(*<*)theory Paperimports "../ReStar" "../Simplifying" "../Sulzmann" "~~/src/HOL/Library/LaTeXsugar"begindeclare [[show_question_marks = false]]abbreviation "der_syn r c \<equiv> der c r"abbreviation "ders_syn r s \<equiv> ders s r"notation (latex output) If ("(\<^raw:\textrm{>if\<^raw:}> (_)/ \<^raw:\textrm{>then\<^raw:}> (_)/ \<^raw:\textrm{>else\<^raw:}> (_))" 10) and Cons ("_\<^raw:\mbox{$\,$}>::\<^raw:\mbox{$\,$}>_" [75,73] 73) and ZERO ("\<^bold>0" 78) and ONE ("\<^bold>1" 78) and CHAR ("_" [1000] 80) and ALT ("_ + _" [77,77] 78) and SEQ ("_ \<cdot> _" [77,77] 78) and STAR ("_\<^sup>\<star>" [1000] 78) and val.Void ("'(')" 79) and val.Char ("Char _" [1000] 78) and val.Left ("Left _" [79] 78) and val.Right ("Right _" [79] 78) and val.Seq ("Seq _ _" [79,79] 78) and val.Stars ("Stars _" [79] 78) and L ("L'(_')" [10] 78) and der_syn ("_\\_" [79, 1000] 76) and ders_syn ("_\\_" [79, 1000] 76) and flat ("|_|" [75] 74) and Sequ ("_ @ _" [78,77] 63) and injval ("inj _ _ _" [79,77,79] 76) and mkeps ("mkeps _" [79] 76) and length ("len _" [73] 73) and Prf ("_ : _" [75,75] 75) and Posix ("'(_, _') \<rightarrow> _" [63,75,75] 75) and lexer ("lexer _ _" [78,78] 77) and F_RIGHT ("F\<^bsub>Right\<^esub> _") and F_LEFT ("F\<^bsub>Left\<^esub> _") and F_ALT ("F\<^bsub>Alt\<^esub> _ _") and F_SEQ1 ("F\<^bsub>Seq1\<^esub> _ _") and F_SEQ2 ("F\<^bsub>Seq2\<^esub> _ _") and F_SEQ ("F\<^bsub>Seq\<^esub> _ _") and simp_SEQ ("simp\<^bsub>Seq\<^esub> _ _" [1000, 1000] 1) and simp_ALT ("simp\<^bsub>Alt\<^esub> _ _" [1000, 1000] 1) and slexer ("lexer\<^sup>+ _ _" [78,78] 77) and ValOrd ("_ >\<^bsub>_\<^esub> _" [77,77,77] 77) and ValOrdEq ("_ \<ge>\<^bsub>_\<^esub> _" [77,77,77] 77)definition "match r s \<equiv> nullable (ders s r)"(*>*)section {* Introduction *}text {*Brzozowski \cite{Brzozowski1964} introduced the notion of the {\emderivative} @{term "der c r"} of a regular expression @{text r} w.r.t.\ acharacter~@{text c}, and showed that it gave a simple solution to theproblem of matching a string @{term s} with a regular expression @{term r}:if the derivative of @{term r} w.r.t.\ (in succession) all the characters ofthe string matches the empty string, then @{term r} matches @{term s} (and{\em vice versa}). The derivative has the property (which may almost beregarded as its specification) that, for every string @{term s} and regularexpression @{term r} and character @{term c}, one has @{term "cs \<in> L(r)"} ifand only if \mbox{@{term "s \<in> L(der c r)"}}. The beauty of Brzozowski'sderivatives is that they are neatly expressible in any functional language,and easily definable and reasoned about in theorem provers---the definitionsjust consist of inductive datatypes and simple recursive functions. Acompletely formalised correctness proof of this matcher in for example HOL4has been mentioned in~\cite{Owens2008}. Another one in Isabelle/HOL is partof the work in \cite{Krauss2011}.One limitation of Brzozowski's matcher is that it only generates a YES/NOanswer for whether a string is being matched by a regular expression.Sulzmann and Lu \cite{Sulzmann2014} extended this matcher to allowgeneration not just of a YES/NO answer but of an actual matching, called a[lexical] {\em value}. They give a simple algorithm to calculate a valuethat appears to be the value associated with POSIX matching\cite{Kuklewicz,Vansummeren2006}. The challenge then is to specify thatvalue, in an algorithm-independent fashion, and to show that Sulzmann andLu's derivative-based algorithm does indeed calculate a value that iscorrect according to the specification.The answer given by Sulzmann and Lu \cite{Sulzmann2014} is to define arelation (called an ``order relation'') on the set of values of @{term r},and to show that (once a string to be matched is chosen) there is a maximumelement and that it is computed by their derivative-based algorithm. Thisproof idea is inspired by work of Frisch and Cardelli \cite{Frisch2004} on aGREEDY regular expression matching algorithm. Beginning with ourobservations that, without evidence that it is transitive, it cannot becalled an ``order relation'', and that the relation is called a ``totalorder'' despite being evidently not total\footnote{The relation @{text"\<ge>\<^bsub>r\<^esub>"} defined in \cite{Sulzmann2014} is a relation on thevalues for the regular expression @{term r}; but it only holds between@{term v} and @{term "v'"} in cases where @{term v} and @{term "v'"} havethe same flattening (underlying string). So a counterexample to totality isgiven by taking two values @{term v} and @{term "v'"} for @{term r} thathave different flattenings (see Section~\ref{posixsec}). A differentrelation @{text "\<ge>\<^bsub>r,s\<^esub>"} on the set of values for @{term r}with flattening @{term s} is definable by the same approach, and is indeedtotal; but that is not what Proposition 1 of \cite{Sulzmann2014} does.}, weidentify problems with this approach (of which some of the proofs are notpublished in \cite{Sulzmann2014}); perhaps more importantly, we give asimple inductive (and algorithm-independent) definition of what we callbeing a {\em POSIX value} for a regular expression @{term r} and a string@{term s}; we show that the algorithm computes such a value and that such avalue is unique. Proofs are both done by hand and checked in Isabelle/HOL.The experience of doing our proofs has been that this mechanical checkingwas absolutely essential: this subject area has hidden snares. This was alsonoted by Kuklewitz \cite{Kuklewicz} who found that nearly all POSIX matchingimplementations are ``buggy'' \cite[Page 203]{Sulzmann2014}.If a regular expression matches a string, then in general there is more thanone way of how the string is matched. There are two commonly useddisambiguation strategies to generate a unique answer: one is called GREEDYmatching \cite{Frisch2004} and the other is POSIXmatching~\cite{Kuklewicz,Sulzmann2014,Vansummeren2006}. For example considerthe string @{term xy} and the regular expression \mbox{@{term "STAR (ALT(ALT x y) xy)"}}. Either the string can be matched in two `iterations' bythe single letter-regular expressions @{term x} and @{term y}, or directlyin one iteration by @{term xy}. The first case corresponds to GREEDYmatching, which first matches with the left-most symbol and only matches thenext symbol in case of a mismatch (this is greedy in the sense of preferringinstant gratification to delayed repletion). The second case is POSIXmatching, which prefers the longest match.In the context of lexing, where an input string needs to be split up into asequence of tokens, POSIX is the more natural disambiguation strategy forwhat programmers consider basic syntactic building blocks in their programs.These building blocks are often specified by some regular expressions, say@{text "r\<^bsub>key\<^esub>"} and @{text "r\<^bsub>id\<^esub>"} for recognising keywords andidentifiers, respectively. There are two underlying (informal) rules behindtokenising a string in a POSIX fashion according to a collection of regularexpressions:\begin{itemize} \item[$\bullet$] \underline{The Longest Match Rule (or ``maximal munch rule''):}The longest initial substring matched by any regular expression is taken asnext token.\smallskip\item[$\bullet$] \underline{Priority Rule:}For a particular longest initial substring, the first regular expressionthat can match determines the token.