theory Tactical
imports Base FirstSteps
begin
chapter {* Tactical Reasoning\label{chp:tactical} *}
text {*
The main reason for descending to the ML-level of Isabelle is to be able to
implement automatic proof procedures. Such proof procedures usually lessen
considerably the burden of manual reasoning, for example, when introducing
new definitions. These proof procedures are centred around refining a goal
state using tactics. This is similar to the \isacommand{apply}-style
reasoning at the user level, where goals are modified in a sequence of proof
steps until all of them are solved. However, there are also more structured
operations available on the ML-level that help with the handling of
variables and assumptions.
*}
section {* Basics of Reasoning with Tactics*}
text {*
To see how tactics work, let us first transcribe a simple \isacommand{apply}-style proof
into ML. Suppose the following proof.
*}
lemma disj_swap: "P \<or> Q \<Longrightarrow> Q \<or> P"
apply(erule disjE)
apply(rule disjI2)
apply(assumption)
apply(rule disjI1)
apply(assumption)
done
text {*
This proof translates to the following ML-code.
@{ML_response_fake [display,gray]
"let
val ctxt = @{context}
val goal = @{prop \"P \<or> Q \<Longrightarrow> Q \<or> P\"}
in
Goal.prove ctxt [\"P\", \"Q\"] [] goal
(fn _ =>
etac @{thm disjE} 1
THEN rtac @{thm disjI2} 1
THEN atac 1
THEN rtac @{thm disjI1} 1
THEN atac 1)
end" "?P \<or> ?Q \<Longrightarrow> ?Q \<or> ?P"}
To start the proof, the function @{ML "Goal.prove"}~@{text "ctxt xs As C
tac"} sets up a goal state for proving the goal @{text C}
(that is @{prop "P \<or> Q \<Longrightarrow> Q \<or> P"} in the proof at hand) under the
assumptions @{text As} (happens to be empty) with the variables
@{text xs} that will be generalised once the goal is proved (in our case
@{text P} and @{text Q}). The @{text "tac"} is the tactic that proves the goal;
it can make use of the local assumptions (there are none in this example).
The functions @{ML etac}, @{ML rtac} and @{ML atac} in the code above correspond to
@{text erule}, @{text rule} and @{text assumption}, respectively.
The operator @{ML THEN} strings the tactics together.
\begin{readmore}
To learn more about the function @{ML Goal.prove} see \isccite{sec:results}
and the file @{ML_file "Pure/goal.ML"}. See @{ML_file
"Pure/tactic.ML"} and @{ML_file "Pure/tctical.ML"} for the code of basic
tactics and tactic combinators; see also Chapters 3 and 4 in the old
Isabelle Reference Manual.
\end{readmore}
(FIXME: what is @{ML Goal.prove_global}?)
Note that in the code above we use antiquotations for referencing the theorems. Many theorems
also have ML-bindings with the same name. Therefore, we could also just have
written @{ML "etac disjE 1"}, or in case where there are no ML-binding obtain
the theorem dynamically using the function @{ML thm}; for example
\mbox{@{ML "etac (thm \"disjE\") 1"}}. Both ways however are considered bad style!
The reason
is that the binding for @{ML disjE} can be re-assigned by the user and thus
one does not have complete control over which theorem is actually
applied. This problem is nicely prevented by using antiquotations, because
then the theorems are fixed statically at compile-time.
During the development of automatic proof procedures, you will often find it
necessary to test a tactic on examples. This can be conveniently
done with the command \isacommand{apply}@{text "(tactic \<verbopen> \<dots> \<verbclose>)"}.
Consider the following sequence of tactics
*}
ML{*val foo_tac =
(etac @{thm disjE} 1
THEN rtac @{thm disjI2} 1
THEN atac 1
THEN rtac @{thm disjI1} 1
THEN atac 1)*}
text {* and the Isabelle proof: *}
lemma "P \<or> Q \<Longrightarrow> Q \<or> P"
apply(tactic {* foo_tac *})
done
text {*
By using @{text "tactic \<verbopen> \<dots> \<verbclose>"} you can call from the
user level of Isabelle the tactic @{ML foo_tac} or
any other function that returns a tactic.
