diff -r 47179a172c54 -r 16af5b8bd285 thys/Journal/Paper.thy --- /dev/null Thu Jan 01 00:00:00 1970 +0000 +++ b/thys/Journal/Paper.thy Sun Feb 26 23:46:22 2017 +0000 @@ -0,0 +1,1260 @@ +(*<*) +theory Paper +imports + "../Lexer" + "../Simplifying" + "../Sulzmann" + "~~/src/HOL/Library/LaTeXsugar" +begin + +declare [[show_question_marks = false]] + +abbreviation + "der_syn r c \ der c r" + +abbreviation + "ders_syn r s \ ders s r" + +notation (latex output) + If ("(\<^raw:\textrm{>if\<^raw:}> (_)/ \<^raw:\textrm{>then\<^raw:}> (_)/ \<^raw:\textrm{>else\<^raw:}> (_))" 10) and + Cons ("_\<^raw:\mbox{$\,$}>::\<^raw:\mbox{$\,$}>_" [75,73] 73) and + + ZERO ("\<^bold>0" 78) and + ONE ("\<^bold>1" 78) and + CHAR ("_" [1000] 80) and + ALT ("_ + _" [77,77] 78) and + SEQ ("_ \ _" [77,77] 78) and + STAR ("_\<^sup>\" [1000] 78) and + + val.Void ("'(')" 1000) and + val.Char ("Char _" [1000] 78) and + val.Left ("Left _" [79] 78) and + val.Right ("Right _" [1000] 78) and + val.Seq ("Seq _ _" [79,79] 78) and + val.Stars ("Stars _" [79] 78) and + + L ("L'(_')" [10] 78) and + der_syn ("_\\_" [79, 1000] 76) and + ders_syn ("_\\_" [79, 1000] 76) and + flat ("|_|" [75] 74) and + Sequ ("_ @ _" [78,77] 63) and + injval ("inj _ _ _" [79,77,79] 76) and + mkeps ("mkeps _" [79] 76) and + length ("len _" [73] 73) and + + Prf ("_ : _" [75,75] 75) and + Posix ("'(_, _') \ _" [63,75,75] 75) and + + lexer ("lexer _ _" [78,78] 77) and + F_RIGHT ("F\<^bsub>Right\<^esub> _") and + F_LEFT ("F\<^bsub>Left\<^esub> _") and + F_ALT ("F\<^bsub>Alt\<^esub> _ _") and + F_SEQ1 ("F\<^bsub>Seq1\<^esub> _ _") and + F_SEQ2 ("F\<^bsub>Seq2\<^esub> _ _") and + F_SEQ ("F\<^bsub>Seq\<^esub> _ _") and + simp_SEQ ("simp\<^bsub>Seq\<^esub> _ _" [1000, 1000] 1) and + simp_ALT ("simp\<^bsub>Alt\<^esub> _ _" [1000, 1000] 1) and + slexer ("lexer\<^sup>+" 1000) and + + ValOrd ("_ >\<^bsub>_\<^esub> _" [77,77,77] 77) and + ValOrdEq ("_ \\<^bsub>_\<^esub> _" [77,77,77] 77) + +definition + "match r s \ nullable (ders s r)" + +(* +comments not implemented + +p9. The condtion "not exists s3 s4..." appears often enough (in particular in +the proof of Lemma 3) to warrant a definition. + +*) + +(*>*) + +section {* Introduction *} + + +text {* + +Brzozowski \cite{Brzozowski1964} introduced the notion of the {\em +derivative} @{term "der c r"} of a regular expression @{text r} w.r.t.\ a +character~@{text c}, and showed that it gave a simple solution to the +problem of matching a string @{term s} with a regular expression @{term r}: +if the derivative of @{term r} w.r.t.\ (in succession) all the characters of +the string matches the empty string, then @{term r} matches @{term s} (and +{\em vice versa}). The derivative has the property (which may almost be +regarded as its specification) that, for every string @{term s} and regular +expression @{term r} and character @{term c}, one has @{term "cs \ L(r)"} if +and only if \mbox{@{term "s \ L(der c r)"}}. The beauty of Brzozowski's +derivatives is that they are neatly expressible in any functional language, +and easily definable and reasoned about in theorem provers---the definitions +just consist of inductive datatypes and simple recursive functions. A +mechanised correctness proof of Brzozowski's matcher in for example HOL4 +has been mentioned by Owens and Slind~\cite{Owens2008}. Another one in Isabelle/HOL is part +of the work by Krauss and Nipkow \cite{Krauss2011}. And another one in Coq is given +by Coquand and Siles \cite{Coquand2012}. + +If a regular expression matches a string, then in general there is more than +one way of how the string is matched. There are two commonly used +disambiguation strategies to generate a unique answer: one is called GREEDY +matching \cite{Frisch2004} and the other is POSIX +matching~\cite{Kuklewicz,Sulzmann2014,Vansummeren2006}. For example consider +the string @{term xy} and the regular expression \mbox{@{term "STAR (ALT +(ALT x y) xy)"}}. Either the string can be matched in two `iterations' by +the single letter-regular expressions @{term x} and @{term y}, or directly +in one iteration by @{term xy}. The first case corresponds to GREEDY +matching, which first matches with the left-most symbol and only matches the +next symbol in case of a mismatch (this is greedy in the sense of preferring +instant gratification to delayed repletion). The second case is POSIX +matching, which prefers the longest match. + +In the context of lexing, where an input string needs to be split up into a +sequence of tokens, POSIX is the more natural disambiguation strategy for +what programmers consider basic syntactic building blocks in their programs. +These building blocks are often specified by some regular expressions, say +@{text "r\<^bsub>key\<^esub>"} and @{text "r\<^bsub>id\<^esub>"} for recognising keywords and +identifiers, respectively. There are two underlying (informal) rules behind +tokenising a string in a POSIX fashion according to a collection of regular +expressions: + +\begin{itemize} +\item[$\bullet$] \emph{The Longest Match Rule} (or \emph{``maximal munch rule''}): +The longest initial substring matched by any regular expression is taken as +next token.\smallskip + +\item[$\bullet$] \emph{Priority Rule:} +For a particular longest initial substring, the first regular expression +that can match determines the token. +\end{itemize} + +\noindent Consider for example a regular expression @{text "r\<^bsub>key\<^esub>"} for recognising keywords +such as @{text "if"}, @{text "then"} and so on; and @{text "r\<^bsub>id\<^esub>"} +recognising identifiers (say, a single character followed by +characters or numbers). Then we can form the regular expression +@{text "(r\<^bsub>key\<^esub> + r\<^bsub>id\<^esub>)\<^sup>\"} and use POSIX matching to tokenise strings, +say @{text "iffoo"} and @{text "if"}. For @{text "iffoo"} we obtain +by the Longest Match Rule a single identifier token, not a keyword +followed by an identifier. For @{text "if"} we obtain by the Priority +Rule a keyword token, not an identifier token---even if @{text "r\<^bsub>id\<^esub>"} +matches also. + +One limitation of Brzozowski's matcher is that it only generates a +YES/NO answer for whether a string is being matched by a regular +expression. Sulzmann and Lu~\cite{Sulzmann2014} extended this matcher +to allow generation not just of a YES/NO answer but of an actual +matching, called a [lexical] {\em value}. They give a simple algorithm +to calculate a value that appears to be the value associated with +POSIX matching. The challenge then is to specify that value, in an +algorithm-independent fashion, and to show that Sulzmann and Lu's +derivative-based algorithm does indeed calculate a value that is +correct according to the specification. + +The answer given by Sulzmann and Lu \cite{Sulzmann2014} is to define a +relation (called an ``order relation'') on the set of values of @{term +r}, and to show that (once a string to be matched is chosen) there is +a maximum element and that it is computed by their derivative-based +algorithm. This proof idea is inspired by work of Frisch and Cardelli +\cite{Frisch2004} on a GREEDY regular expression matching +algorithm. However, we were not able to establish transitivity and +totality for the ``order relation'' by Sulzmann and Lu. In Section +\ref{argu} we identify some inherent problems with their approach (of +which some of the proofs are not published in \cite{Sulzmann2014}); +perhaps more importantly, we give a simple inductive (and +algorithm-independent) definition of what we call being a {\em POSIX +value} for a regular expression @{term r} and a string @{term s}; we +show that the algorithm computes such a value and that such a value is +unique. Our proofs are both done by hand and checked in Isabelle/HOL. The +experience of doing our proofs has been that this mechanical checking +was absolutely essential: this subject area has hidden snares. This +was also noted by Kuklewicz \cite{Kuklewicz} who found that nearly all +POSIX matching implementations are ``buggy'' \cite[Page +203]{Sulzmann2014} and by Grathwohl et al \cite[Page 36]{CrashCourse2014} +who wrote: + +\begin{quote} +\it{}``The POSIX strategy is more complicated than the greedy because of +the dependence on information about the length of matched strings in the +various subexpressions.'' +\end{quote} + +%\footnote{The relation @{text "\\<^bsub>r\<^esub>"} defined by Sulzmann and Lu \cite{Sulzmann2014} +%is a relation on the +%values for the regular expression @{term r}; but it only holds between +%@{term "v\<^sub>1"} and @{term "v\<^sub>2"} in cases where @{term "v\<^sub>1"} and @{term "v\<^sub>2"} have +%the same flattening (underlying string). So a counterexample to totality is +%given by taking two values @{term "v\<^sub>1"} and @{term "v\<^sub>2"} for @{term r} that +%have different flattenings (see Section~\ref{posixsec}). A different +%relation @{text "\\<^bsub>r,s\<^esub>"} on the set of values for @{term r} +%with flattening @{term s} is definable by the same approach, and is indeed +%total; but that is not what Proposition 1 of \cite{Sulzmann2014} does.