\end{itemize}\noindent Consider for example @{text "r\<^bsub>key\<^esub>"} recognising keywords such as@{text "if"}, @{text "then"} and so on; and @{text "r\<^bsub>id\<^esub>"} recognisingidentifiers (say, a single character followed by characters or numbers).Then we can form the regular expression @{text "(r\<^bsub>key\<^esub> + r\<^bsub>id\<^esub>)\<^sup>\<star>"} and usePOSIX matching to tokenise strings, say @{text "iffoo"} and @{text "if"}.For @{text "iffoo"} we obtain by the longest match rule a single identifiertoken, not a keyword followed by an identifier. For @{text "if"} we obtain bythe priority rule a keyword token, not an identifier token---even if @{text"r\<^bsub>id\<^esub>"} matches also.\bigskip\noindent {\bf Contributions:} We have implemented in Isabelle/HOL thederivative-based regular expression matching algorithm ofSulzmann and Lu \cite{Sulzmann2014}. We have proved the correctness of thisalgorithm according to our specification of what a POSIX value is. Sulzmannand Lu sketch in \cite{Sulzmann2014} an informal correctness proof: but tous it contains unfillable gaps.\footnote{An extended version of\cite{Sulzmann2014} is available at the website of its first author; thisextended version already includes remarks in the appendix that theirinformal proof contains gaps, and possible fixes are not fully worked out.}Our specification of a POSIX value consists of a simple inductive definitionthat given a string and a regular expression uniquely determines this value.Derivatives as calculated by Brzozowski's method are usually more complexregular expressions than the initial one; various optimisations arepossible. We prove the correctness when simplifications of @{term "ALT ZEROr"}, @{term "ALT r ZERO"}, @{term "SEQ ONE r"} and @{term "SEQ r ONE"} to@{term r} are applied.*}section {* Preliminaries *}text {* \noindent Strings in Isabelle/HOL are lists of characters with theempty string being represented by the empty list, written @{term "[]"}, andlist-cons being written as @{term "DUMMY # DUMMY"}. Often we use the usualbracket notation for lists also for strings; for example a string consistingof just a single character @{term c} is written @{term "[c]"}. By using thetype @{type char} for characters we have a supply of finitely manycharacters roughly corresponding to the ASCII character set. Regularexpressions are defined as usual as the elements of the following inductivedatatype: \begin{center} @{text "r :="} @{const "ZERO"} $\mid$ @{const "ONE"} $\mid$ @{term "CHAR c"} $\mid$ @{term "ALT r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2"} $\mid$ @{term "SEQ r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2"} $\mid$ @{term "STAR r"} \end{center} \noindent where @{const ZERO} stands for the regular expression that does not match any string, @{const ONE} for the regular expression that matches only the empty string and @{term c} for matching a character literal. The language of a regular expression is also defined as usual by the recursive function @{term L} with the clauses: \begin{center} \begin{tabular}{l@ {\hspace{5mm}}rcl} (1) & @{thm (lhs) L.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) L.simps(1)}\\ (2) & @{thm (lhs) L.simps(2)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) L.simps(2)}\\ (3) & @{thm (lhs) L.simps(3)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) L.simps(3)}\\ (4) & @{thm (lhs) L.simps(4)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) L.simps(4)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]}\\ (5) & @{thm (lhs) L.simps(5)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) L.simps(5)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]}\\ (6) & @{thm (lhs) L.simps(6)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) L.simps(6)}\\ \end{tabular} \end{center} \noindent In clause (4) we use the operation @{term "DUMMY ;; DUMMY"} for the concatenation of two languages (it is also list-append for strings). We use the star-notation for regular expressions and for languages (in the last clause above). The star for languages is defined inductively by two clauses: @{text "(i)"} the empty string being in the star of a language and @{text "(ii)"} if @{term "s\<^sub>1"} is in a language and @{term "s\<^sub>2"} in the star of this language, then also @{term "s\<^sub>1 @ s\<^sub>2"} is in the star of this language. It will also be convenient to use the following notion of a \emph{semantic derivative} (or \emph{left quotient}) of a language defined as: \begin{center} \begin{tabular}{lcl} @{thm (lhs) Der_def} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) Der_def}\\ \end{tabular} \end{center} \noindent For semantic derivatives we have the following equations (for example mechanically proved in \cite{Krauss2011}): \begin{equation}\label{SemDer} \begin{array}{lcl} @{thm (lhs) Der_null} & \dn & @{thm (rhs) Der_null}\\ @{thm (lhs) Der_empty} & \dn & @{thm (rhs) Der_empty}\\ @{thm (lhs) Der_char} & \dn & @{thm (rhs) Der_char}\\ @{thm (lhs) Der_union} & \dn & @{thm (rhs) Der_union}\\ @{thm (lhs) Der_Sequ} & \dn & @{thm (rhs) Der_Sequ}\\ @{thm (lhs) Der_star} & \dn & @{thm (rhs) Der_star} \end{array} \end{equation} \noindent \emph{\Brz's derivatives} of regular expressions \cite{Brzozowski1964} can be easily defined by two recursive functions: the first is from regular expressions to booleans (implementing a test when a regular expression can match the empty string), and the second takes a regular expression and a character to a (derivative) regular expression: \begin{center} \begin{tabular}{lcl} @{thm (lhs) nullable.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) nullable.simps(1)}\\ @{thm (lhs) nullable.simps(2)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) nullable.simps(2)}\\ @{thm (lhs) nullable.simps(3)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) nullable.simps(3)}\\ @{thm (lhs) nullable.simps(4)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) nullable.simps(4)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]}\\ @{thm (lhs) nullable.simps(5)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) nullable.simps(5)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]}\\ @{thm (lhs) nullable.simps(6)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) nullable.simps(6)}\medskip\\ \end{tabular} \end{center} \begin{center} \begin{tabular}{lcl} @{thm (lhs) der.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) der.simps(1)}\\ @{thm (lhs) der.simps(2)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) der.simps(2)}\\ @{thm (lhs) der.simps(3)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) der.simps(3)}\\ @{thm (lhs) der.simps(4)[of c "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) der.simps(4)[of c "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]}\\ @{thm (lhs) der.simps(5)[of c "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) der.simps(5)[of c "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]}\\ @{thm (lhs) der.simps(6)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) der.simps(6)} \end{tabular} \end{center} \noindent We may extend this definition to give derivatives w.r.t.~strings: \begin{center} \begin{tabular}{lcl} @{thm (lhs) ders.