The tactic @{ML foo_tac} is just a sequence of simple tactics stringed
together by @{ML THEN}. As can be seen, each simple tactic in @{ML foo_tac}
has a hard-coded number that stands for the subgoal analysed by the
tactic (@{text "1"} stands for the first, or top-most, subgoal). This hard-coding
of goals is sometimes wanted, but usually it is not. To avoid the explicit numbering,
you can write\label{tac:footacprime}
*}
ML{*val foo_tac' =
(etac @{thm disjE}
THEN' rtac @{thm disjI2}
THEN' atac
THEN' rtac @{thm disjI1}
THEN' atac)*}
text {*
and then give the number for the subgoal explicitly when the tactic is
called. So in the next proof you can first discharge the second subgoal, and
subsequently the first.
*}
lemma "P1 \<or> Q1 \<Longrightarrow> Q1 \<or> P1"
and "P2 \<or> Q2 \<Longrightarrow> Q2 \<or> P2"
apply(tactic {* foo_tac' 2 *})
apply(tactic {* foo_tac' 1 *})
done
text {*
This kind of addressing is more difficult to achieve when the goal is
hard-coded inside the tactic. For most operators that combine tactics
(@{ML THEN} is only one such operator) a ``primed'' version exists.
The tactics @{ML foo_tac} and @{ML foo_tac'} are very specific for
analysing goals being only of the form @{prop "P \<or> Q \<Longrightarrow> Q \<or> P"}. If the goal is not
of this form, then they return the error message:
\begin{isabelle}
@{text "*** empty result sequence -- proof command failed"}\\
@{text "*** At command \"apply\"."}
\end{isabelle}
This means the tactics failed. The reason for this error message is that tactics
are functions mapping a goal state to a (lazy) sequence of successor states.
Hence the type of a tactic is:
*}
ML{*type tactic = thm -> thm Seq.seq*}
text {*
By convention, if a tactic fails, then it should return the empty sequence.
Therefore, if you write your own tactics, they should not raise exceptions
willy-nilly; only in very grave failure situations should a tactic raise the
exception @{text THM}.
The simplest tactics are @{ML no_tac} and @{ML all_tac}. The first returns
the empty sequence and is defined as
*}
ML{*fun no_tac thm = Seq.empty*}
text {*
which means @{ML no_tac} always fails. The second returns the given theorem wrapped
up in a single member sequence; it is defined as
*}
ML{*fun all_tac thm = Seq.single thm*}
text {*
which means @{ML all_tac} always succeeds, but also does not make any progress
with the proof.
The lazy list of possible successor goal states shows through at the user-level
of Isabelle when using the command \isacommand{back}. For instance in the
following proof there are two possibilities for how to apply
@{ML foo_tac'}: either using the first assumption or the second.
*}
lemma "\<lbrakk>P \<or> Q; P \<or> Q\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> Q \<or> P"
apply(tactic {* foo_tac' 1 *})
back
done
text {*
By using \isacommand{back}, we construct the proof that uses the
second assumption. While in the proof above, it does not really matter which
assumption is used, in more interesting cases provability might depend
on exploring different possibilities.
\begin{readmore}
See @{ML_file "Pure/General/seq.ML"} for the implementation of lazy
sequences. In day-to-day Isabelle programming, however, one rarely
constructs sequences explicitly, but uses the predefined tactics and
tactic combinators instead.