} + + +\noindent {\bf Contributions:} We have implemented in Isabelle/HOL the +derivative-based regular expression matching algorithm of +Sulzmann and Lu \cite{Sulzmann2014}. We have proved the correctness of this +algorithm according to our specification of what a POSIX value is (inspired +by work of Vansummeren \cite{Vansummeren2006}). Sulzmann +and Lu sketch in \cite{Sulzmann2014} an informal correctness proof: but to +us it contains unfillable gaps.\footnote{An extended version of +\cite{Sulzmann2014} is available at the website of its first author; this +extended version already includes remarks in the appendix that their +informal proof contains gaps, and possible fixes are not fully worked out.} +Our specification of a POSIX value consists of a simple inductive definition +that given a string and a regular expression uniquely determines this value. +Derivatives as calculated by Brzozowski's method are usually more complex +regular expressions than the initial one; various optimisations are +possible. We prove the correctness when simplifications of @{term "ALT ZERO +r"}, @{term "ALT r ZERO"}, @{term "SEQ ONE r"} and @{term "SEQ r ONE"} to +@{term r} are applied. + +*} + +section {* Preliminaries *} + +text {* \noindent Strings in Isabelle/HOL are lists of characters with the +empty string being represented by the empty list, written @{term "[]"}, and +list-cons being written as @{term "DUMMY # DUMMY"}. Often we use the usual +bracket notation for lists also for strings; for example a string consisting +of just a single character @{term c} is written @{term "[c]"}. By using the +type @{type char} for characters we have a supply of finitely many +characters roughly corresponding to the ASCII character set. Regular +expressions are defined as usual as the elements of the following inductive +datatype: + + \begin{center} + @{text "r :="} + @{const "ZERO"} $\mid$ + @{const "ONE"} $\mid$ + @{term "CHAR c"} $\mid$ + @{term "ALT r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2"} $\mid$ + @{term "SEQ r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2"} $\mid$ + @{term "STAR r"} + \end{center} + + \noindent where @{const ZERO} stands for the regular expression that does + not match any string, @{const ONE} for the regular expression that matches + only the empty string and @{term c} for matching a character literal. The + language of a regular expression is also defined as usual by the + recursive function @{term L} with the six clauses: + + \begin{center} + \begin{tabular}{l@ {\hspace{3mm}}rcl} + (1) & @{thm (lhs) L.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) L.simps(1)}\\ + (2) & @{thm (lhs) L.simps(2)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) L.simps(2)}\\ + (3) & @{thm (lhs) L.simps(3)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) L.simps(3)}\\ + \end{tabular} + \hspace{14mm} + \begin{tabular}{l@ {\hspace{3mm}}rcl} + (4) & @{thm (lhs) L.simps(4)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) L.simps(4)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]}\\ + (5) & @{thm (lhs) L.simps(5)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) L.simps(5)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]}\\ + (6) & @{thm (lhs) L.simps(6)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) L.simps(6)}\\ + \end{tabular} + \end{center} + + \noindent In clause (4) we use the operation @{term "DUMMY ;; + DUMMY"} for the concatenation of two languages (it is also list-append for + strings). We use the star-notation for regular expressions and for + languages (in the last clause above). The star for languages is defined + inductively by two clauses: @{text "(i)"} the empty string being in + the star of a language and @{text "(ii)"} if @{term "s\<^sub>1"} is in a + language and @{term "s\<^sub>2"} in the star of this language, then also @{term + "s\<^sub>1 @ s\<^sub>2"} is in the star of this language. It will also be convenient + to use the following notion of a \emph{semantic derivative} (or \emph{left + quotient}) of a language defined as + % + \begin{center} + @{thm Der_def}\;. + \end{center} + + \noindent + For semantic derivatives we have the following equations (for example + mechanically proved in \cite{Krauss2011}): + % + \begin{equation}\label{SemDer} + \begin{array}{lcl} + @{thm (lhs) Der_null} & \dn & @{thm (rhs) Der_null}\\ + @{thm (lhs) Der_empty} & \dn & @{thm (rhs) Der_empty}\\ + @{thm (lhs) Der_char} & \dn & @{thm (rhs) Der_char}\\ + @{thm (lhs) Der_union} & \dn & @{thm (rhs) Der_union}\\ + @{thm (lhs) Der_Sequ} & \dn & @{thm (rhs) Der_Sequ}\\ + @{thm (lhs) Der_star} & \dn & @{thm (rhs) Der_star} + \end{array} + \end{equation} + + + \noindent \emph{\Brz's derivatives} of regular expressions + \cite{Brzozowski1964} can be easily defined by two recursive functions: + the first is from regular expressions to booleans (implementing a test + when a regular expression can match the empty string), and the second + takes a regular expression and a character to a (derivative) regular + expression: + + \begin{center} + \begin{tabular}{lcl} + @{thm (lhs) nullable.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) nullable.simps(1)}\\ + @{thm (lhs) nullable.simps(2)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) nullable.simps(2)}\\ + @{thm (lhs) nullable.simps(3)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) nullable.simps(3)}\\ + @{thm (lhs) nullable.simps(4)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) nullable.simps(4)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]}\\ + @{thm (lhs) nullable.simps(5)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) nullable.simps(5)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]}\\ + @{thm (lhs) nullable.simps(6)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) nullable.simps(6)}\medskip\\ + + %\end{tabular} + %\end{center} + + %\begin{center} + %\begin{tabular}{lcl} + + @{thm (lhs) der.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) der.simps(1)}\\ + @{thm (lhs) der.simps(2)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) der.simps(2)}\\ + @{thm (lhs) der.simps(3)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) der.simps(3)}\\ + @{thm (lhs) der.simps(4)[of c "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) der.simps(4)[of c "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]}\\ + @{thm (lhs) der.simps(5)[of c "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) der.simps(5)[of c "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]}\\ + @{thm (lhs) der.simps(6)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) der.simps(6)} + \end{tabular} + \end{center} + + \noindent + We may extend this definition to give derivatives w.r.t.~strings: + + \begin{center} + \begin{tabular}{lcl} + @{thm (lhs) ders.