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) ders.simps(1)}\\ @{thm (lhs) ders.simps(2)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) ders.simps(2)}\\ \end{tabular} \end{center} \noindent Given the equations in \eqref{SemDer}, it is a relatively easy exercise in mechanical reasoning to establish that \begin{proposition}\label{derprop}\mbox{}\\ \begin{tabular}{ll} @{text "(1)"} & @{thm (lhs) nullable_correctness} if and only if @{thm (rhs) nullable_correctness}, and \\ @{text "(2)"} & @{thm[mode=IfThen] der_correctness}. \end{tabular} \end{proposition} \noindent With this in place it is also very routine to prove that the regular expression matcher defined as \begin{center} @{thm match_def} \end{center} \noindent gives a positive answer if and only if @{term "s \<in> L r"}. Consequently, this regular expression matching algorithm satisfies the usual specification for regular expression matching. While the matcher above calculates a provably correct YES/NO answer for whether a regular expression matches a string or not, the novel idea of Sulzmann and Lu \cite{Sulzmann2014} is to append another phase to this algorithm in order to calculate a [lexical] value. We will explain the details next.*}section {* POSIX Regular Expression Matching\label{posixsec} *}text {* The clever idea in \cite{Sulzmann2014} is to introduce values for encoding \emph{how} a regular expression matches a string and then define a function on values that mirrors (but inverts) the construction of the derivative on regular expressions. \emph{Values} are defined as the inductive datatype \begin{center} @{text "v :="} @{const "Void"} $\mid$ @{term "val.Char c"} $\mid$ @{term "Left v"} $\mid$ @{term "Right v"} $\mid$ @{term "Seq v\<^sub>1 v\<^sub>2"} $\mid$ @{term "Stars vs"} \end{center} \noindent where we use @{term vs} to stand for a list of values. (This is similar to the approach taken by Frisch and Cardelli for GREEDY matching \cite{Frisch2004}, and Sulzmann and Lu \cite{Sulzmann2014} for POSIX matching). The string underlying a value can be calculated by the @{const flat} function, written @{term "flat DUMMY"} and defined as: \begin{center} \begin{tabular}{lcl} @{thm (lhs) flat.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) flat.simps(1)}\\ @{thm (lhs) flat.simps(2)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) flat.simps(2)}\\ @{thm (lhs) flat.simps(3)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) flat.simps(3)}\\ @{thm (lhs) flat.simps(4)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) flat.simps(4)}\\ @{thm (lhs) flat.simps(5)[of "v\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>2"]} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) flat.simps(5)[of "v\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>2"]}\\ @{thm (lhs) flat.simps(6)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) flat.simps(6)}\\ @{thm (lhs) flat.simps(7)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) flat.simps(7)}\\ \end{tabular} \end{center} \noindent Sulzmann and Lu also define inductively an inhabitation relation that associates values to regular expressions: \begin{center} \begin{tabular}{c} @{thm[mode=Axiom] Prf.intros(4)} \qquad @{thm[mode=Axiom] Prf.intros(5)[of "c"]}\smallskip\\ @{thm[mode=Rule] Prf.intros(2)[of "v\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]} \qquad @{thm[mode=Rule] Prf.intros(3)[of "v\<^sub>2" "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]}\smallskip\\ @{thm[mode=Rule] Prf.intros(1)[of "v\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>2" "r\<^sub>2"]}\smallskip\\ @{thm[mode=Axiom] Prf.intros(6)[of "r"]} \qquad @{thm[mode=Rule] Prf.intros(7)[of "v" "r" "vs"]} \end{tabular} \end{center} \noindent Note that no values are associated with the regular expression @{term ZERO}, and that the only value associated with the regular expression @{term ONE} is @{term Void}, pronounced (if one must) as @{text "Void"}. It is routine to establish how values ``inhabiting'' a regular expression correspond to the language of a regular expression, namely \begin{proposition} @{thm L_flat_Prf} \end{proposition} In general there is more than one value associated with a regular expression. In case of POSIX matching the problem is to calculate the unique value that satisfies the (informal) POSIX rules from the Introduction. Graphically the POSIX value calculation algorithm by Sulzmann and Lu can be illustrated by the picture in Figure~\ref{Sulz} where the path from the left to the right involving @{term derivatives}/@{const nullable} is the first phase of the algorithm (calculating successive \Brz's derivatives) and @{const mkeps}/@{text inj}, the path from right to left, the second phase. This picture shows the steps required when a regular expression, say @{text "r\<^sub>1"}, matches the string @{term "[a,b,c]"}. We first build the three derivatives (according to @{term a}, @{term b} and @{term c}). We then use @{const nullable} to find out whether the resulting derivative regular expression @{term "r\<^sub>4"} can match the empty string. If yes, we call the function @{const mkeps} that produces a value @{term "v\<^sub>4"} for how @{term "r\<^sub>4"} can match the empty string (taking into account the POSIX constraints in case there are several ways). This functions is defined by the clauses:\begin{figure}[t]\begin{center}\begin{tikzpicture}[scale=2,node distance=1.3cm, every node/.style={minimum size=7mm}]\node (r1) {@{term "r\<^sub>1"}};\node (r2) [right=of r1]{@{term "r\<^sub>2"}};\draw[->,line width=1mm](r1)--(r2) node[above,midway] {@{term "der a DUMMY"}};\node (r3) [right=of r2]{@{term "r\<^sub>3"}};\draw[->,line width=1mm](r2)--(r3) node[above,midway] {@{term "der b DUMMY"}};\node (r4) [right=of r3]{@{term "r\<^sub>4"}};\draw[->,line width=1mm](r3)--(r4) node[above,midway] {@{term "der c DUMMY"}};\draw (r4) node[anchor=west] {\;\raisebox{3mm}{@{term nullable}}};\node (v4) [below=of r4]{@{term "v\<^sub>4"}};\draw[->,line width=1mm](r4) -- (v4);\node (v3) [left=of v4] {@{term "v\<^sub>3"}};\draw[->,line width=1mm](v4)--(v3) node[below,midway] {@{text "inj r\<^sub>3 c"}};\node (v2) [left=of v3]{@{term "v\<^sub>2"}};\draw[->,line width=1mm](v3)--(v2) node[below,midway] {@{text "inj r\<^sub>2 b"}};\node (v1) [left=of v2] {@{term "v\<^sub>1"}};\draw[->,line width=1mm](v2)--(v1) node[below,midway] {@{text "inj r\<^sub>1 a"}};\draw (r4) node[anchor=north west] {\;\raisebox{-8mm}{@{term "mkeps"}}};\end{tikzpicture}\end{center}\caption{The two phases of the algorithm by Sulzmann \& Lu \cite{Sulzmann2014},matching the string @{term "[a,b,c]"}. The first phase (the arrows from left to right) is \Brz's matcher building successive derivatives. If the last regular expression is @{term nullable}, then the functions of the second phase are called (the top-down and right-to-left arrows): first @{term mkeps} calculates a value witnessinghow the empty string has been recognised by @{term "r\<^sub>4"}. Afterthat the function @{term inj} ``injects back'' the characters of the string intothe values.\label{Sulz}}\end{figure} \begin{center} \begin{tabular}{lcl} @{thm (lhs) mkeps.