\end{readmore}
It might be surprising that tactics, which transform
one goal state to the next, are functions from theorems to theorem
(sequences). The surprise resolves by knowing that every
goal state is indeed a theorem. To shed more light on this,
let us modify the code of @{ML all_tac} to obtain the following
tactic
*}
ML{*fun my_print_tac ctxt thm =
let
val _ = warning (str_of_thm ctxt thm)
in
Seq.single thm
end*}
text_raw {*
\begin{figure}[p]
\begin{isabelle}
*}
lemma shows "\<lbrakk>A; B\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> A \<and> B"
apply(tactic {* my_print_tac @{context} *})
txt{* \begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage}\medskip
\begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
\small\colorbox{gray!20}{
\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}}
internal goal state:\\
@{text "(\<lbrakk>A; B\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> A \<and> B) \<Longrightarrow> (\<lbrakk>A; B\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> A \<and> B)"}
\end{tabular}}
\end{minipage}\medskip
*}
apply(rule conjI)
apply(tactic {* my_print_tac @{context} *})
txt{* \begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage}\medskip
\begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
\small\colorbox{gray!20}{
\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}}
internal goal state:\\
@{text "(\<lbrakk>A; B\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> A) \<Longrightarrow> (\<lbrakk>A; B\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> B) \<Longrightarrow> (\<lbrakk>A; B\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> A \<and> B)"}
\end{tabular}}
\end{minipage}\medskip
*}
apply(assumption)
apply(tactic {* my_print_tac @{context} *})
txt{* \begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage}\medskip
\begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
\small\colorbox{gray!20}{
\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}}
internal goal state:\\
@{text "(\<lbrakk>A; B\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> B) \<Longrightarrow> (\<lbrakk>A; B\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> A \<and> B)"}
\end{tabular}}
\end{minipage}\medskip
*}
apply(assumption)
apply(tactic {* my_print_tac @{context} *})
txt{* \begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage}\medskip
\begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
\small\colorbox{gray!20}{
\begin{tabular}{@ {}l@ {}}
internal goal state:\\
@{text "\<lbrakk>A; B\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> A \<and> B"}
\end{tabular}}
\end{minipage}\medskip
*}
done
text_raw {*
\end{isabelle}
\caption{The figure shows a proof where each intermediate goal state is
printed by the Isabelle system and by @{ML my_print_tac}. The latter shows
the goal state as represented internally (highlighted boxes). This
illustrates that every goal state in Isabelle is represented by a theorem:
when we start the proof of \mbox{@{text "\<lbrakk>A; B\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> A \<and> B"}} the theorem is
@{text "(\<lbrakk>A; B\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> A \<and> B) \<Longrightarrow> (\<lbrakk>A; B\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> A \<and> B)"}; when we finish the proof the
theorem is @{text "\<lbrakk>A; B\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> A \<and> B"}.\label{fig:goalstates}}
\end{figure}
*}
text {*
which prints out the given theorem (using the string-function defined in
Section~\ref{sec:printing}) and then behaves like @{ML all_tac}. With this
tactic we are in the position to inspect every goal state in a
proof. Consider now the proof in Figure~\ref{fig:goalstates}: as can be seen,
internally every goal state is an implication of the form
@{text[display] "A\<^isub>1 \<Longrightarrow> \<dots> \<Longrightarrow> A\<^isub>n \<Longrightarrow> (C)"}
where @{term C} is the goal to be proved and the @{term "A\<^isub>i"} are
the subgoals. So after setting up the lemma, the goal state is always of the
form @{text "C \<Longrightarrow> (C)"}; when the proof is finished we are left with @{text
"(C)"}. Since the goal @{term C} can potentially be an implication, there is
a ``protector'' wrapped around it (in from of an outermost constant @{text
"Const (\"prop\", bool \<Rightarrow> bool)"}; however this constant
is invisible in the figure). This prevents that premises of @{text C} are
mis-interpreted as open subgoals. While tactics can operate on the subgoals
(the @{text "A\<^isub>i"} above), they are expected to leave the conclusion
@{term C} intact, with the exception of possibly instantiating schematic
variables. If you use the predefined tactics, which we describe in the next
section, this will always be the case.
\begin{readmore}
For more information about the internals of goals see \isccite{sec:tactical-goals}.
\end{readmore}
*}
section {* Simple Tactics *}
text {*
Let us start with the tactic @{ML print_tac}, which is quite useful for low-level
debugging of tactics. It just prints out a message and the current goal state.