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) ders.simps(1)}\\ + @{thm (lhs) ders.simps(2)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) ders.simps(2)}\\ + \end{tabular} + \end{center} + + \noindent Given the equations in \eqref{SemDer}, it is a relatively easy + exercise in mechanical reasoning to establish that + + \begin{proposition}\label{derprop}\mbox{}\\ + \begin{tabular}{ll} + @{text "(1)"} & @{thm (lhs) nullable_correctness} if and only if + @{thm (rhs) nullable_correctness}, and \\ + @{text "(2)"} & @{thm[mode=IfThen] der_correctness}. + \end{tabular} + \end{proposition} + + \noindent With this in place it is also very routine to prove that the + regular expression matcher defined as + % + \begin{center} + @{thm match_def} + \end{center} + + \noindent gives a positive answer if and only if @{term "s \ L r"}. + Consequently, this regular expression matching algorithm satisfies the + usual specification for regular expression matching. While the matcher + above calculates a provably correct YES/NO answer for whether a regular + expression matches a string or not, the novel idea of Sulzmann and Lu + \cite{Sulzmann2014} is to append another phase to this algorithm in order + to calculate a [lexical] value. We will explain the details next. + +*} + +section {* POSIX Regular Expression Matching\label{posixsec} *} + +text {* + + The clever idea by Sulzmann and Lu \cite{Sulzmann2014} is to define + values for encoding \emph{how} a regular expression matches a string + and then define a function on values that mirrors (but inverts) the + construction of the derivative on regular expressions. \emph{Values} + are defined as the inductive datatype + + \begin{center} + @{text "v :="} + @{const "Void"} $\mid$ + @{term "val.Char c"} $\mid$ + @{term "Left v"} $\mid$ + @{term "Right v"} $\mid$ + @{term "Seq v\<^sub>1 v\<^sub>2"} $\mid$ + @{term "Stars vs"} + \end{center} + + \noindent where we use @{term vs} to stand for a list of + values. (This is similar to the approach taken by Frisch and + Cardelli for GREEDY matching \cite{Frisch2004}, and Sulzmann and Lu + for POSIX matching \cite{Sulzmann2014}). The string underlying a + value can be calculated by the @{const flat} function, written + @{term "flat DUMMY"} and defined as: + + \begin{center} + \begin{tabular}[t]{lcl} + @{thm (lhs) flat.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) flat.simps(1)}\\ + @{thm (lhs) flat.simps(2)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) flat.simps(2)}\\ + @{thm (lhs) flat.simps(3)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) flat.simps(3)}\\ + @{thm (lhs) flat.simps(4)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) flat.simps(4)} + \end{tabular}\hspace{14mm} + \begin{tabular}[t]{lcl} + @{thm (lhs) flat.simps(5)[of "v\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>2"]} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) flat.simps(5)[of "v\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>2"]}\\ + @{thm (lhs) flat.simps(6)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) flat.simps(6)}\\ + @{thm (lhs) flat.simps(7)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) flat.simps(7)}\\ + \end{tabular} + \end{center} + + \noindent Sulzmann and Lu also define inductively an inhabitation relation + that associates values to regular expressions: + + \begin{center} + \begin{tabular}{c} + \\[-8mm] + @{thm[mode=Axiom] Prf.intros(4)} \qquad + @{thm[mode=Axiom] Prf.intros(5)[of "c"]}\\[4mm] + @{thm[mode=Rule] Prf.intros(2)[of "v\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]} \qquad + @{thm[mode=Rule] Prf.intros(3)[of "v\<^sub>2" "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]}\\[4mm] + @{thm[mode=Rule] Prf.intros(1)[of "v\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>2" "r\<^sub>2"]}\\[4mm] + @{thm[mode=Axiom] Prf.intros(6)[of "r"]} \qquad + @{thm[mode=Rule] Prf.intros(7)[of "v" "r" "vs"]} + \end{tabular} + \end{center} + + \noindent Note that no values are associated with the regular expression + @{term ZERO}, and that the only value associated with the regular + expression @{term ONE} is @{term Void}, pronounced (if one must) as @{text + "Void"}. It is routine to establish how values ``inhabiting'' a regular + expression correspond to the language of a regular expression, namely + + \begin{proposition} + @{thm L_flat_Prf} + \end{proposition} + + In general there is more than one value associated with a regular + expression. In case of POSIX matching the problem is to calculate the + unique value that satisfies the (informal) POSIX rules from the + Introduction. Graphically the POSIX value calculation algorithm by + Sulzmann and Lu can be illustrated by the picture in Figure~\ref{Sulz} + where the path from the left to the right involving @{term derivatives}/@{const + nullable} is the first phase of the algorithm (calculating successive + \Brz's derivatives) and @{const mkeps}/@{text inj}, the path from right to + left, the second phase. This picture shows the steps required when a + regular expression, say @{text "r\<^sub>1"}, matches the string @{term + "[a,b,c]"}. We first build the three derivatives (according to @{term a}, + @{term b} and @{term c}). We then use @{const nullable} to find out + whether the resulting derivative regular expression @{term "r\<^sub>4"} + can match the empty string. If yes, we call the function @{const mkeps} + that produces a value @{term "v\<^sub>4"} for how @{term "r\<^sub>4"} can + match the empty string (taking into account the POSIX constraints in case + there are several ways). This function is defined by the clauses: + +\begin{figure}[t] +\begin{center} +\begin{tikzpicture}[scale=2,node distance=1.3cm, + every node/.style={minimum size=6mm}] +\node (r1) {@{term "r\<^sub>1"}}; +\node (r2) [right=of r1]{@{term "r\<^sub>2"}}; +\draw[->,line width=1mm](r1)--(r2) node[above,midway] {@{term "der a DUMMY"}}; +\node (r3) [right=of r2]{@{term "r\<^sub>3"}}; +\draw[->,line width=1mm](r2)--(r3) node[above,midway] {@{term "der b DUMMY"}}; +\node (r4) [right=of r3]{@{term "r\<^sub>4"}}; +\draw[->,line width=1mm](r3)--(r4) node[above,midway] {@{term "der c DUMMY"}}; +\draw (r4) node[anchor=west] {\;\raisebox{3mm}{@{term nullable}}}; +\node (v4) [below=of r4]{@{term "v\<^sub>4"}}; +\draw[->,line width=1mm](r4) -- (v4); +\node (v3) [left=of v4] {@{term "v\<^sub>3"}}; +\draw[->,line width=1mm](v4)--(v3) node[below,midway] {@{text "inj r\<^sub>3 c"}}; +\node (v2) [left=of v3]{@{term "v\<^sub>2"}}; +\draw[->,line width=1mm](v3)--(v2) node[below,midway] {@{text "inj r\<^sub>2 b"}}; +\node (v1) [left=of v2] {@{term "v\<^sub>1"}}; +\draw[->,line width=1mm](v2)--(v1) node[below,midway] {@{text "inj r\<^sub>1 a"}}; +\draw (r4) node[anchor=north west] {\;\raisebox{-8mm}{@{term "mkeps"}}}; +\end{tikzpicture} +\end{center} +\mbox{}\\[-13mm] + +\caption{The two phases of the algorithm by Sulzmann \& Lu \cite{Sulzmann2014}, +matching the string @{term "[a,b,c]"}. The first phase (the arrows from +left to right) is \Brz's matcher building successive derivatives. If the +last regular expression is @{term nullable}, then the functions of the +second phase are called (the top-down and right-to-left arrows): first +@{term mkeps} calculates a value @{term "v\<^sub>4"} witnessing +how the empty string has been recognised by @{term "r\<^sub>4"}. After +that the function @{term inj} ``injects back'' the characters of the string into +the values. +\label{Sulz}} +\end{figure} + + \begin{center} + \begin{tabular}{lcl} + @{thm (lhs) mkeps.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) mkeps.simps(1)}\\ + @{thm (lhs) mkeps.simps(2)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) mkeps.simps(2)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]}\\ + @{thm (lhs) mkeps.simps(3)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) mkeps.simps(3)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]}\\ + @{thm (lhs) mkeps.simps(4)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) mkeps.simps(4)}\\ + \end{tabular} + \end{center} + + \noindent Note that this function needs only to be partially defined, + namely only for regular expressions that are nullable. In case @{const + nullable} fails, the string @{term "[a,b,c]"} cannot be matched by @{term + "r\<^sub>1"} and the null value @{term "None"} is returned. Note also how this function + makes some subtle choices leading to a POSIX value: for example if an + alternative regular expression, say @{term "ALT r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2"}, can + match the empty string and furthermore @{term "r\<^sub>1"} can match the + empty string, then we return a @{text Left}-value. The @{text + Right}-value will only be returned if @{term "r\<^sub>1"} cannot match the empty + string. + + The most interesting idea from Sulzmann and Lu \cite{Sulzmann2014} is + the construction of a value for how @{term "r\<^sub>1"} can match the + string @{term "[a,b,c]"} from the value how the last derivative, @{term + "r\<^sub>4"} in Fig.~\ref{Sulz}, can match the empty string. Sulzmann and + Lu achieve this by stepwise ``injecting back'' the characters into the + values thus inverting the operation of building derivatives, but on the level + of values. The corresponding function, called @{term inj}, takes three + arguments, a regular expression, a character and a value. For example in + the first (or right-most) @{term inj}-step in Fig.