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) mkeps.simps(1)}\\ @{thm (lhs) mkeps.simps(2)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) mkeps.simps(2)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]}\\ @{thm (lhs) mkeps.simps(3)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) mkeps.simps(3)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]}\\ @{thm (lhs) mkeps.simps(4)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) mkeps.simps(4)}\\ \end{tabular} \end{center} \noindent Note that this function needs only to be partially defined, namely only for regular expressions that are nullable. In case @{const nullable} fails, the string @{term "[a,b,c]"} cannot be matched by @{term "r\<^sub>1"} and an error is raised instead. Note also how this function makes some subtle choices leading to a POSIX value: for example if an alternative regular expression, say @{term "ALT r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2"}, can match the empty string and furthermore @{term "r\<^sub>1"} can match the empty string, then we return a @{text Left}-value. The @{text Right}-value will only be returned if @{term "r\<^sub>1"} cannot match the empty string. The most interesting idea from Sulzmann and Lu \cite{Sulzmann2014} is the construction of a value for how @{term "r\<^sub>1"} can match the string @{term "[a,b,c]"} from the value how the last derivative, @{term "r\<^sub>4"} in Fig~\ref{Sulz}, can match the empty string. Sulzmann and Lu achieve this by stepwise ``injecting back'' the characters into the values thus inverting the operation of building derivatives, but on the level of values. The corresponding function, called @{term inj}, takes three arguments, a regular expression, a character and a value. For example in the first (or right-most) @{term inj}-step in Fig~\ref{Sulz} the regular expression @{term "r\<^sub>3"}, the character @{term c} from the last derivative step and @{term "v\<^sub>4"}, which is the value corresponding to the derivative regular expression @{term "r\<^sub>4"}. The result is the new value @{term "v\<^sub>3"}. The final result of the algorithm is the value @{term "v\<^sub>1"}. The @{term inj} function is defined by recursion on regular expressions and by analysing the shape of values (corresponding to the derivative regular expressions). % \begin{center} \begin{tabular}{l@ {\hspace{5mm}}lcl} (1) & @{thm (lhs) injval.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) injval.simps(1)}\\ (2) & @{thm (lhs) injval.simps(2)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2" "c" "v\<^sub>1"]} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) injval.simps(2)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2" "c" "v\<^sub>1"]}\\ (3) & @{thm (lhs) injval.simps(3)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2" "c" "v\<^sub>2"]} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) injval.simps(3)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2" "c" "v\<^sub>2"]}\\ (4) & @{thm (lhs) injval.simps(4)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2" "c" "v\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>2"]} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) injval.simps(4)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2" "c" "v\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>2"]}\\ (5) & @{thm (lhs) injval.simps(5)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2" "c" "v\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>2"]} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) injval.simps(5)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2" "c" "v\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>2"]}\\ (6) & @{thm (lhs) injval.simps(6)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2" "c" "v\<^sub>2"]} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) injval.simps(6)[of "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2" "c" "v\<^sub>2"]}\\ (7) & @{thm (lhs) injval.simps(7)[of "r" "c" "v" "vs"]} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) injval.simps(7)[of "r" "c" "v" "vs"]}\\ \end{tabular} \end{center} \noindent To better understand what is going on in this definition it might be instructive to look first at the three sequence cases (clauses (4)--(6)). In each case we need to construct an ``injected value'' for @{term "SEQ r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2"}. This must be a value of the form @{term "Seq DUMMY DUMMY"}. Recall the clause of the @{text derivative}-function for sequence regular expressions: \begin{center} @{thm (lhs) der.simps(5)[of c "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]} $\dn$ @{thm (rhs) der.simps(5)[of c "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]} \end{center} \noindent Consider first the @{text "else"}-branch where the derivative is @{term "SEQ (der c r\<^sub>1) r\<^sub>2"}. The corresponding value must therefore be the form @{term "Seq v\<^sub>1 v\<^sub>2"}, which matches the left-hand side in clause~(4) of @{term inj}. In the @{text "if"}-branch the derivative is an alternative, namely @{term "ALT (SEQ (der c r\<^sub>1) r\<^sub>2) (der c r\<^sub>2)"}. This means we either have to consider a @{text Left}- or @{text Right}-value. In case of the @{text Left}-value we know further it must be a value for a sequence regular expression. Therefore the pattern we match in the clause (5) is @{term "Left (Seq v\<^sub>1 v\<^sub>2)"}, while in (6) it is just @{term "Right v\<^sub>2"}. One more interesting point is in the right-hand side of clause (6): since in this case the regular expression @{text "r\<^sub>1"} does not ``contribute'' to matching the string, that means it only matches the empty string, we need to call @{const mkeps} in order to construct a value for how @{term "r\<^sub>1"} can match this empty string. A similar argument applies for why we can expect in the left-hand side of clause (7) that the value is of the form @{term "Seq v (Stars vs)"}---the derivative of a star is @{term "SEQ (der c r) (STAR r)"}. Finally, the reason for why we can ignore the second argument in clause (1) of @{term inj} is that it will only ever be called in cases where @{term "c=d"}, but the usual linearity restrictions in patterns do not allow us to build this constraint explicitly into our function definition.\footnote{Sulzmann and Lu state this clause as @{thm (lhs) injval.simps(1)[of "c" "c"]} $\dn$ @{thm (rhs) injval.simps(1)[of "c"]}, but our deviation is harmless.} The idea of the @{term inj}-function to ``inject'' a character, say @{term c}, into a value can be made precise by the first part of the following lemma, which shows that the underlying string of an injected value has a prepended character @{term c}; the second part shows that the underlying string of an @{const mkeps}-value is always the empty string (given the regular expression is nullable since otherwise @{text mkeps} might not be defined). \begin{lemma}\mbox{}\smallskip\\\label{Prf_injval_flat} \begin{tabular}{ll} (1) & @{thm[mode=IfThen] Prf_injval_flat}\\ (2) & @{thm[mode=IfThen] mkeps_flat} \end{tabular} \end{lemma} \begin{proof} Both properties are by routine inductions: the first one can, for example, be proved by an induction over the definition of @{term derivatives}; the second by an induction on @{term r}. There are no interesting cases.\qed \end{proof} Having defined the @{const mkeps} and @{text inj} function we can extend \Brz's matcher so that a [lexical] value is constructed (assuming the regular expression matches the string). The clauses of the Sulzmann and Lu lexer are \begin{center} \begin{tabular}{lcl} @{thm (lhs) lexer.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) lexer.simps(1)}\\ @{thm (lhs) lexer.simps(2)} & $\dn$ & @{text "case"} @{term "lexer (der c r) s"} @{text of}\\ & & \phantom{$|$} @{term "None"} @{text "\<Rightarrow>"} @{term None}\\ & & $|$ @{term "Some v"} @{text "\<Rightarrow>"} @{term "Some (injval r c v)"} \end{tabular} \end{center} \noindent If the regular expression does not match the string, @{const None} is returned, indicating an error is raised. If the regular expression \emph{does} match the string, then @{const Some} value is returned. One important virtue of this algorithm is that it can be implemented with ease in any functional programming language and also in Isabelle/HOL. In the remaining part of this section we prove that this algorithm is correct. The well-known idea of POSIX matching is informally defined by the longest match and priority rule (see Introduction); as correctly argued in \cite{Sulzmann2014}, this needs formal specification. Sulzmann and Lu define a \emph{dominance} relation\footnote{Sulzmann and Lu call it an ordering relation, but without giving evidence that it is transitive.