1 |
|
2 theory Tutorial3s |
|
3 imports Lambda |
|
4 begin |
|
5 |
|
6 section {* Formalising Barendregt's Proof of the Substitution Lemma *} |
|
7 |
|
8 text {* |
|
9 The substitution lemma is another theorem where the variable |
|
10 convention plays a crucial role. |
|
11 |
|
12 Barendregt's proof of this lemma needs in the variable case a |
|
13 case distinction. One way to do this in Isar is to use blocks. |
|
14 A block consist of some assumptions and reasoning steps |
|
15 enclosed in curly braces, like |
|
16 |
|
17 { \<dots> |
|
18 have "statement" |
|
19 have "last_statement_in_the_block" |
|
20 } |
|
21 |
|
22 Such a block may contain local assumptions like |
|
23 |
|
24 { assume "A" |
|
25 assume "B" |
|
26 \<dots> |
|
27 have "C" by \<dots> |
|
28 } |
|
29 |
|
30 Where "C" is the last have-statement in this block. The behaviour |
|
31 of such a block to the 'outside' is the implication |
|
32 |
|
33 A \<Longrightarrow> B \<Longrightarrow> C |
|
34 |
|
35 Now if we want to prove a property "smth" using the case-distinctions |
|
36 P1, P2 and P3 then we can use the following reasoning: |
|
37 |
|
38 { assume "P1" |
|
39 \<dots> |
|
40 have "smth" |
|
41 } |
|
42 moreover |
|
43 { assume "P2" |
|
44 \<dots> |
|
45 have "smth" |
|
46 } |
|
47 moreover |
|
48 { assume "P3" |
|
49 \<dots> |
|
50 have "smth" |
|
51 } |
|
52 ultimately have "smth" by blast |
|
53 |
|
54 The blocks establish the implications |
|
55 |
|
56 P1 \<Longrightarrow> smth |
|
57 P2 \<Longrightarrow> smth |
|
58 P3 \<Longrightarrow> smth |
|
59 |
|
60 If we know that P1, P2 and P3 cover all the cases, that is P1 \<or> P2 \<or> P3 |
|
61 holds, then we have 'ultimately' established the property "smth" |
|
62 |
|
63 *} |
|
64 |
|
65 subsection {* Two preliminary facts *} |
|
66 |
|
67 lemma forget: |
|
68 shows "atom x \<sharp> t \<Longrightarrow> t[x ::= s] = t" |
|
69 by (nominal_induct t avoiding: x s rule: lam.strong_induct) |
|
70 (auto simp add: lam.fresh fresh_at_base) |
|
71 |
|
72 lemma fresh_fact: |
|
73 assumes a: "atom z \<sharp> s" |
|
74 and b: "z = y \<or> atom z \<sharp> t" |
|
75 shows "atom z \<sharp> t[y ::= s]" |
|
76 using a b |
|
77 by (nominal_induct t avoiding: z y s rule: lam.strong_induct) |
|
78 (auto simp add: lam.fresh fresh_at_base) |
|
79 |
|
80 |
|
81 |
|
82 section {* EXERCISE 10 *} |
|
83 |
|
84 text {* |
|
85 Fill in the cases 1.2 and 1.3 and the equational reasoning |
|
86 in the lambda-case. |
|
87 *} |
|
88 |
|
89 lemma |
|
90 assumes a: "x \<noteq> y" |
|
91 and b: "atom x \<sharp> L" |
|
92 shows "M[x ::= N][y ::= L] = M[y ::= L][x ::= N[y ::= L]]" |
|
93 using a b |
|
94 proof (nominal_induct M avoiding: x y N L rule: lam.strong_induct) |
|
95 case (Var z) |
|
96 have a1: "x \<noteq> y" by fact |
|
97 have a2: "atom x \<sharp> L" by fact |