~\ref{Sulz} the regular + expression @{term "r\<^sub>3"}, the character @{term c} from the last + derivative step and @{term "v\<^sub>4"}, which is the value corresponding + to the derivative regular expression @{term "r\<^sub>4"}. The result is + the new value @{term "v\<^sub>3"}. The final result of the algorithm is + the value @{term "v\<^sub>1"}. The @{term inj} function is defined by recursion on regular + expressions and by analysing the shape of values (corresponding to + the derivative regular expressions). + % + \begin{center} + \begin{tabular}{l@ {\hspace{5mm}}lcl} + (1) & @{thm (lhs) injval.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) injval.simps(1)}\\ + (2) & @{thm (lhs) injval.simps(2)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2" "c" "v\<^sub>1"]} & $\dn$ & + @{thm (rhs) injval.simps(2)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2" "c" "v\<^sub>1"]}\\ + (3) & @{thm (lhs) injval.simps(3)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2" "c" "v\<^sub>2"]} & $\dn$ & + @{thm (rhs) injval.simps(3)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2" "c" "v\<^sub>2"]}\\ + (4) & @{thm (lhs) injval.simps(4)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2" "c" "v\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>2"]} & $\dn$ + & @{thm (rhs) injval.simps(4)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2" "c" "v\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>2"]}\\ + (5) & @{thm (lhs) injval.simps(5)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2" "c" "v\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>2"]} & $\dn$ + & @{thm (rhs) injval.simps(5)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2" "c" "v\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>2"]}\\ + (6) & @{thm (lhs) injval.simps(6)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2" "c" "v\<^sub>2"]} & $\dn$ + & @{thm (rhs) injval.simps(6)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2" "c" "v\<^sub>2"]}\\ + (7) & @{thm (lhs) injval.simps(7)[of "r" "c" "v" "vs"]} & $\dn$ + & @{thm (rhs) injval.simps(7)[of "r" "c" "v" "vs"]}\\ + \end{tabular} + \end{center} + + \noindent To better understand what is going on in this definition it + might be instructive to look first at the three sequence cases (clauses + (4)--(6)). In each case we need to construct an ``injected value'' for + @{term "SEQ r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2"}. This must be a value of the form @{term + "Seq DUMMY DUMMY"}\,. Recall the clause of the @{text derivative}-function + for sequence regular expressions: + + \begin{center} + @{thm (lhs) der.simps(5)[of c "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]} $\dn$ @{thm (rhs) der.simps(5)[of c "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]} + \end{center} + + \noindent Consider first the @{text "else"}-branch where the derivative is @{term + "SEQ (der c r\<^sub>1) r\<^sub>2"}. The corresponding value must therefore + be of the form @{term "Seq v\<^sub>1 v\<^sub>2"}, which matches the left-hand + side in clause~(4) of @{term inj}. In the @{text "if"}-branch the derivative is an + alternative, namely @{term "ALT (SEQ (der c r\<^sub>1) r\<^sub>2) (der c + r\<^sub>2)"}. This means we either have to consider a @{text Left}- or + @{text Right}-value. In case of the @{text Left}-value we know further it + must be a value for a sequence regular expression. Therefore the pattern + we match in the clause (5) is @{term "Left (Seq v\<^sub>1 v\<^sub>2)"}, + while in (6) it is just @{term "Right v\<^sub>2"}. One more interesting + point is in the right-hand side of clause (6): since in this case the + regular expression @{text "r\<^sub>1"} does not ``contribute'' to + matching the string, that means it only matches the empty string, we need to + call @{const mkeps} in order to construct a value for how @{term "r\<^sub>1"} + can match this empty string. A similar argument applies for why we can + expect in the left-hand side of clause (7) that the value is of the form + @{term "Seq v (Stars vs)"}---the derivative of a star is @{term "SEQ (der c r) + (STAR r)"}. Finally, the reason for why we can ignore the second argument + in clause (1) of @{term inj} is that it will only ever be called in cases + where @{term "c=d"}, but the usual linearity restrictions in patterns do + not allow us to build this constraint explicitly into our function + definition.\footnote{Sulzmann and Lu state this clause as @{thm (lhs) + injval.simps(1)[of "c" "c"]} $\dn$ @{thm (rhs) injval.simps(1)[of "c"]}, + but our deviation is harmless.} + + The idea of the @{term inj}-function to ``inject'' a character, say + @{term c}, into a value can be made precise by the first part of the + following lemma, which shows that the underlying string of an injected + value has a prepended character @{term c}; the second part shows that the + underlying string of an @{const mkeps}-value is always the empty string + (given the regular expression is nullable since otherwise @{text mkeps} + might not be defined). + + \begin{lemma}\mbox{}\smallskip\\\label{Prf_injval_flat} + \begin{tabular}{ll} + (1) & @{thm[mode=IfThen] Prf_injval_flat}\\ + (2) & @{thm[mode=IfThen] mkeps_flat} + \end{tabular} + \end{lemma} + + \begin{proof} + Both properties are by routine inductions: the first one can, for example, + be proved by induction over the definition of @{term derivatives}; the second by + an induction on @{term r}. There are no interesting cases.\qed + \end{proof} + + Having defined the @{const mkeps} and @{text inj} function we can extend + \Brz's matcher so that a [lexical] value is constructed (assuming the + regular expression matches the string). The clauses of the Sulzmann and Lu lexer are + + \begin{center} + \begin{tabular}{lcl} + @{thm (lhs) lexer.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) lexer.simps(1)}\\ + @{thm (lhs) lexer.simps(2)} & $\dn$ & @{text "case"} @{term "lexer (der c r) s"} @{text of}\\ + & & \phantom{$|$} @{term "None"} @{text "\"} @{term None}\\ + & & $|$ @{term "Some v"} @{text "\"} @{term "Some (injval r c v)"} + \end{tabular} + \end{center} + + \noindent If the regular expression does not match the string, @{const None} is + returned. If the regular expression \emph{does} + match the string, then @{const Some} value is returned. One important + virtue of this algorithm is that it can be implemented with ease in any + functional programming language and also in Isabelle/HOL. In the remaining + part of this section we prove that this algorithm is correct. + + The well-known idea of POSIX matching is informally defined by the longest + match and priority rule (see Introduction); as correctly argued in \cite{Sulzmann2014}, this + needs formal specification. Sulzmann and Lu define an ``ordering + relation'' between values and argue + that there is a maximum value, as given by the derivative-based algorithm. + In contrast, we shall introduce a simple inductive definition that + specifies directly what a \emph{POSIX value} is, incorporating the + POSIX-specific choices into the side-conditions of our rules. Our + definition is inspired by the matching relation given by Vansummeren + \cite{Vansummeren2006}. The relation we define is ternary and written as + \mbox{@{term "s \ r \ v"}}, relating strings, regular expressions and + values. + % + \begin{center} + \begin{tabular}{c} + @{thm[mode=Axiom] Posix.intros(1)}@{text "P"}@{term "ONE"} \qquad + @{thm[mode=Axiom] Posix.intros(2)}@{text "P"}@{term "c"}\medskip\\ + @{thm[mode=Rule] Posix.intros(3)[of "s" "r\<^sub>1" "v" "r\<^sub>2"]}@{text "P+L"}\qquad + @{thm[mode=Rule] Posix.intros(4)[of "s" "r\<^sub>2" "v" "r\<^sub>1"]}@{text "P+R"}\medskip\\ + $\mprset{flushleft} + \inferrule + {@{thm (prem 1) Posix.intros(5)[of "s\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>1" "s\<^sub>2" "r\<^sub>2" "v\<^sub>2"]} \qquad + @{thm (prem 2) Posix.intros(5)[of "s\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>1" "s\<^sub>2" "r\<^sub>2" "v\<^sub>2"]} \\\\ + @{thm (prem 3) Posix.intros(5)[of "s\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>1" "s\<^sub>2" "r\<^sub>2" "v\<^sub>2"]}} + {@{thm (concl) Posix.intros(5)[of "s\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>1" "s\<^sub>2" "r\<^sub>2" "v\<^sub>2"]}}$@{text "PS"}\\ + @{thm[mode=Axiom] Posix.intros(7)}@{text "P[]"}\medskip\\ + $\mprset{flushleft} + \inferrule + {@{thm (prem 1) Posix.intros(6)[of "s\<^sub>1" "r" "v" "s\<^sub>2" "vs"]} \qquad + @{thm (prem 2) Posix.intros(6)[of "s\<^sub>1" "r" "v" "s\<^sub>2" "vs"]} \qquad + @{thm (prem 3) Posix.intros(6)[of "s\<^sub>1" "r" "v" "s\<^sub>2" "vs"]} \\\\ + @{thm (prem 4) Posix.intros(6)[of "s\<^sub>1" "r" "v" "s\<^sub>2" "vs"]}} + {@{thm (concl) Posix.intros(6)[of "s\<^sub>1" "r" "v" "s\<^sub>2" "vs"]}}$@{text "P\"} + \end{tabular} + \end{center} + + \noindent + We can prove that given a string @{term s} and regular expression @{term + r}, the POSIX value @{term v} is uniquely determined by @{term "s \ r \ v"}. + + \begin{theorem}\mbox{}\smallskip\\\label{posixdeterm} + \begin{tabular}{ll} + @{text "(1)"} & If @{thm (prem 1) Posix1(1)} then @{thm (concl) + Posix1(1)} and @{thm (concl) Posix1(2)}.