} between values and argue that there is a maximum value, as given by the derivative-based algorithm. In contrast, we shall introduce a simple inductive definition that specifies directly what a \emph{POSIX value} is, incorporating the POSIX-specific choices into the side-conditions of our rules. Our definition is inspired by the matching relation given in \cite{Vansummeren2006}. The relation we define is ternary and written as \mbox{@{term "s \<in> r \<rightarrow> v"}}, relating strings, regular expressions and values. \begin{center} \begin{tabular}{c} @{thm[mode=Axiom] Posix.intros(1)}@{text "P"}@{term "ONE"} \qquad @{thm[mode=Axiom] Posix.intros(2)}@{text "P"}@{term "c"}\bigskip\\ @{thm[mode=Rule] Posix.intros(3)[of "s" "r\<^sub>1" "v" "r\<^sub>2"]}@{text "P+L"}\qquad @{thm[mode=Rule] Posix.intros(4)[of "s" "r\<^sub>2" "v" "r\<^sub>1"]}@{text "P+R"}\bigskip\\ $\mprset{flushleft} \inferrule {@{thm (prem 1) Posix.intros(5)[of "s\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>1" "s\<^sub>2" "r\<^sub>2" "v\<^sub>2"]} \qquad @{thm (prem 2) Posix.intros(5)[of "s\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>1" "s\<^sub>2" "r\<^sub>2" "v\<^sub>2"]} \\\\ @{thm (prem 3) Posix.intros(5)[of "s\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>1" "s\<^sub>2" "r\<^sub>2" "v\<^sub>2"]}} {@{thm (concl) Posix.intros(5)[of "s\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>1" "s\<^sub>2" "r\<^sub>2" "v\<^sub>2"]}}$@{text "PS"}\\ @{thm[mode=Axiom] Posix.intros(7)}@{text "P[]"}\bigskip\\ $\mprset{flushleft} \inferrule {@{thm (prem 1) Posix.intros(6)[of "s\<^sub>1" "r" "v" "s\<^sub>2" "vs"]} \qquad @{thm (prem 2) Posix.intros(6)[of "s\<^sub>1" "r" "v" "s\<^sub>2" "vs"]} \qquad @{thm (prem 3) Posix.intros(6)[of "s\<^sub>1" "r" "v" "s\<^sub>2" "vs"]} \\\\ @{thm (prem 4) Posix.intros(6)[of "s\<^sub>1" "r" "v" "s\<^sub>2" "vs"]}} {@{thm (concl) Posix.intros(6)[of "s\<^sub>1" "r" "v" "s\<^sub>2" "vs"]}}$@{text "P\<star>"} \end{tabular} \end{center} \noindent We claim that this relation captures the idea behind the two informal POSIX rules shown in the Introduction: Consider for example the rules @{text "P+L"} and @{text "P+R"} where the POSIX value for a string and an alternative regular expression, that is @{term "(s, ALT r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2)"}, is specified---it is always a @{text "Left"}-value, \emph{except} when the string to be matched is not in the language of @{term "r\<^sub>1"}; only then it is a @{text Right}-value (see the side-condition in @{text "P+R"}). Interesting is also the rule for sequence regular expressions (@{text "PS"}). The first two premises state that @{term "v\<^sub>1"} and @{term "v\<^sub>2"} are the POSIX values for @{term "(s\<^sub>1, r\<^sub>1)"} and @{term "(s\<^sub>2, r\<^sub>2)"} respectively. Consider now the third premise and note that the POSIX value of this rule should match the string @{term "s\<^sub>1 @ s\<^sub>2"}. According to the longest match rule, we want that the @{term "s\<^sub>1"} is the longest initial split of \mbox{@{term "s\<^sub>1 @ s\<^sub>2"}} such that @{term "s\<^sub>2"} is still recognised by @{term "r\<^sub>2"}. Let us assume, contrary to the third premise, that there \emph{exist} an @{term "s\<^sub>3"} and @{term "s\<^sub>4"} such that @{term "s\<^sub>2"} can be split up into a non-empty string @{term "s\<^sub>3"} and a possibly empty string @{term "s\<^sub>4"}. Moreover the longer string @{term "s\<^sub>1 @ s\<^sub>3"} can be matched by @{text "r\<^sub>1"} and the shorter @{term "s\<^sub>4"} can still be matched by @{term "r\<^sub>2"}. In this case @{term "s\<^sub>1"} would \emph{not} be the longest initial split of \mbox{@{term "s\<^sub>1 @ s\<^sub>2"}} and therefore @{term "Seq v\<^sub>1 v\<^sub>2"} cannot be a POSIX value for @{term "(s\<^sub>1 @ s\<^sub>2, SEQ r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2)"}. The main point is that this side-condition ensures the longest match rule is satisfied. A similar condition is imposed on the POSIX value in the @{text "P\<star>"}-rule. Also there we want that @{term "s\<^sub>1"} is the longest initial split of @{term "s\<^sub>1 @ s\<^sub>2"} and furthermore the corresponding value @{term v} cannot be flattened to the empty string. In effect, we require that in each ``iteration'' of the star, some non-empty substring needs to be ``chipped'' away; only in case of the empty string we accept @{term "Stars []"} as the POSIX value. We can prove that given a string @{term s} and regular expression @{term r}, the POSIX value @{term v} is uniquely determined by @{term "s \<in> r \<rightarrow> v"}. \begin{theorem} @{thm[mode=IfThen] Posix_determ(1)[of _ _ "v\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>2"]} \end{theorem} \begin{proof} By induction on the definition of @{term "s \<in> r \<rightarrow> v\<^sub>1"} and a case analysis of @{term "s \<in> r \<rightarrow> v\<^sub>2"}. This proof requires the auxiliary lemma that @{thm (prem 1) Posix1(1)} implies @{thm (concl) Posix1(1)} and @{thm (concl) Posix1(2)}, which are both easily established by inductions.\qed \end{proof} \noindent Next is the lemma that shows the function @{term "mkeps"} calculates the POSIX value for the empty string and a nullable regular expression. \begin{lemma}\label{lemmkeps} @{thm[mode=IfThen] Posix_mkeps} \end{lemma} \begin{proof} By routine induction on @{term r}.\qed \end{proof} \noindent The central lemma for our POSIX relation is that the @{text inj}-function preserves POSIX values. \begin{lemma}\label{Posix2} @{thm[mode=IfThen] Posix2_roy_version} \end{lemma} \begin{proof} By induction on @{text r}. Suppose @{term "r = ALT r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2"}. There are two subcases, namely @{text "(a)"} \mbox{@{term "v = Left v'"}} and @{term "s \<in> der c r\<^sub>1 \<rightarrow> v'"}; and @{text "(b)"} @{term "v = Right v'"}, @{term "s \<notin> L (der c r\<^sub>1)"} and @{term "s \<in> der c r\<^sub>2 \<rightarrow> v'"}. In @{text "(a)"} we know @{term "s \<in> der c r\<^sub>1 \<rightarrow> v'"}, from which we can infer @{term "(c # s) \<in> r\<^sub>1 \<rightarrow> injval r\<^sub>1 c v'"} by induction hypothesis and hence @{term "(c # s) \<in> ALT r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2 \<rightarrow> injval (ALT r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2) c (Left v')"} as needed. Similarly in subcase @{text "(b)"} where, however, in addition we have to use Prop.~\ref{derprop}(2) in order to infer @{term "c # s \<notin> L r\<^sub>1"} from @{term "s \<notin> L (der c r\<^sub>1)"}. Suppose @{term "r = SEQ r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2"}. There are three subcases: \begin{quote} \begin{description} \item[@{text "(a)"}] @{term "v = Left (Seq v\<^sub>1 v\<^sub>2)"} and @{term "nullable r\<^sub>1"} \item[@{text "(b)"}] @{term "v = Right v\<^sub>1"} and @{term "nullable r\<^sub>1"} \item[@{text "(c)"}] @{term "v = Seq v\<^sub>1 v\<^sub>2"} and @{term "\<not> nullable r\<^sub>1"} \end{description} \end{quote} \noindent For @{text "(a)"} we know @{term "s\<^sub>1 \<in> der c r\<^sub>1 \<rightarrow> v\<^sub>1"} and @{term "s\<^sub>2 \<in> r\<^sub>2 \<rightarrow> v\<^sub>2"} as well as \[@{term "\<not> (\<exists>s\<^sub>3 s\<^sub>4. s\<^sub>3 \<noteq> [] \<and> s\<^sub>3 @ s\<^sub>4 = s\<^sub>2 \<and> s\<^sub>1 @ s\<^sub>3 \<in> L (der c r\<^sub>1) \<and> s\<^sub>4 \<in> L r\<^sub>2)"}\] \noindent From the latter we can infer by Prop.