|
98 show "Var z[x::=N][y::=L] = Var z[y::=L][x::=N[y::=L]]" (is "?LHS = ?RHS") |
|
99 proof - |
|
100 { -- {* Case 1.1 *} |
|
101 assume c1: "z = x" |
|
102 have "(1)": "?LHS = N[y::=L]" using c1 by simp |
|
103 have "(2)": "?RHS = N[y::=L]" using c1 a1 by simp |
|
104 have "?LHS = ?RHS" using "(1)" "(2)" by simp |
|
105 } |
|
106 moreover |
|
107 { -- {* Case 1.2 *} |
|
108 assume c2: "z = y" "z \<noteq> x" |
|
109 have "(1)": "?LHS = L" using c2 by simp |
|
110 have "(2)": "?RHS = L[x::=N[y::=L]]" using c2 by simp |
|
111 have "(3)": "L[x::=N[y::=L]] = L" using a2 forget by simp |
|
112 have "?LHS = ?RHS" using "(1)" "(2)" "(3)" by simp |
|
113 } |
|
114 moreover |
|
115 { -- {* Case 1.3 *} |
|
116 assume c3: "z \<noteq> x" "z \<noteq> y" |
|
117 have "(1)": "?LHS = Var z" using c3 by simp |
|
118 have "(2)": "?RHS = Var z" using c3 by simp |
|
119 have "?LHS = ?RHS" using "(1)" "(2)" by simp |
|
120 } |
|
121 ultimately show "?LHS = ?RHS" by blast |
|
122 qed |
|
123 next |
|
124 case (Lam z M1) -- {* case 2: lambdas *} |
|
125 have ih: "\<lbrakk>x \<noteq> y; atom x \<sharp> L\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> M1[x ::= N][y ::= L] = M1[y ::= L][x ::= N[y ::= L]]" by fact |
|
126 have a1: "x \<noteq> y" by fact |
|
127 have a2: "atom x \<sharp> L" by fact |
|
128 have fs: "atom z \<sharp> x" "atom z \<sharp> y" "atom z \<sharp> N" "atom z \<sharp> L" by fact+ -- {* !! *} |
|
129 then have b: "atom z \<sharp> N[y::=L]" by (simp add: fresh_fact) |
|
130 show "(Lam [z].M1)[x ::= N][y ::= L] = (Lam [z].M1)[y ::= L][x ::= N[y ::= L]]" (is "?LHS=?RHS") |
|
131 proof - |
|
132 have "?LHS = Lam [z].(M1[x ::= N][y ::= L])" using fs by simp |
|
133 also have "\<dots> = Lam [z].(M1[y ::= L][x ::= N[y ::= L]])" using ih a1 a2 by simp |
|
134 also have "\<dots> = (Lam [z].(M1[y ::= L]))[x ::= N[y ::= L]]" using b fs by simp |
|
135 also have "\<dots> = ?RHS" using fs by simp |
|
136 finally show "?LHS = ?RHS" by simp |
|
137 qed |
|
138 next |
|
139 case (App M1 M2) -- {* case 3: applications *} |
|
140 then show "(App M1 M2)[x::=N][y::=L] = (App M1 M2)[y::=L][x::=N[y::=L]]" by simp |
|
141 qed |
|
142 |
|
143 text {* |
|
144 Again the strong induction principle enables Isabelle to find |
|
145 the proof of the substitution lemma completely automatically. |
|
146 *} |
|
147 |
|
148 lemma substitution_lemma_version: |
|
149 assumes asm: "x \<noteq> y" "atom x \<sharp> L" |
|
150 shows "M[x::=N][y::=L] = M[y::=L][x::=N[y::=L]]" |
|
151 using asm |
|
152 by (nominal_induct M avoiding: x y N L rule: lam.strong_induct) |
|
153 (auto simp add: fresh_fact forget) |
|
154 |
|
155 subsection {* MINI EXERCISE *} |
|
156 |
|
157 text {* |
|
158 Compare and contrast Barendregt's reasoning and the |
|
159 formalised proofs. |
|
160 *} |
|
161 |
|
162 end |
|