\\ + @{text "(2)"} & @{thm[mode=IfThen] Posix_determ(1)[of _ _ "v" "v'"]} + \end{tabular} + \end{theorem} + + \begin{proof} Both by induction on the definition of @{term "s \ r \ v"}. + The second parts follows by a case analysis of @{term "s \ r \ v'"} and + the first part.\qed + \end{proof} + + \noindent + We claim that our @{term "s \ r \ v"} relation captures the idea behind the two + informal POSIX rules shown in the Introduction: Consider for example the + rules @{text "P+L"} and @{text "P+R"} where the POSIX value for a string + and an alternative regular expression, that is @{term "(s, ALT r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2)"}, + is specified---it is always a @{text "Left"}-value, \emph{except} when the + string to be matched is not in the language of @{term "r\<^sub>1"}; only then it + is a @{text Right}-value (see the side-condition in @{text "P+R"}). + Interesting is also the rule for sequence regular expressions (@{text + "PS"}). The first two premises state that @{term "v\<^sub>1"} and @{term "v\<^sub>2"} + are the POSIX values for @{term "(s\<^sub>1, r\<^sub>1)"} and @{term "(s\<^sub>2, r\<^sub>2)"} + respectively. Consider now the third premise and note that the POSIX value + of this rule should match the string \mbox{@{term "s\<^sub>1 @ s\<^sub>2"}}. According to the + longest match rule, we want that the @{term "s\<^sub>1"} is the longest initial + split of \mbox{@{term "s\<^sub>1 @ s\<^sub>2"}} such that @{term "s\<^sub>2"} is still recognised + by @{term "r\<^sub>2"}. Let us assume, contrary to the third premise, that there + \emph{exist} an @{term "s\<^sub>3"} and @{term "s\<^sub>4"} such that @{term "s\<^sub>2"} + can be split up into a non-empty string @{term "s\<^sub>3"} and a possibly empty + string @{term "s\<^sub>4"}. Moreover the longer string @{term "s\<^sub>1 @ s\<^sub>3"} can be + matched by @{text "r\<^sub>1"} and the shorter @{term "s\<^sub>4"} can still be + matched by @{term "r\<^sub>2"}. In this case @{term "s\<^sub>1"} would \emph{not} be the + longest initial split of \mbox{@{term "s\<^sub>1 @ s\<^sub>2"}} and therefore @{term "Seq v\<^sub>1 + v\<^sub>2"} cannot be a POSIX value for @{term "(s\<^sub>1 @ s\<^sub>2, SEQ r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2)"}. + The main point is that our side-condition ensures the longest + match rule is satisfied. + + A similar condition is imposed on the POSIX value in the @{text + "P\"}-rule. Also there we want that @{term "s\<^sub>1"} is the longest initial + split of @{term "s\<^sub>1 @ s\<^sub>2"} and furthermore the corresponding value + @{term v} cannot be flattened to the empty string. In effect, we require + that in each ``iteration'' of the star, some non-empty substring needs to + be ``chipped'' away; only in case of the empty string we accept @{term + "Stars []"} as the POSIX value. + + Next is the lemma that shows the function @{term "mkeps"} calculates + the POSIX value for the empty string and a nullable regular expression. + + \begin{lemma}\label{lemmkeps} + @{thm[mode=IfThen] Posix_mkeps} + \end{lemma} + + \begin{proof} + By routine induction on @{term r}.\qed + \end{proof} + + \noindent + The central lemma for our POSIX relation is that the @{text inj}-function + preserves POSIX values. + + \begin{lemma}\label{Posix2} + @{thm[mode=IfThen] Posix_injval} + \end{lemma} + + \begin{proof} + By induction on @{text r}. We explain two cases. + + \begin{itemize} + \item[$\bullet$] Case @{term "r = ALT r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2"}. There are + two subcases, namely @{text "(a)"} \mbox{@{term "v = Left v'"}} and @{term + "s \ der c r\<^sub>1 \ v'"}; and @{text "(b)"} @{term "v = Right v'"}, @{term + "s \ L (der c r\<^sub>1)"} and @{term "s \ der c r\<^sub>2 \ v'"}. In @{text "(a)"} we + know @{term "s \ der c r\<^sub>1 \ v'"}, from which we can infer @{term "(c # s) + \ r\<^sub>1 \ injval r\<^sub>1 c v'"} by induction hypothesis and hence @{term "(c # + s) \ ALT r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2 \ injval (ALT r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2) c (Left v')"} as needed. Similarly + in subcase @{text "(b)"} where, however, in addition we have to use + Prop.~\ref{derprop}(2) in order to infer @{term "c # s \ L r\<^sub>1"} from @{term + "s \ L (der c r\<^sub>1)"}. + + \item[$\bullet$] Case @{term "r = SEQ r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2"}. There are three subcases: + + \begin{quote} + \begin{description} + \item[@{text "(a)"}] @{term "v = Left (Seq v\<^sub>1 v\<^sub>2)"} and @{term "nullable r\<^sub>1"} + \item[@{text "(b)"}] @{term "v = Right v\<^sub>1"} and @{term "nullable r\<^sub>1"} + \item[@{text "(c)"}] @{term "v = Seq v\<^sub>1 v\<^sub>2"} and @{term "\ nullable r\<^sub>1"} + \end{description} + \end{quote} + + \noindent For @{text "(a)"} we know @{term "s\<^sub>1 \ der c r\<^sub>1 \ v\<^sub>1"} and + @{term "s\<^sub>2 \ r\<^sub>2 \ v\<^sub>2"} as well as + % + \[@{term "\ (\s\<^sub>3 s\<^sub>4. s\<^sub>3 \ [] \ s\<^sub>3 @ s\<^sub>4 = s\<^sub>2 \ s\<^sub>1 @ s\<^sub>3 \ L (der c r\<^sub>1) \ s\<^sub>4 \ L r\<^sub>2)"}\] + + \noindent From the latter we can infer by Prop.~\ref{derprop}(2): + % + \[@{term "\ (\s\<^sub>3 s\<^sub>4. s\<^sub>3 \ [] \ s\<^sub>3 @ s\<^sub>4 = s\<^sub>2 \ (c # s\<^sub>1) @ s\<^sub>3 \ L r\<^sub>1 \ s\<^sub>4 \ L r\<^sub>2)"}\] + + \noindent We can use the induction hypothesis for @{text "r\<^sub>1"} to obtain + @{term "(c # s\<^sub>1) \ r\<^sub>1 \ injval r\<^sub>1 c v\<^sub>1"}. Putting this all together allows us to infer + @{term "((c # s\<^sub>1) @ s\<^sub>2) \ SEQ r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2 \ Seq (injval r\<^sub>1 c v\<^sub>1) v\<^sub>2"}. The case @{text "(c)"} + is similar. + + For @{text "(b)"} we know @{term "s \ der c r\<^sub>2 \ v\<^sub>1"} and + @{term "s\<^sub>1 @ s\<^sub>2 \ L (SEQ (der c r\<^sub>1) r\<^sub>2)"}. From the former + we have @{term "(c # s) \ r\<^sub>2 \ (injval r\<^sub>2 c v\<^sub>1)"} by induction hypothesis + for @{term "r\<^sub>2"}. From the latter we can infer + % + \[@{term "\ (\s\<^sub>3 s\<^sub>4. s\<^sub>3 \ [] \ s\<^sub>3 @ s\<^sub>4 = c # s \ s\<^sub>3 \ L r\<^sub>1 \ s\<^sub>4 \ L r\<^sub>2)"}\] + + \noindent By Lem.~\ref{lemmkeps} we know @{term "[] \ r\<^sub>1 \ (mkeps r\<^sub>1)"} + holds. Putting this all together, we can conclude with @{term "(c # + s) \ SEQ r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2 \ Seq (mkeps r\<^sub>1) (injval r\<^sub>2 c v\<^sub>1)"}, as required. + + Finally suppose @{term "r = STAR r\<^sub>1"}. This case is very similar to the + sequence case, except that we need to also ensure that @{term "flat (injval r\<^sub>1 + c v\<^sub>1) \ []"}. This follows from @{term "(c # s\<^sub>1) + \ r\<^sub>1 \ injval r\<^sub>1 c v\<^sub>1"} (which in turn follows from @{term "s\<^sub>1 \ der c + r\<^sub>1 \ v\<^sub>1"} and the induction hypothesis).\qed + \end{itemize} + \end{proof} + + \noindent + With Lem.~\ref{Posix2} in place, it is completely routine to establish + that the Sulzmann and Lu lexer satisfies our specification (returning + the null value @{term "None"} iff the string is not in the language of the regular expression, + and returning a unique POSIX value iff the string \emph{is} in the language): + + \begin{theorem}\mbox{}\smallskip\\\label{lexercorrect} + \begin{tabular}{ll} + (1) & @{thm (lhs) lexer_correct_None} if and only if @{thm (rhs) lexer_correct_None}\\ + (2) & @{thm (lhs) lexer_correct_Some} if and only if @{thm (rhs) lexer_correct_Some}\\ + \end{tabular} + \end{theorem} + + \begin{proof} + By induction on @{term s} using Lem.~\ref{lemmkeps} and \ref{Posix2}.