~\ref{derprop}(2): \[@{term "\<not> (\<exists>s\<^sub>3 s\<^sub>4. s\<^sub>3 \<noteq> [] \<and> s\<^sub>3 @ s\<^sub>4 = s\<^sub>2 \<and> (c # s\<^sub>1) @ s\<^sub>3 \<in> L r\<^sub>1 \<and> s\<^sub>4 \<in> L r\<^sub>2)"}\] \noindent We can use the induction hypothesis for @{text "r\<^sub>1"} to obtain @{term "(c # s\<^sub>1) \<in> r\<^sub>1 \<rightarrow> injval r\<^sub>1 c v\<^sub>1"}. Putting this all together allows us to infer @{term "((c # s\<^sub>1) @ s\<^sub>2) \<in> SEQ r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2 \<rightarrow> Seq (injval r\<^sub>1 c v\<^sub>1) v\<^sub>2"}. The case @{text "(c)"} is similarly. For @{text "(b)"} we know @{term "s \<in> der c r\<^sub>2 \<rightarrow> v\<^sub>1"} and @{term "s\<^sub>1 @ s\<^sub>2 \<notin> L (SEQ (der c r\<^sub>1) r\<^sub>2)"}. From the former we have @{term "(c # s) \<in> r\<^sub>2 \<rightarrow> (injval r\<^sub>2 c v\<^sub>1)"} by induction hypothesis for @{term "r\<^sub>2"}. From the latter we can infer \[@{term "\<not> (\<exists>s\<^sub>3 s\<^sub>4. s\<^sub>3 \<noteq> [] \<and> s\<^sub>3 @ s\<^sub>4 = c # s \<and> s\<^sub>3 \<in> L r\<^sub>1 \<and> s\<^sub>4 \<in> L r\<^sub>2)"}\] \noindent By Lem.~\ref{lemmkeps} we know @{term "[] \<in> r\<^sub>1 \<rightarrow> (mkeps r\<^sub>1)"} holds. Putting this all together, we can conclude with @{term "(c # s) \<in> SEQ r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2 \<rightarrow> Seq (mkeps r\<^sub>1) (injval r\<^sub>2 c v\<^sub>1)"}, as required. Finally suppose @{term "r = STAR r\<^sub>1"}. This case is very similar to the sequence case, except that we need to also ensure that @{term "flat (injval r\<^sub>1 c v\<^sub>1) \<noteq> []"}. This follows from @{term "(c # s\<^sub>1) \<in> r\<^sub>1 \<rightarrow> injval r\<^sub>1 c v\<^sub>1"} (which in turn follows from @{term "s\<^sub>1 \<in> der c r\<^sub>1 \<rightarrow> v\<^sub>1"} and the induction hypothesis).\qed \end{proof} \noindent With Lem.~\ref{Posix2} in place, it is completely routine to establish that the Sulzmann and Lu lexer satisfies our specification (returning an ``error'' iff the string is not in the language of the regular expression, and returning a unique POSIX value iff the string \emph{is} in the language): \begin{theorem}\mbox{}\smallskip\\ \begin{tabular}{ll} (1) & @{thm (lhs) lexer_correct_None} if and only if @{thm (rhs) lexer_correct_None}\\ (2) & @{thm (lhs) lexer_correct_Some} if and only if @{thm (rhs) lexer_correct_Some}\\ \end{tabular} \end{theorem} \begin{proof} By induction on @{term s} using Lem.~\ref{lemmkeps} and \ref{Posix2}.\qed \end{proof} \noindent This concludes our correctness proof. Note that we have not changed the algorithm of Sulzmann and Lu,\footnote{Any deviation we introduced is harmless.} but introduced our own specification for what a correct result---a POSIX value---should be. A strong point in favour of Sulzmann and Lu's algorithm is that it can be extended in various ways.*}section {* Extensions and Optimisations*}text {* If we are interested in tokenising a string, then we need to not just split up the string into tokens, but also ``classify'' the tokens (for example whether it is a keyword or an identifier). This can be done with only minor modifications to the algorithm by introducing \emph{record regular expressions} and \emph{record values} (for example \cite{Sulzmann2014b}): \begin{center} @{text "r :="} @{text "..."} $\mid$ @{text "(l : r)"} \qquad\qquad @{text "v :="} @{text "..."} $\mid$ @{text "(l : v)"} \end{center} \noindent where @{text l} is a label, say a string, @{text r} a regular expression and @{text v} a value. All functions can be smoothly extended to these regular expressions and values. For example \mbox{@{text "(l : r)"}} is nullable iff @{term r} is, and so on. The purpose of the record regular expression is to mark certain parts of a regular expression and then record in the calculated value which parts of the string were matched by this part. The label can then serve as classification for the tokens. For this recall the regular expression @{text "(r\<^bsub>key\<^esub> + r\<^bsub>id\<^esub>)\<^sup>\<star>"} for keywords and identifiers from the Introduction. With record regular expression we can form \mbox{@{text "((key : r\<^bsub>key\<^esub>) + (id : r\<^bsub>id\<^esub>))\<^sup>\<star>"}} and then traverse the calculated value and only collect the underlying strings in record values. With this we obtain finite sequences of pairs of labels and strings, for example \[@{text "(l\<^sub>1 : s\<^sub>1), ..., (l\<^sub>n : s\<^sub>n)"}\] \noindent from which tokens with classifications (keyword-token, identifier-token and so on) can be extracted. Derivatives as calculated by \Brz's method are usually more complex regular expressions than the initial one; the result is that the deivative-based matching and lexing algorithms are often abysmally slow. However, various optimisations are possible, such as the simplifications of @{term "ALT ZERO r"}, @{term "ALT r ZERO"}, @{term "SEQ ONE r"} and @{term "SEQ r ONE"} to @{term r}. These simplifications can speed up the algorithms considerably, as noted in \cite{Sulzmann2014}. One of the advantages of having a simple specification and correctness proof is that the latter can be refined to prove the correctness of such simplification steps. While the simplification of regular expressions according to rules like \begin{center} \begin{tabular}{lcl} @{term "ALT ZERO r"} & @{text "\<Rightarrow>"} & @{term r}\\ @{term "ALT r ZERO"} & @{text "\<Rightarrow>"} & @{term r}\\ @{term "SEQ ONE r"} & @{text "\<Rightarrow>"} & @{term r}\\ @{term "SEQ r ONE"} & @{text "\<Rightarrow>"} & @{term r} \end{tabular} \end{center} \noindent is well understood, there is an obstacle with the POSIX value calculation algorithm by Sulzmann and Lu: if we build a derivative regular expression and then simplify it, we will calculate a POSIX value for this simplified derivative regular expression, \emph{not} for the original (unsimplified) derivative regular expression. Sulzmann and Lu overcome this obstacle by not just calculating a simplified regular expression, but also calculating a \emph{rectification function} that ``repairs'' the incorrect value. The rectification functions can be (slightly clumsily) implemented in Isabelle/HOL as follows using some auxiliary functions: \begin{center} \begin{tabular}{lcl} @{thm (lhs) F_RIGHT.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{text "Right (f v)"}\\ @{thm (lhs) F_LEFT.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{text "Left (f v)"}\\ @{thm (lhs) F_ALT.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{text "Right (f\<^sub>2 v)"}\\ @{thm (lhs) F_ALT.simps(2)} & $\dn$ & @{text "Left (f\<^sub>1 v)"}\\ @{thm (lhs) F_SEQ1.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{text "Seq (f\<^sub>1 ()) (f\<^sub>2 v)"}\\ @{thm (lhs) F_SEQ2.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{text "Seq (f\<^sub>1 v) (f\<^sub>2 ())"}\\ @{thm (lhs) F_SEQ.