Processing the proof
*}
lemma shows "False \<Longrightarrow> True"
apply(tactic {* print_tac "foo message" *})
txt{*gives:\medskip
\begin{minipage}{\textwidth}\small
@{text "foo message"}\\[3mm]
@{prop "False \<Longrightarrow> True"}\\
@{text " 1. False \<Longrightarrow> True"}\\
\end{minipage}
*}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
Another simple tactic is the function @{ML atac}, which, as shown in the previous
section, corresponds to the assumption command.
*}
lemma shows "P \<Longrightarrow> P"
apply(tactic {* atac 1 *})
txt{*\begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage}*}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
Similarly, @{ML rtac}, @{ML dtac}, @{ML etac} and @{ML ftac} correspond
to @{text rule}, @{text drule}, @{text erule} and @{text frule},
respectively. Each of them takes a theorem as argument and attempts to
apply it to a goal. Below are three self-explanatory examples.
*}
lemma shows "P \<and> Q"
apply(tactic {* rtac @{thm conjI} 1 *})
txt{*\begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage}*}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
lemma shows "P \<and> Q \<Longrightarrow> False"
apply(tactic {* etac @{thm conjE} 1 *})
txt{*\begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage}*}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
lemma shows "False \<and> True \<Longrightarrow> False"
apply(tactic {* dtac @{thm conjunct2} 1 *})
txt{*\begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage}*}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
Note the number in each tactic call. Also as mentioned in the previous section, most
basic tactics take such an argument; it addresses the subgoal they are analysing.
In the proof below, we first split up the conjunction in the second subgoal by
focusing on this subgoal first.
*}
lemma shows "Foo" and "P \<and> Q"
apply(tactic {* rtac @{thm conjI} 2 *})
txt {*\begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage}*}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
The function @{ML resolve_tac} is similar to @{ML rtac}, except that it
expects a list of theorems as arguments. From this list it will apply the
first applicable theorem (later theorems that are also applicable can be
explored via the lazy sequences mechanism). Given the code
*}
ML{*val resolve_tac_xmp = resolve_tac [@{thm impI}, @{thm conjI}]*}
text {*
an example for @{ML resolve_tac} is the following proof where first an outermost
implication is analysed and then an outermost conjunction.
*}
lemma shows "C \<longrightarrow> (A \<and> B)" and "(A \<longrightarrow> B) \<and> C"
apply(tactic {* resolve_tac_xmp 1 *})
apply(tactic {* resolve_tac_xmp 2 *})
txt{*\begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage}*}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
Similarly versions taking a list of theorems exist for the tactics
@{ML dtac} (@{ML dresolve_tac}), @{ML etac} (@{ML eresolve_tac}) and so on.
Another simple tactic is @{ML cut_facts_tac}. It inserts a list of theorems
into the assumptions of the current goal state. For example
*}
lemma shows "True \<noteq> False"
apply(tactic {* cut_facts_tac [@{thm True_def}, @{thm False_def}] 1 *})
txt{*produces the goal state\medskip
\begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage}*}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
Since rules are applied using higher-order unification, an automatic proof
procedure might become too fragile, if it just applies inference rules as
shown above. The reason is that a number of rules introduce meta-variables
into the goal state. Consider for example the proof
*}
lemma shows "\<forall>x\<in>A. P x \<Longrightarrow> Q x"
apply(tactic {* dtac @{thm bspec} 1 *})
txt{*\begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage}*}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
where the application of Rule @{text bspec} generates two subgoals involving the
meta-variable @{text "?x"}. Now, if you are not careful, tactics
applied to the first subgoal might instantiate this meta-variable in such a
way that the second subgoal becomes unprovable. If it is clear what the @{text "?x"}
should be, then this situation can be avoided by introducing a more
constraint version of the @{text bspec}-rule. Such constraints can be given by
pre-instantiating theorems with other theorems. One function to do this is
@{ML RS}
@{ML_response_fake [display,gray]
"@{thm disjI1} RS @{thm conjI}" "\<lbrakk>?P1; ?Q\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> (?P1 \<or> ?Q1) \<and> ?Q"}
which in the example instantiates the first premise of the @{text conjI}-rule
with the rule @{text disjI1}. If the instantiation is impossible, as in the
case of
@{ML_response_fake_both [display,gray]
"@{thm conjI} RS @{thm mp}"
"*** Exception- THM (\"RSN: no unifiers\", 1,
[\"\<lbrakk>?P; ?Q\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> ?P \<and> ?Q\", \"\<lbrakk>?P \<longrightarrow> ?Q; ?P\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> ?Q\"]) raised"}
then the function raises an exception. The function @{ML RSN} is similar to @{ML RS}, but
takes an additional number as argument that makes explicit which premise
should be instantiated.
