moment we are interested in |
403 $(as, x)$ and $(bs, y)$ as alpha-equivalent? (At the moment we are interested in |
|
404 the notion of alpha-equivalence that is \emph{not} preserved by adding |
403 the notion of alpha-equivalence that is \emph{not} preserved by adding |
405 vacuous binders.) To answer this we identify four conditions: {\it i)} given |
404 vacuous binders.) To answer this, we identify four conditions: {\it i)} given |
406 a free-variable function of type \mbox{@{text "fv :: \<beta> \<Rightarrow> atom set"}}, then $x$ and $y$ |
405 a free-variable function $\fv$ of type \mbox{@{text "\<beta> \<Rightarrow> atom set"}}, then $x$ and $y$ |
407 need to have the same set of free variables; moreover there must be a permutation, |
406 need to have the same set of free variables; moreover there must be a permutation, |
408 $p$ that {\it ii)} leaves the free variables $x$ and $y$ unchanged, |
407 $p$ so that {\it ii)} it leaves the free variables $x$ and $y$ unchanged, |
409 but {\it iii)} ``moves'' their bound names so that we obtain modulo a relation, |
408 but {\it iii)} ``moves'' their bound names such that we obtain modulo a relation, |
410 say \mbox{@{text "_ R _"}}, two equal terms. We also require {\it iv)} that $p$ makes |
409 say \mbox{@{text "_ R _"}}, two equal terms. We also require {\it iv)} that $p$ makes |
411 the abstracted sets $as$ and $bs$ equal (since at the moment we do not want |
410 the abstracted sets $as$ and $bs$ equal. The requirements {\it i)} to {\it iv)} can |
412 that the sets $as$ and $bs$ differ on vacuous binders). These requirements can |
411 be stated formally as follows: |
413 be stated formally as follows |
|
414 % |
412 % |
415 \begin{equation}\label{alphaset} |
413 \begin{equation}\label{alphaset} |
416 \begin{array}{@ {\hspace{10mm}}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l} |
414 \begin{array}{@ {\hspace{10mm}}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l} |
417 \multicolumn{2}{l}{(as, x) \approx_{set}^{\fv, R, p} (bs, y) \;\dn\hspace{30mm}\;}\\[1mm] |
415 \multicolumn{2}{l}{(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}_{set}^{\fv, R, p} (bs, y) \;\dn\hspace{30mm}\;}\\[1mm] |
418 & @{text "fv(x) - as = fv(y) - bs"}\\ |
416 & @{text "fv(x) - as = fv(y) - bs"}\\ |
419 \wedge & @{text "fv(x) - as #* p"}\\ |
417 \wedge & @{text "fv(x) - as #* p"}\\ |
420 \wedge & @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"}\\ |
418 \wedge & @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"}\\ |
421 \wedge & @{text "(p \<bullet> as) = bs"}\\ |
419 \wedge & @{text "(p \<bullet> as) = bs"}\\ |
422 \end{array} |
420 \end{array} |
423 \end{equation} |
421 \end{equation} |
424 |
422 |
425 \noindent |
423 \noindent |
426 Alpha equivalence between such pairs is then the relation with the additional |
424 Note that this relation is dependent on $p$. Alpha-equivalence is then the relation where |
427 existential quantification over $p$. Note that this relation is additionally |
425 we existentially quantify over this $p$. |
428 dependent on the free-variable function $\fv$ and the relation $R$. The reason |
426 Also note that the relation is dependent on a free-variable function $\fv$ and a relation |
429 for this generality is that we want to use $\approx_{set}$ for both ``raw'' terms |
427 $R$. The reason for this extra generality is that we will use $\approx_{set}$ for both |
430 and alpha-equated terms. In the latter case, $R$ can be replaced by equality $(op =)$ and |
428 ``raw'' terms and alpha-equated terms. In the latter case, $R$ will be replaced by |
431 we are going to prove that $\fv$ will be equal to the support of $x$ and $y$. |
429 equality $(op =)$ and we are going to prove that $\fv$ will be equal to the support |
|