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{text "Seq (f\<^sub>1 v\<^sub>1) (f\<^sub>2 v\<^sub>2)"}\bigskip\\ @{term "simp_ALT (ZERO, DUMMY) (r\<^sub>2, f\<^sub>2)"} & $\dn$ & @{term "(r\<^sub>2, F_RIGHT f\<^sub>2)"}\\ @{term "simp_ALT (r\<^sub>1, f\<^sub>1) (ZERO, DUMMY)"} & $\dn$ & @{term "(r\<^sub>1, F_LEFT f\<^sub>1)"}\\ @{term "simp_ALT (r\<^sub>1, f\<^sub>1) (r\<^sub>2, f\<^sub>2)"} & $\dn$ & @{term "(ALT r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2, F_ALT f\<^sub>1 f\<^sub>2)"}\\ @{term "simp_SEQ (ONE, f\<^sub>1) (r\<^sub>2, f\<^sub>2)"} & $\dn$ & @{term "(r\<^sub>2, F_SEQ1 f\<^sub>1 f\<^sub>2)"}\\ @{term "simp_SEQ (r\<^sub>1, f\<^sub>1) (ONE, f\<^sub>2)"} & $\dn$ & @{term "(r\<^sub>1, F_SEQ2 f\<^sub>1 f\<^sub>2)"}\\ @{term "simp_SEQ (r\<^sub>1, f\<^sub>1) (r\<^sub>2, f\<^sub>2)"} & $\dn$ & @{term "(SEQ r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2, F_SEQ f\<^sub>1 f\<^sub>2)"}\\ \end{tabular} \end{center} \noindent The functions @{text "simp\<^bsub>ALT\<^esub>"} and @{text "simp\<^bsub>SEQ\<^esub>"} encode the simplification rules and compose the rectification functions. The main simplification function is then \begin{center} \begin{tabular}{lcl} @{term "simp (ALT r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2)"} & $\dn$ & @{term "simp_ALT (simp r\<^sub>1) (simp r\<^sub>2)"}\\ @{term "simp (SEQ r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2)"} & $\dn$ & @{term "simp_SEQ (simp r\<^sub>1) (simp r\<^sub>2)"}\\ @{term "simp r"} & $\dn$ & @{term "(r, id)"}\\ \end{tabular} \end{center} \noindent where @{term "id"} stands for the identity function. This function returns a simplified regular expression and a corresponding rectification function. Note that we do not simplify under stars: this seems to slow down the algorithm, rather than speed up. The optimised lexer is then given by the clauses: \begin{center} \begin{tabular}{lcl} @{thm (lhs) slexer.simps(1)} & $\dn$ & @{thm (rhs) slexer.simps(1)}\\ @{thm (lhs) slexer.simps(2)} & $\dn$ & @{text "let (r\<^sub>s, f\<^sub>r) = simp (r "}$\backslash$@{text " c) in"}\\ & & @{text "case"} @{term "slexer r\<^sub>s s"} @{text of}\\ & & \phantom{$|$} @{term "None"} @{text "\<Rightarrow>"} @{term None}\\ & & $|$ @{term "Some v"} @{text "\<Rightarrow>"} @{text "Some (inj r c (f\<^sub>r v))"} \end{tabular} \end{center} \noindent In the second clause we first calculate the derivative @{text "r \\ c"} and then simplify the result. This gives us a simplified derivative @{text "r\<^sub>s"} and a rectification function @{text "f\<^sub>r"}. The lexer is then recursively called with the simplified derivative, but before we inject the character @{term c} into value, we need to rectify it (that is construct @{term "f\<^sub>r v"}). We can prove that \begin{lemma} @{thm slexer_correctness} \end{lemma} \noindent holds but for lack of space refer the reader to our mechanisation for details.*}section {* The Correctness Argument by Sulzmmann and Lu *}text {*% \newcommand{\greedy}{\succcurlyeq_{gr}} \newcommand{\posix}{>} An extended version of \cite{Sulzmann2014} is available at the website of its first author; this includes some ``proofs'', claimed in \cite{Sulzmann2014} to be ``rigorous''. Since these are evidently not in final form, we make no comment thereon, preferring to give general reasons for our belief that the approach of \cite{Sulzmann2014} is problematic. Their central definition is an ``ordering relation'' defined by the rules (slightly adapted to fit our notation):\begin{center} \begin{tabular}{@ {}c@ {\hspace{4mm}}c@ {}} @{thm[mode=Rule] C2[of "v\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>1'" "v\<^sub>2" "r\<^sub>2" "v\<^sub>2'"]}(C2) &@{thm[mode=Rule] C1[of "v\<^sub>2" "r\<^sub>2" "v\<^sub>2'" "v\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>1"]}(C1)\smallskip\\@{thm[mode=Rule] A1[of "v\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>2" "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]}(A1) &@{thm[mode=Rule] A2[of "v\<^sub>2" "v\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2"]}(A2)\smallskip\\@{thm[mode=Rule] A3[of "v\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>2" "v\<^sub>2" "r\<^sub>1"]}(A3) &@{thm[mode=Rule] A4[of "v\<^sub>1" "r\<^sub>1" "v\<^sub>2" "r\<^sub>2"]}(A4)\smallskip\\@{thm[mode=Rule] K1[of "v" "vs" "r"]}(K1) &@{thm[mode=Rule] K2[of "v" "vs" "r"]}(K2)\smallskip\\@{thm[mode=Rule] K3[of "v\<^sub>1" "r" "v\<^sub>2" "vs\<^sub>1" "vs\<^sub>2"]}(K3) &@{thm[mode=Rule] K4[of "vs\<^sub>1" "r" "vs\<^sub>2" "v"]}(K4)\end{tabular}\end{center} \noindent The idea behind the rules (A1) and (A2), for example, is that a @{text Left}-value is bigger than a @{text Right}-value, if the underlying string of the @{text Left}-value is longer or of equal length to the underlying string of the @{text Right}-value. The order is reversed, however, if the @{text Right}-value can match a longer string than a @{text Left}-value. In this way the POSIX value is supposed to be the biggest value for a given string and regular expression. Sulzmann and Lu explicitly refer to the paper \cite{Frisch2004} by Frisch and Cardelli from where they have taken the idea for their correctness proof. Frisch and Cardelli introduced a similar ordering for GREEDY matching and they showed that their GREEDY matching algorithm always produces a maximal element according to this ordering (from all possible solutions). The only difference between their GREEDY ordering and the ``ordering'' by Sulzmann and Lu is that GREEDY always prefers a @{text Left}-value over a @{text Right}-value, no matter what the underlying string is. This seems to be only a very minor difference, but it has drastic consequences in terms of what properties both orderings enjoy. What is interesting for our purposes is that the properties reflexivity, totality and transitivity for this GREEDY ordering can be proved relatively easily by induction. These properties of GREEDY, however, do not transfer to the POSIX ``ordering'' by Sulzmann and Lu. To start with, @{text "v\<^sub>1 \<ge>r v\<^sub>2"} is not defined inductively, but as @{term "v\<^sub>1 = v\<^sub>2"} or @{term "(v\<^sub>1 >r v\<^sub>2) \<and> (flat v\<^sub>1 = flat (v\<^sub>2::val))"}. This means that @{term "v\<^sub>1 >(r::rexp) (v\<^sub>2::val)"} does not necessarily imply @{term "v\<^sub>1 \<ge>(r::rexp) (v\<^sub>2::val)"}. Moreover, transitivity does not hold in the ``usual'' formulation, for example: \begin{proposition} Suppose @{term "\<turnstile> v\<^sub>1 : r"}, @{term "\<turnstile> v\<^sub>2 : r"} and @{term "\<turnstile> v\<^sub>3 : r"}. If @{term "v\<^sub>1 >(r::rexp) (v\<^sub>2::val)"} and @{term "v\<^sub>2 >(r::rexp) (v\<^sub>3::val)"} then @{term "v\<^sub>1 >(r::rexp) (v\<^sub>3::val)"}. \end{proposition} \noindent If formulated in this way, then there are various counter examples: For example let @{term r} be @{text "a + ((a + a)\<cdot>(a + \<zero>))"} then the @{term "v\<^sub>1"}, @{term "v\<^sub>2"} and @{term "v\<^sub>3"} below are values of @{term r}: \begin{center} \begin{tabular}{lcl} @{term "v\<^sub>1"} & $=$ & @{term "Left(Char a)"}\\ @{term "v\<^sub>2"} & $=$ & @{term "Right(Seq (Left(Char a)) (Right Void))"}\\ @{term "v\<^sub>3"} & $=$ & @{term "Right(Seq (Right(Char a)) (Left(Char a)))"} \end{tabular} \end{center} \noindent Moreover @{term "v\<^sub>1 >(r::rexp) v\<^sub>2"} and @{term "v\<^sub>2 >(r::rexp) v\<^sub>3"}, but \emph{not} @{term "v\<^sub>1 >(r::rexp) v\<^sub>3"}! The reason is that although @{term "v\<^sub>3"} is a @{text "Right"}-value, it can match a longer string, namely @{term "flat v\<^sub>3 = [a,a]"}, while @{term "flat v\<^sub>1"} (and @{term "flat v\<^sub>2"}) matches only @{term "[a]"}. So transitivity in this formulation does not hold---in this example actually @{term "v\<^sub>3 >(r::rexp) v\<^sub>1"}! Sulzmann and Lu ``fix'' this problem by weakening the transitivity property. They require in addition that the underlying strings are of the same length. This excludes the counter example above and any counter-example we were able to find (by hand and by machine). Thus the transitivity lemma should be formulated as: \begin{proposition} Suppose @{term "\<turnstile> v\<^sub>1 : r"}, @{term "\<turnstile> v\<^sub>2 : r"} and @{term "\<turnstile> v\<^sub>3 : r"}, and also @{text "|v\<^sub>1| = |v\<^sub>2| = |v\<^sub>3|"}.