\qed + \end{proof} + + \noindent In (2) we further know by Thm.~\ref{posixdeterm} that the + value returned by the lexer must be unique. A simple corollary + of our two theorems is: + + \begin{corollary}\mbox{}\smallskip\\\label{lexercorrectcor} + \begin{tabular}{ll} + (1) & @{thm (lhs) lexer_correctness(2)} if and only if @{thm (rhs) lexer_correctness(2)}\\ + (2) & @{thm (lhs) lexer_correctness(1)} if and only if @{thm (rhs) lexer_correctness(1)}\\ + \end{tabular} + \end{corollary} + + \noindent + This concludes our + correctness proof. Note that we have not changed the algorithm of + Sulzmann and Lu,\footnote{All deviations we introduced are + harmless.} but introduced our own specification for what a correct + result---a POSIX value---should be. A strong point in favour of + Sulzmann and Lu's algorithm is that it can be extended in various + ways. + +*} + +section {* Extensions and Optimisations*} + +text {* + + If we are interested in tokenising a string, then we need to not just + split up the string into tokens, but also ``classify'' the tokens (for + example whether it is a keyword or an identifier). This can be done with + only minor modifications to the algorithm by introducing \emph{record + regular expressions} and \emph{record values} (for example + \cite{Sulzmann2014b}): + + \begin{center} + @{text "r :="} + @{text "..."} $\mid$ + @{text "(l : r)"} \qquad\qquad + @{text "v :="} + @{text "..."} $\mid$ + @{text "(l : v)"} + \end{center} + + \noindent where @{text l} is a label, say a string, @{text r} a regular + expression and @{text v} a value. All functions can be smoothly extended + to these regular expressions and values. For example \mbox{@{text "(l : + r)"}} is nullable iff @{term r} is, and so on. The purpose of the record + regular expression is to mark certain parts of a regular expression and + then record in the calculated value which parts of the string were matched + by this part. The label can then serve as classification for the tokens. + For this recall the regular expression @{text "(r\<^bsub>key\<^esub> + r\<^bsub>id\<^esub>)\<^sup>\"} for + keywords and identifiers from the Introduction. With the record regular + expression we can form \mbox{@{text "((key : r\<^bsub>key\<^esub>) + (id : r\<^bsub>id\<^esub>))\<^sup>\"}} + and then traverse the calculated value and only collect the underlying + strings in record values. With this we obtain finite sequences of pairs of + labels and strings, for example + + \[@{text "(l\<^sub>1 : s\<^sub>1), ..., (l\<^sub>n : s\<^sub>n)"}\] + + \noindent from which tokens with classifications (keyword-token, + identifier-token and so on) can be extracted. + + Derivatives as calculated by \Brz's method are usually more complex + regular expressions than the initial one; the result is that the + derivative-based matching and lexing algorithms are often abysmally slow. + However, various optimisations are possible, such as the simplifications + of @{term "ALT ZERO r"}, @{term "ALT r ZERO"}, @{term "SEQ ONE r"} and + @{term "SEQ r ONE"} to @{term r}. These simplifications can speed up the + algorithms considerably, as noted in \cite{Sulzmann2014}. One of the + advantages of having a simple specification and correctness proof is that + the latter can be refined to prove the correctness of such simplification + steps. While the simplification of regular expressions according to + rules like + + \begin{equation}\label{Simpl} + \begin{array}{lcllcllcllcl} + @{term "ALT ZERO r"} & @{text "\"} & @{term r} \hspace{8mm}%\\ + @{term "ALT r ZERO"} & @{text "\"} & @{term r} \hspace{8mm}%\\ + @{term "SEQ ONE r"} & @{text "\"} & @{term r} \hspace{8mm}%\\ + @{term "SEQ r ONE"} & @{text "\"} & @{term r} + \end{array} + \end{equation} + + \noindent is well understood, there is an obstacle with the POSIX value + calculation algorithm by Sulzmann and Lu: if we build a derivative regular + expression and then simplify it, we will calculate a POSIX value for this + simplified derivative regular expression, \emph{not} for the original (unsimplified) + derivative regular expression. Sulzmann and Lu \cite{Sulzmann2014} overcome this obstacle by + not just calculating a simplified regular expression, but also calculating + a \emph{rectification function} that ``repairs'' the incorrect value. + + The rectification functions can be (slightly clumsily) implemented in + Isabelle/HOL as follows using some auxiliary functions: + + \begin{center} + \begin{tabular}{lcl} + @{thm (lhs) F_RIGHT.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{text "Right (f v)"}\\ + @{thm (lhs) F_LEFT.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{text "Left (f v)"}\\ + + @{thm (lhs) F_ALT.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{text "Right (f\<^sub>2 v)"}\\ + @{thm (lhs) F_ALT.simps(2)} & $\dn$ & @{text "Left (f\<^sub>1 v)"}\\ + + @{thm (lhs) F_SEQ1.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{text "Seq (f\<^sub>1 ()) (f\<^sub>2 v)"}\\ + @{thm (lhs) F_SEQ2.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{text "Seq (f\<^sub>1 v) (f\<^sub>2 ())"}\\ + @{thm (lhs) F_SEQ.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{text "Seq (f\<^sub>1 v\<^sub>1) (f\<^sub>2 v\<^sub>2)"}\medskip\\ + %\end{tabular} + % + %\begin{tabular}{lcl} + @{term "simp_ALT (ZERO, DUMMY) (r\<^sub>2, f\<^sub>2)"} & $\dn$ & @{term "(r\<^sub>2, F_RIGHT f\<^sub>2)"}\\ + @{term "simp_ALT (r\<^sub>1, f\<^sub>1) (ZERO, DUMMY)"} & $\dn$ & @{term "(r\<^sub>1, F_LEFT f\<^sub>1)"}\\ + @{term "simp_ALT (r\<^sub>1, f\<^sub>1) (r\<^sub>2, f\<^sub>2)"} & $\dn$ & @{term "(ALT r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2, F_ALT f\<^sub>1 f\<^sub>2)"}\\ + @{term "simp_SEQ (ONE, f\<^sub>1) (r\<^sub>2, f\<^sub>2)"} & $\dn$ & @{term "(r\<^sub>2, F_SEQ1 f\<^sub>1 f\<^sub>2)"}\\ + @{term "simp_SEQ (r\<^sub>1, f\<^sub>1) (ONE, f\<^sub>2)"} & $\dn$ & @{term "(r\<^sub>1, F_SEQ2 f\<^sub>1 f\<^sub>2)"}\\ + @{term "simp_SEQ (r\<^sub>1, f\<^sub>1) (r\<^sub>2, f\<^sub>2)"} & $\dn$ & @{term "(SEQ r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2, F_SEQ f\<^sub>1 f\<^sub>2)"}\\ + \end{tabular} + \end{center} + + \noindent + The functions @{text "simp\<^bsub>Alt\<^esub>"} and @{text "simp\<^bsub>Seq\<^esub>"} encode the simplification rules + in \eqref{Simpl} and compose the rectification functions (simplifications can occur + deep inside the regular expression). The main simplification function is then + + \begin{center} + \begin{tabular}{lcl} + @{term "simp (ALT r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2)"} & $\dn$ & @{term "simp_ALT (simp r\<^sub>1) (simp r\<^sub>2)"}\\ + @{term "simp (SEQ r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2)"} & $\dn$ & @{term "simp_SEQ (simp r\<^sub>1) (simp r\<^sub>2)"}\\ + @{term "simp r"} & $\dn$ & @{term "(r, id)"}\\ + \end{tabular} + \end{center} + + \noindent where @{term "id"} stands for the identity function. The + function @{const simp} returns a simplified regular expression and a corresponding + rectification function. Note that we do not simplify under stars: this + seems to slow down the algorithm, rather than speed it up. The optimised + lexer is then given by the clauses: + + \begin{center} + \begin{tabular}{lcl} + @{thm (lhs) slexer.