430 of $x$ and $y$. To have these parameters means, however, we can derive properties about |
|
431 them generically. |
432 |
432 |
433 The definition in \eqref{alphaset} does not make any distinction between the |
433 The definition in \eqref{alphaset} does not make any distinction between the |
434 order of abstracted variables. If we do want this then we can define alpha-equivalence |
434 order of abstracted variables. If we want this, then we can define alpha-equivalence |
435 for pairs of the form \mbox{@{text "(as, x) :: (atom list) \<times> \<beta>"}} by |
435 for pairs of the form \mbox{@{text "(as, x)"}} with type @{text "(atom list) \<times> \<beta>"} |
|
436 as follows |
436 % |
437 % |
437 \begin{equation}\label{alphalist} |
438 \begin{equation}\label{alphalist} |
438 \begin{array}{@ {\hspace{10mm}}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l} |
439 \begin{array}{@ {\hspace{10mm}}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l} |
439 \multicolumn{2}{l}{(as, x) \approx_{list}^{\fv, R, p} (bs, y) \;\dn\hspace{30mm}\;}\\[1mm] |
440 \multicolumn{2}{l}{(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}_{list}^{\fv, R, p} (bs, y) \;\dn\hspace{30mm}\;}\\[1mm] |
440 & @{text "fv(x) - (set as) = fv(y) - (set bs)"}\\ |
441 & @{text "fv(x) - (set as) = fv(y) - (set bs)"}\\ |
441 \wedge & @{text "fv(x) - (set as) #* p"}\\ |
442 \wedge & @{text "fv(x) - (set as) #* p"}\\ |
442 \wedge & @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"}\\ |
443 \wedge & @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"}\\ |
443 \wedge & @{text "(p \<bullet> as) = bs"}\\ |
444 \wedge & @{text "(p \<bullet> as) = bs"}\\ |
444 \end{array} |
445 \end{array} |
446 |
447 |
447 \noindent |
448 \noindent |
448 where $set$ is just the function that coerces a list of atoms into a set of atoms. |
449 where $set$ is just the function that coerces a list of atoms into a set of atoms. |
449 |
450 |
450 If we do not want to make any difference between the order of binders and |
451 If we do not want to make any difference between the order of binders and |
451 allow vacuous binders, then we just need to drop the fourth condition in \eqref{alphaset} |
452 also allow vacuous binders, then we keep sets of binders, but drop the fourth |
452 and define |
453 condition in \eqref{alphaset}: |
453 % |
454 % |
454 \begin{equation}\label{alphaset} |
455 \begin{equation}\label{alphares} |
455 \begin{array}{@ {\hspace{10mm}}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l} |
456 \begin{array}{@ {\hspace{10mm}}r@ {\hspace{2mm}}l} |
456 \multicolumn{2}{l}{(as, x) \approx_{res}^{\fv, R, p} (bs, y) \;\dn\hspace{30mm}\;}\\[1mm] |
457 \multicolumn{2}{l}{(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}_{res}^{\fv, R, p} (bs, y) \;\dn\hspace{30mm}\;}\\[1mm] |
457 & @{text "fv(x) - as = fv(y) - bs"}\\ |
458 & @{text "fv(x) - as = fv(y) - bs"}\\ |
458 \wedge & @{text "fv(x) - as #* p"}\\ |
459 \wedge & @{text "fv(x) - as #* p"}\\ |
459 \wedge & @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"}\\ |
460 \wedge & @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"}\\ |
460 \end{array} |
461 \end{array} |
461 \end{equation} |
462 \end{equation} |
462 |
463 |
463 To get a feeling how these definitions pan out in practise consider the case of |
464 \begin{exmple}\rm |
464 abstracting names over types (like in type-schemes). For this we set $R$ to be |
465 It might be useful to consider some examples for how these definitions pan out in practise. |
465 the equality and for $\fv(T)$ we define |
466 For this consider the case of abstracting a set of variables over types (as in type-schemes). |
|
467 We set $R$ to be the equality and for $\fv(T)$ we define |
466 |
468 |
467 \begin{center} |
469 \begin{center} |