\\ If @{term "v\<^sub>1 >(r::rexp) (v\<^sub>2::val)"} and @{term "v\<^sub>2 >(r::rexp) (v\<^sub>3::val)"} then @{term "v\<^sub>1 >(r::rexp) (v\<^sub>3::val)"}. \end{proposition} \noindent While we agree with Sulzmann and Lu that this property probably(!) holds, proving it seems not so straightforward: although one begins with the assumption that the values have the same flattening, this cannot be maintained as one descends into the induction. This is a problem that occurs in a number of places in the proofs by Sulzmann and Lu. Although they do not give an explicit proof of the transitivity property, they give a closely related property about the existence of maximal elements. They state that this can be verified by an induction on $r$. We disagree with this as we shall show next in case of transitivity. The case where the reasoning breaks down is the sequence case, say @{term "SEQ r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2"}. The induction hypotheses in this case are\begin{center}\begin{tabular}{@ {}c@ {\hspace{10mm}}c@ {}}\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {\hspace{-7mm}}l@ {}}IH @{term "r\<^sub>1"}:\\@{text "\<forall> v\<^sub>1, v\<^sub>2, v\<^sub>3."} \\ & @{term "\<turnstile> v\<^sub>1 : r\<^sub>1"}\;@{text "\<and>"} @{term "\<turnstile> v\<^sub>2 : r\<^sub>1"}\;@{text "\<and>"} @{term "\<turnstile> v\<^sub>3 : r\<^sub>1"}\\ & @{text "\<and>"} @{text "|v\<^sub>1| = |v\<^sub>2| = |v\<^sub>3|"}\\ & @{text "\<and>"} @{term "v\<^sub>1 >(r\<^sub>1::rexp) v\<^sub>2 \<and> v\<^sub>2 >(r\<^sub>1::rexp) v\<^sub>3"}\medskip\\ & $\Rightarrow$ @{term "v\<^sub>1 >(r\<^sub>1::rexp) v\<^sub>3"}\end{tabular} &\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {\hspace{-7mm}}l@ {}}IH @{term "r\<^sub>2"}:\\@{text "\<forall> v\<^sub>1, v\<^sub>2, v\<^sub>3."}\\ & @{term "\<turnstile> v\<^sub>1 : r\<^sub>2"}\;@{text "\<and>"} @{term "\<turnstile> v\<^sub>2 : r\<^sub>2"}\;@{text "\<and>"} @{term "\<turnstile> v\<^sub>3 : r\<^sub>2"}\\ & @{text "\<and>"} @{text "|v\<^sub>1| = |v\<^sub>2| = |v\<^sub>3|"}\\ & @{text "\<and>"} @{term "v\<^sub>1 >(r\<^sub>2::rexp) v\<^sub>2 \<and> v\<^sub>2 >(r\<^sub>2::rexp) v\<^sub>3"}\medskip\\ & $\Rightarrow$ @{term "v\<^sub>1 >(r\<^sub>2::rexp) v\<^sub>3"}\end{tabular}\end{tabular}\end{center} \noindent We can assume that % \begin{equation} @{term "(Seq (v\<^sub>1\<^sub>l) (v\<^sub>1\<^sub>r)) >(SEQ r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2) (Seq (v\<^sub>2\<^sub>l) (v\<^sub>2\<^sub>r))"} \qquad\textrm{and}\qquad @{term "(Seq (v\<^sub>2\<^sub>l) (v\<^sub>2\<^sub>r)) >(SEQ r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2) (Seq (v\<^sub>3\<^sub>l) (v\<^sub>3\<^sub>r))"} \label{assms} \end{equation} \noindent hold, and furthermore that the values have equal length, namely: % \begin{equation} @{term "flat (Seq (v\<^sub>1\<^sub>l) (v\<^sub>1\<^sub>r)) = flat (Seq (v\<^sub>2\<^sub>l) (v\<^sub>2\<^sub>r))"} \qquad\textrm{and}\qquad @{term "flat (Seq (v\<^sub>2\<^sub>l) (v\<^sub>2\<^sub>r)) = flat (Seq (v\<^sub>3\<^sub>l) (v\<^sub>3\<^sub>r))"} \label{lens} \end{equation} \noindent We need to show that @{term "(Seq (v\<^sub>1\<^sub>l) (v\<^sub>1\<^sub>r)) >(SEQ r\<^sub>1 r\<^sub>2) (Seq (v\<^sub>3\<^sub>l) (v\<^sub>3\<^sub>r))"} holds. We can proceed by analysing how the assumptions in \eqref{assms} have arisen. There are four cases. Let us assume we are in the case where we know \[ @{term "v\<^sub>1\<^sub>l >(r\<^sub>1::rexp) v\<^sub>2\<^sub>l"} \qquad\textrm{and}\qquad @{term "v\<^sub>2\<^sub>l >(r\<^sub>1::rexp) v\<^sub>3\<^sub>l"} \] \noindent and also know the corresponding inhabitation judgements. This is exactly a case where we would like to apply the induction hypothesis IH~$r_1$. But we cannot! We still need to show that @{term "flat (v\<^sub>1\<^sub>l) = flat(v\<^sub>2\<^sub>l)"} and @{term "flat(v\<^sub>2\<^sub>l) = flat(v\<^sub>3\<^sub>l)"}. We know from \eqref{lens} that the lengths of the sequence values are equal, but from this we cannot infer anything about the lengths of the component values. Indeed in general they will be unequal, that is \[ @{term "flat(v\<^sub>1\<^sub>l) \<noteq> flat(v\<^sub>2\<^sub>l)"} \qquad\textrm{and}\qquad @{term "flat(v\<^sub>1\<^sub>r) \<noteq> flat(v\<^sub>2\<^sub>r)"} \] \noindent but still \eqref{lens} will hold. Now we are stuck, since the IH does not apply. As said, this problem where the induction hypothesis does not apply arises in several places in the proof of Sulzmann and Lu, not just for proving transitivity.*}section {* Conclusion *}text {* We have implemented the POSIX value calculation algorithm introduced in \cite{Sulzmann2014}. Our implementation is nearly identical to the original and all modifications we introduced are harmless (like our char-clause for @{text inj}). We have proved this algorithm to be correct, but correct according to our own specification of what POSIX values are. Our specification (inspired from work in \cite{Vansummeren2006}) appears to be much simpler than in \cite{Sulzmann2014} and our proofs are nearly always straightforward. We have attempted to formalise the original proof by Sulzmann and Lu \cite{Sulzmann2014}, but we believe it contains unfillable gaps. In the online version of \cite{Sulzmann2014}, the authors already acknowledge some small problems, but our experience suggests that there are more serious problems. Having proved the correctness of the POSIX lexing algorithm in \cite{Sulzmann2014}, which lessons have we learned? Well, this is a perfect example for the importance of the \emph{right} definitions. We have (on and off) banged our heads on doors as soon as as first versions of \cite{Sulzmann2014} appeared, but have made little progress with turning the relatively detailed proof sketch in \cite{Sulzmann2014} into a formalisable proof. Having seen \cite{Vansummeren2006} and adapting the POSIX definition given there for the algorithm by Sulzmann and Lu made all the difference: the proofs, as said, are nearly straightforward. The question remains whether the original proof idea of \cite{Sulzmann2014}, potentially using our result as a stepping stone, can be made to work? Alas, we really do not know despite considerable effort and door banging. Closely related to our work is an automata-based lexer formalised by Nipkow \cite{Nipkow98}. This lexer also splits up strings into longest initial substrings, but Nipkow's algorithm is not completely computational. The algorithm by Sulzmann and Lu, in contrast, can be implemented with easy in any functional language. A bespoke lexer for the Imp-language is formalised in Coq as part of the Software Foundations book \cite{Pierce2015}. The disadvantage of such bespoke lexers is that they do not generalise easily to more advanced features. Our formalisation is available from \url{http://www.inf.kcl.ac.uk/staff/urbanc/lex}. %\noindent %{\bf Acknowledgements:} %We are grateful for the comments we received from anonymous %referees. \small \bibliographystyle{plain} \bibliography{root}*}(*<*)end(*>*)