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) slexer.simps(1)}\\ + @{thm (lhs) slexer.simps(2)} & $\dn$ & + @{text "let (r\<^sub>s, f\<^sub>r) = simp (r "}$\backslash$@{text " c) in"}\\ + & & @{text "case"} @{term "slexer r\<^sub>s s"} @{text of}\\ + & & \phantom{$|$} @{term "None"} @{text "\"} @{term None}\\ + & & $|$ @{term "Some v"} @{text "\"} @{text "Some (inj r c (f\<^sub>r v))"} + \end{tabular} + \end{center} + + \noindent + In the second clause we first calculate the derivative @{term "der c r"} + and then simplify the result. This gives us a simplified derivative + @{text "r\<^sub>s"} and a rectification function @{text "f\<^sub>r"}. The lexer + is then recursively called with the simplified derivative, but before + we inject the character @{term c} into the value @{term v}, we need to rectify + @{term v} (that is construct @{term "f\<^sub>r v"}). Before we can establish the correctness + of @{term "slexer"}, we need to show that simplification preserves the language + and simplification preserves our POSIX relation once the value is rectified + (recall @{const "simp"} generates a (regular expression, rectification function) pair): + + \begin{lemma}\mbox{}\smallskip\\\label{slexeraux} + \begin{tabular}{ll} + (1) & @{thm L_fst_simp[symmetric]}\\ + (2) & @{thm[mode=IfThen] Posix_simp} + \end{tabular} + \end{lemma} + + \begin{proof} Both are by induction on @{text r}. There is no + interesting case for the first statement. For the second statement, + of interest are the @{term "r = ALT r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2"} and @{term "r = SEQ r\<^sub>1 + r\<^sub>2"} cases. In each case we have to analyse four subcases whether + @{term "fst (simp r\<^sub>1)"} and @{term "fst (simp r\<^sub>2)"} equals @{const + ZERO} (respectively @{const ONE}). For example for @{term "r = ALT + r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2"}, consider the subcase @{term "fst (simp r\<^sub>1) = ZERO"} and + @{term "fst (simp r\<^sub>2) \ ZERO"}. By assumption we know @{term "s \ + fst (simp (ALT r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2)) \ v"}. From this we can infer @{term "s \ fst (simp r\<^sub>2) \ v"} + and by IH also (*) @{term "s \ r\<^sub>2 \ (snd (simp r\<^sub>2) v)"}. Given @{term "fst (simp r\<^sub>1) = ZERO"} + we know @{term "L (fst (simp r\<^sub>1)) = {}"}. By the first statement + @{term "L r\<^sub>1"} is the empty set, meaning (**) @{term "s \ L r\<^sub>1"}. + Taking (*) and (**) together gives by the \mbox{@{text "P+R"}}-rule + @{term "s \ ALT r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2 \ Right (snd (simp r\<^sub>2) v)"}. In turn this + gives @{term "s \ ALT r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2 \ snd (simp (ALT r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2)) v"} as we need to show. + The other cases are similar.\qed + \end{proof} + + \noindent We can now prove relatively straightforwardly that the + optimised lexer produces the expected result: + + \begin{theorem} + @{thm slexer_correctness} + \end{theorem} + + \begin{proof} By induction on @{term s} generalising over @{term + r}. The case @{term "[]"} is trivial. For the cons-case suppose the + string is of the form @{term "c # s"}. By induction hypothesis we + know @{term "slexer r s = lexer r s"} holds for all @{term r} (in + particular for @{term "r"} being the derivative @{term "der c + r"}). Let @{term "r\<^sub>s"} be the simplified derivative regular expression, that is @{term + "fst (simp (der c r))"}, and @{term "f\<^sub>r"} be the rectification + function, that is @{term "snd (simp (der c r))"}. We distinguish the cases + whether (*) @{term "s \ L (der c r)"} or not. In the first case we + have by Thm.~\ref{lexercorrect}(2) a value @{term "v"} so that @{term + "lexer (der c r) s = Some v"} and @{term "s \ der c r \ v"} hold. + By Lem.~\ref{slexeraux}(1) we can also infer from~(*) that @{term "s + \ L r\<^sub>s"} holds. Hence we know by Thm.~\ref{lexercorrect}(2) that + there exists a @{term "v'"} with @{term "lexer r\<^sub>s s = Some v'"} and + @{term "s \ r\<^sub>s \ v'"}. From the latter we know by + Lem.~\ref{slexeraux}(2) that @{term "s \ der c r \ (f\<^sub>r v')"} holds. + By the uniqueness of the POSIX relation (Thm.~\ref{posixdeterm}) we + can infer that @{term v} is equal to @{term "f\<^sub>r v'"}---that is the + rectification function applied to @{term "v'"} + produces the original @{term "v"}. Now the case follows by the + definitions of @{const lexer} and @{const slexer}. + + In the second case where @{term "s \ L (der c r)"} we have that + @{term "lexer (der c r) s = None"} by Thm.~\ref{lexercorrect}(1). We + also know by Lem.~\ref{slexeraux}(1) that @{term "s \ L r\<^sub>s"}. Hence + @{term "lexer r\<^sub>s s = None"} by Thm.~\ref{lexercorrect}(1) and + by IH then also @{term "slexer r\<^sub>s s = None"}. With this we can + conclude in this case too.\qed + + \end{proof} +*} + +section {* The Correctness Argument by Sulzmann and Lu\label{argu} *} + +text {* +% \newcommand{\greedy}{\succcurlyeq_{gr}} + \newcommand{\posix}{>} + + An extended version of \cite{Sulzmann2014} is available at the website of + its first author; this includes some ``proofs'', claimed in + \cite{Sulzmann2014} to be ``rigorous''. Since these are evidently not in + final form, we make no comment thereon, preferring to give general reasons + for our belief that the approach of \cite{Sulzmann2014} is problematic. + Their central definition is an ``ordering relation'' defined by the + rules (slightly adapted to fit our notation): + +\begin{center} +\begin{tabular}{@ {}c@ {\hspace{4mm}}c@ {}} +@{thm[mode=Rule] C2[of "v\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>1\" "v\<^sub>2" "r\<^sub>2" "v\<^sub>2\"]}\,(C2) & +@{thm[mode=Rule] C1[of "v\<^sub>2" "r\<^sub>2" "v\<^sub>2\" "v\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>1"]}\,(C1)\smallskip\\ + +@{thm[mode=Rule] A1[of "v\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>2" "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]}\,(A1) & +@{thm[mode=Rule] A2[of "v\<^sub>2" "v\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]}\,(A2)\smallskip\\ + +@{thm[mode=Rule] A3[of "v\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2" "v\<^sub>2" "r\<^sub>1"]}\,(A3) & +@{thm[mode=Rule] A4[of "v\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>2" "r\<^sub>2"]}\,(A4)\smallskip\\ + +@{thm[mode=Rule] K1[of "v" "vs" "r"]}\,(K1) & +@{thm[mode=Rule] K2[of "v" "vs" "r"]}\,(K2)\smallskip\\ + +@{thm[mode=Rule] K3[of "v\<^sub>1" "r" "v\<^sub>2" "vs\<^sub>1" "vs\<^sub>2"]}\,(K3) & +@{thm[mode=Rule] K4[of "vs\<^sub>1" "r" "vs\<^sub>2" "v"]}\,(K4) +\end{tabular} +\end{center} + + \noindent The idea behind the rules (A1) and (A2), for example, is that a + @{text Left}-value is bigger than a @{text Right}-value, if the underlying + string of the @{text Left}-value is longer or of equal length to the + underlying string of the @{text Right}-value. The order is reversed, + however, if the @{text Right}-value can match a longer string than a + @{text Left}-value. In this way the POSIX value is supposed to be the + biggest value for a given string and regular expression. + + Sulzmann and Lu explicitly refer to the paper \cite{Frisch2004} by Frisch + and Cardelli from where they have taken the idea for their correctness + proof. Frisch and Cardelli introduced a similar ordering for GREEDY + matching and they showed that their GREEDY matching algorithm always + produces a maximal element according to this ordering (from all possible + solutions). The only difference between their GREEDY ordering and the + ``ordering'' by Sulzmann and Lu is that GREEDY always prefers a @{text + Left}-value over a @{text Right}-value, no matter what the underlying + string is. This seems to be only a very minor difference, but it has + drastic consequences in terms of what properties both orderings enjoy. + What is interesting for our purposes is that the properties reflexivity, + totality and transitivity for this GREEDY ordering can be proved + relatively easily by induction. + + These properties of GREEDY, however, do not transfer to the POSIX + ``ordering'' by Sulzmann and Lu, which they define as @{text "v\<^sub>1 \\<^sub>r v\<^sub>2"}. + To start with, @{text "v\<^sub>1 \\<^sub>r v\<^sub>2"} is + not defined inductively, but as $($@{term "v\<^sub>1 = v\<^sub>2"}$)$ $\vee$ $($@{term "(v\<^sub>1 >r + v\<^sub>2) \ (flat v\<^sub>1 = flat (v\<^sub>2::val))"}$)$. This means that @{term "v\<^sub>1 + >(r::rexp) (v\<^sub>2::val)"} does not necessarily imply @{term "v\<^sub>1 \(r::rexp) + (v\<^sub>2::val)"}. Moreover, transitivity does not hold in the ``usual'' + formulation, for example: + + \begin{falsehood} + Suppose @{term "\ v\<^sub>1 : r"}, @{term "\ v\<^sub>2 : r"} and @{term "\ v\<^sub>3 : r"}. + If @{term "v\<^sub>1 >(r::rexp) (v\<^sub>2::val)"} and @{term "v\<^sub>2 >(r::rexp) (v\<^sub>3::val)"} + then @{term "v\<^sub>1 >(r::rexp) (v\<^sub>3::val)"}. + \end{falsehood} + + \noindent If formulated in this way, then there are various counter + examples: For example let @{term r} be @{text "a + ((a + a)\(a + \))"} + then the @{term "v\<^sub>1"}, @{term "v\<^sub>2"} and @{term "v\<^sub>3"} below are values + of @{term r}: + + \begin{center} + \begin{tabular}{lcl} + @{term "v\<^sub>1"} & $=$ & @{term "Left(Char a)"}\\ + @{term "v\<^sub>2"} & $=$ & @{term "Right(Seq (Left(Char a)) (Right Void))"}\\ + @{term "v\<^sub>3"} & $=$ & @{term "Right(Seq (Right(Char a)) (Left(Char a)))"} + \end{tabular} + \end{center} + + \noindent Moreover @{term "v\<^sub>1 >(r::rexp) v\<^sub>2"} and @{term "v\<^sub>2 >(r::rexp) + v\<^sub>3"}, but \emph{not} @{term "v\<^sub>1 >(r::rexp) v\<^sub>3"}! The reason is that + although @{term "v\<^sub>3"} is a @{text "Right"}-value, it can match a longer + string, namely @{term "flat v\<^sub>3 = [a,a]"}, while @{term "flat v\<^sub>1"} (and + @{term "flat v\<^sub>2"}) matches only @{term "[a]"}. So transitivity in this + formulation does not hold---in this example actually @{term "v\<^sub>3 + >(r::rexp) v\<^sub>1"}! + + Sulzmann and Lu ``fix'' this problem by weakening the transitivity + property. They require in addition that the underlying strings are of the + same length. This excludes the counter example above and any + counter-example we were able to find (by hand and by machine). Thus the + transitivity lemma should be formulated as: + + \begin{conject} + Suppose @{term "\ v\<^sub>1 : r"}, @{term "\ v\<^sub>2 : r"} and @{term "\ v\<^sub>3 : r"}, + and also @{text "|v\<^sub>1| = |v\<^sub>2| = |v\<^sub>3|"}.