468 $\fv(x) = \{x\} \qquad \fv(T_1 \rightarrow T_2) = \fv(T_1) \cup \fv(T_2)$ |
470 $\fv(x) = \{x\} \qquad \fv(T_1 \rightarrow T_2) = \fv(T_1) \cup \fv(T_2)$ |
469 \end{center} |
471 \end{center} |
470 |
472 |
471 \noindent |
473 \noindent |
472 Now reacall the examples in \eqref{ex1}, \eqref{ex2} and \eqref{ex3}: it can be easily |
474 Now recall the examples shown in \eqref{ex1}, \eqref{ex2} and \eqref{ex3}. It can be easily |
473 checked that @{text "({x,y}, x \<rightarrow> y)"} and |
475 checked that @{text "({x, y}, x \<rightarrow> y)"} and |
474 @{text "({y,x}, y \<rightarrow> x)"} are equal according to $\approx_{set}$ and $\approx_{ref}$ by taking $p$ to |
476 @{text "({y, x}, y \<rightarrow> x)"} are equal according to $\approx_{set}$ and $\approx_{res}$ by taking $p$ to |
475 be the swapping @{text "(x \<rightleftharpoons> y)"}; but assuming @{text "x \<noteq> y"} then for instance |
477 be the swapping @{term "(x \<rightleftharpoons> y)"}. In case of @{text "x \<noteq> y"} then |
476 $([x,y], x \rightarrow y) \not\approx_{list} ([y,x], x \rightarrow y)$ since there is no permutation that |
478 $([x, y], x \rightarrow y) \not\approx_{list} ([y,x], x \rightarrow y)$ since there is no permutation that |
477 makes the lists @{text "[x,y]"} and @{text "[y,x]"} equal, but leaves the type \mbox{@{text "x \<rightarrow> y"}} |
479 makes the lists @{text "[x, y]"} and @{text "[y, x]"} equal, and in addition leaves the |
478 unchanged. |
480 type \mbox{@{text "x \<rightarrow> y"}} unchanged. Again if @{text "x \<noteq> y"}, we have that |
|
481 $(\{x\}, x) \approx_{res} (\{x,y\}, x)$ by taking $p$ to be the identity permutation. |
|
482 However $(\{x\}, x) \not\approx_{set} (\{x,y\}, x)$ since there is no permutation that makes |
|
483 the sets $\{x\}$ and $\{x,y\}$ equal (similarly for $\approx_{list}$). |
|
484 \end{exmple} |
|
485 |
|
486 \noindent |
|
487 Let $\star$ range over $\{set, res, list\}$. We prove next under which |
|
488 conditions the $\approx\hspace{0.05mm}_\star^{\fv, R, p}$ are equivalence |
|
489 relations and equivariant: |
|
490 |
|
491 \begin{lemma} |
|
492 {\it i)} Given the fact that $x\;R\;x$ holds, then |
|
493 $(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, 0}_\star (as, x)$. {\it ii)} Given |
|
494 that @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"} implies @{text "(-p \<bullet> y) R x"}, then |
|
495 $(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, p}_\star (bs, y)$ implies |
|
496 $(bs, y) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, - p}_\star (as, x)$. {\it iii)} Given |
|
497 that @{text "(p \<bullet> x) R y"} and @{text "(q \<bullet> y) R z"} implies |
|
498 @{text "((q + p) \<bullet> x) R z"}, then $(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, p}_\star (bs, y)$ |
|
499 and $(bs, y) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, q}_\star (cs, z)$ implies |
|
500 $(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, q + p}_\star (cs, z)$. Given |
|
501 @{text "(q \<bullet> x) R y"} implies @{text "(p \<bullet> (q \<bullet> x)) R (p \<bullet> y)"} and |
|
502 @{text "p \<bullet> (fv x) = fv (p \<bullet> x)"} then @{text "p \<bullet> (fv y) = fv (p \<bullet> y)"}, then |
|
503 $(as, x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, q}_\star (bs, y)$ implies |
|
504 $(p \;\isasymbullet\; as, p \;\isasymbullet\; x) \approx\hspace{0.05mm}^{\fv, R, q}_\star |
|
505 (p \;\isasymbullet\; bs, p \;\isasymbullet\; y)$. |
|
506 \end{lemma} |
|
507 |
|
508 \begin{proof} |
|
509 All properties are by unfolding the definitions and simple calculations. |
|
510 \end{proof} |
479 *} |
511 *} |
480 |
512 |
481 section {* Alpha-Equivalence and Free Variables *} |
513 section {* Alpha-Equivalence and Free Variables *} |
482 |
514 |
483 text {* |
515 text {* |