\\ + If @{term "v\<^sub>1 >(r::rexp) (v\<^sub>2::val)"} and @{term "v\<^sub>2 >(r::rexp) (v\<^sub>3::val)"} + then @{term "v\<^sub>1 >(r::rexp) (v\<^sub>3::val)"}. + \end{conject} + + \noindent While we agree with Sulzmann and Lu that this property + probably(!) holds, proving it seems not so straightforward: although one + begins with the assumption that the values have the same flattening, this + cannot be maintained as one descends into the induction. This is a problem + that occurs in a number of places in the proofs by Sulzmann and Lu. + + Although they do not give an explicit proof of the transitivity property, + they give a closely related property about the existence of maximal + elements. They state that this can be verified by an induction on @{term r}. We + disagree with this as we shall show next in case of transitivity. The case + where the reasoning breaks down is the sequence case, say @{term "SEQ r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2"}. + The induction hypotheses in this case are + +\begin{center} +\begin{tabular}{@ {}c@ {\hspace{10mm}}c@ {}} +\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {\hspace{-7mm}}l@ {}} +IH @{term "r\<^sub>1"}:\\ +@{text "\ v\<^sub>1, v\<^sub>2, v\<^sub>3."} \\ + & @{term "\ v\<^sub>1 : r\<^sub>1"}\;@{text "\"} + @{term "\ v\<^sub>2 : r\<^sub>1"}\;@{text "\"} + @{term "\ v\<^sub>3 : r\<^sub>1"}\\ + & @{text "\"} @{text "|v\<^sub>1| = |v\<^sub>2| = |v\<^sub>3|"}\\ + & @{text "\"} @{term "v\<^sub>1 >(r\<^sub>1::rexp) v\<^sub>2 \ v\<^sub>2 >(r\<^sub>1::rexp) v\<^sub>3"}\medskip\\ + & $\Rightarrow$ @{term "v\<^sub>1 >(r\<^sub>1::rexp) v\<^sub>3"} +\end{tabular} & +\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {\hspace{-7mm}}l@ {}} +IH @{term "r\<^sub>2"}:\\ +@{text "\ v\<^sub>1, v\<^sub>2, v\<^sub>3."}\\ + & @{term "\ v\<^sub>1 : r\<^sub>2"}\;@{text "\"} + @{term "\ v\<^sub>2 : r\<^sub>2"}\;@{text "\"} + @{term "\ v\<^sub>3 : r\<^sub>2"}\\ + & @{text "\"} @{text "|v\<^sub>1| = |v\<^sub>2| = |v\<^sub>3|"}\\ + & @{text "\"} @{term "v\<^sub>1 >(r\<^sub>2::rexp) v\<^sub>2 \ v\<^sub>2 >(r\<^sub>2::rexp) v\<^sub>3"}\medskip\\ + & $\Rightarrow$ @{term "v\<^sub>1 >(r\<^sub>2::rexp) v\<^sub>3"} +\end{tabular} +\end{tabular} +\end{center} + + \noindent We can assume that + % + \begin{equation} + @{term "(Seq (v\<^sub>1\<^sub>l) (v\<^sub>1\<^sub>r)) >(SEQ r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2) (Seq (v\<^sub>2\<^sub>l) (v\<^sub>2\<^sub>r))"} + \qquad\textrm{and}\qquad + @{term "(Seq (v\<^sub>2\<^sub>l) (v\<^sub>2\<^sub>r)) >(SEQ r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2) (Seq (v\<^sub>3\<^sub>l) (v\<^sub>3\<^sub>r))"} + \label{assms} + \end{equation} + + \noindent hold, and furthermore that the values have equal length, namely: + % + \begin{equation} + @{term "flat (Seq (v\<^sub>1\<^sub>l) (v\<^sub>1\<^sub>r)) = flat (Seq (v\<^sub>2\<^sub>l) (v\<^sub>2\<^sub>r))"} + \qquad\textrm{and}\qquad + @{term "flat (Seq (v\<^sub>2\<^sub>l) (v\<^sub>2\<^sub>r)) = flat (Seq (v\<^sub>3\<^sub>l) (v\<^sub>3\<^sub>r))"} + \label{lens} + \end{equation} + + \noindent We need to show that @{term "(Seq (v\<^sub>1\<^sub>l) (v\<^sub>1\<^sub>r)) >(SEQ r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2) + (Seq (v\<^sub>3\<^sub>l) (v\<^sub>3\<^sub>r))"} holds. We can proceed by analysing how the + assumptions in \eqref{assms} have arisen. There are four cases. Let us + assume we are in the case where we know + + \[ + @{term "v\<^sub>1\<^sub>l >(r\<^sub>1::rexp) v\<^sub>2\<^sub>l"} + \qquad\textrm{and}\qquad + @{term "v\<^sub>2\<^sub>l >(r\<^sub>1::rexp) v\<^sub>3\<^sub>l"} + \] + + \noindent and also know the corresponding inhabitation judgements. This is + exactly a case where we would like to apply the induction hypothesis + IH~$r_1$. But we cannot! We still need to show that @{term "flat (v\<^sub>1\<^sub>l) = + flat(v\<^sub>2\<^sub>l)"} and @{term "flat(v\<^sub>2\<^sub>l) = flat(v\<^sub>3\<^sub>l)"}. We know from + \eqref{lens} that the lengths of the sequence values are equal, but from + this we cannot infer anything about the lengths of the component values. + Indeed in general they will be unequal, that is + + \[ + @{term "flat(v\<^sub>1\<^sub>l) \ flat(v\<^sub>2\<^sub>l)"} + \qquad\textrm{and}\qquad + @{term "flat(v\<^sub>1\<^sub>r) \ flat(v\<^sub>2\<^sub>r)"} + \] + + \noindent but still \eqref{lens} will hold. Now we are stuck, since the IH + does not apply. As said, this problem where the induction hypothesis does + not apply arises in several places in the proof of Sulzmann and Lu, not + just for proving transitivity. + +*} + +section {* Conclusion *} + +text {* + + We have implemented the POSIX value calculation algorithm introduced by + Sulzmann and Lu + \cite{Sulzmann2014}. Our implementation is nearly identical to the + original and all modifications we introduced are harmless (like our char-clause for + @{text inj}). We have proved this algorithm to be correct, but correct + according to our own specification of what POSIX values are. Our + specification (inspired from work by Vansummeren \cite{Vansummeren2006}) appears to be + much simpler than in \cite{Sulzmann2014} and our proofs are nearly always + straightforward. We have attempted to formalise the original proof + by Sulzmann and Lu \cite{Sulzmann2014}, but we believe it contains + unfillable gaps. In the online version of \cite{Sulzmann2014}, the authors + already acknowledge some small problems, but our experience suggests + that there are more serious problems. + + Having proved the correctness of the POSIX lexing algorithm in + \cite{Sulzmann2014}, which lessons have we learned? Well, this is a + perfect example for the importance of the \emph{right} definitions. We + have (on and off) explored mechanisations as soon as first versions + of \cite{Sulzmann2014} appeared, but have made little progress with + turning the relatively detailed proof sketch in \cite{Sulzmann2014} into a + formalisable proof. Having seen \cite{Vansummeren2006} and adapted the + POSIX definition given there for the algorithm by Sulzmann and Lu made all + the difference: the proofs, as said, are nearly straightforward. The + question remains whether the original proof idea of \cite{Sulzmann2014}, + potentially using our result as a stepping stone, can be made to work? + Alas, we really do not know despite considerable effort. + + + Closely related to our work is an automata-based lexer formalised by + Nipkow \cite{Nipkow98}. This lexer also splits up strings into longest + initial substrings, but Nipkow's algorithm is not completely + computational. The algorithm by Sulzmann and Lu, in contrast, can be + implemented with ease in any functional language. A bespoke lexer for the + Imp-language is formalised in Coq as part of the Software Foundations book + by Pierce et al \cite{Pierce2015}. The disadvantage of such bespoke lexers is that they + do not generalise easily to more advanced features. + Our formalisation is available from the Archive of Formal Proofs \cite{aduAFP16} + under \url{http://www.isa-afp.org/entries/Posix-Lexing.shtml}.\medskip + + \noindent + {\bf Acknowledgements:} + We are very grateful to Martin Sulzmann for his comments on our work and + moreover for patiently explaining to us the details in \cite{Sulzmann2014}. We + also received very helpful comments from James Cheney and anonymous referees. + % \small + \bibliographystyle{plain} + \bibliography{root} + +*} + + +(*<*) +end +(*>*) \ No newline at end of file