To improve readability of the theorems we produce below, we shall use
the following function
*}
ML{*fun no_vars ctxt thm =
let
val ((_, [thm']), _) = Variable.import_thms true [thm] ctxt
in
thm'
end*}
text {*
that transform the schematic variables of a theorem into free variables.
Using this function for the first @{ML RS}-expression above would produce
the more readable result:
@{ML_response_fake [display,gray]
"no_vars @{context} (@{thm disjI1} RS @{thm conjI})" "\<lbrakk>P; Q\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> (P \<or> Qa) \<and> Q"}
If you want to instantiate more than one premise of a theorem, you can use
the function @{ML MRS}:
@{ML_response_fake [display,gray]
"no_vars @{context} ([@{thm disjI1}, @{thm disjI2}] MRS @{thm conjI})"
"\<lbrakk>P; Q\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> (P \<or> Qa) \<and> (Pa \<or> Q)"}
If you need to instantiate lists of theorems, you can use the
functions @{ML RL} and @{ML MRL}. For example in the code below,
every theorem in the second list is instantiated with every
theorem in the first.
@{ML_response_fake [display,gray]
"[@{thm impI}, @{thm disjI2}] RL [@{thm conjI}, @{thm disjI1}]"
"[\<lbrakk>P \<Longrightarrow> Q; Qa\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> (P \<longrightarrow> Q) \<and> Qa,
\<lbrakk>Q; Qa\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> (P \<or> Q) \<and> Qa,
(P \<Longrightarrow> Q) \<Longrightarrow> (P \<longrightarrow> Q) \<or> Qa,
Q \<Longrightarrow> (P \<or> Q) \<or> Qa]"}
\begin{readmore}
The combinators for instantiating theorems are defined in @{ML_file "Pure/drule.ML"}.
\end{readmore}
Often proofs on the ML-level involve elaborate operations on assumptions and
@{text "\<And>"}-quantified variables. To do such operations using the basic tactics
shown so far is very unwieldy and brittle. Some convenience and
safety is provided by the tactic @{ML SUBPROOF}. This tactic fixes the parameters
and binds the various components of a goal state to a record.
To see what happens, assume the function defined in Figure~\ref{fig:sptac}, which
takes a record and just prints out the content of this record (using the
string transformation functions from in Section~\ref{sec:printing}). Consider
now the proof:
*}
text_raw{*
\begin{figure}
\begin{isabelle}
*}
ML{*fun sp_tac {prems, params, asms, concl, context, schematics} =
let
val str_of_params = str_of_cterms context params
val str_of_asms = str_of_cterms context asms
val str_of_concl = str_of_cterm context concl
val str_of_prems = str_of_thms context prems
val str_of_schms = str_of_cterms context (snd schematics)
val _ = (warning ("params: " ^ str_of_params);
warning ("schematics: " ^ str_of_schms);
warning ("assumptions: " ^ str_of_asms);
warning ("conclusion: " ^ str_of_concl);
warning ("premises: " ^ str_of_prems))
in
no_tac
end*}
text_raw{*
\end{isabelle}
\caption{A function that prints out the various parameters provided by the tactic
@{ML SUBPROOF}. It uses the functions defined in Section~\ref{sec:printing} for
extracting strings from @{ML_type cterm}s and @{ML_type thm}s.\label{fig:sptac}}
\end{figure}
*}
lemma shows "\<And>x y. A x y \<Longrightarrow> B y x \<longrightarrow> C (?z y) x"
apply(tactic {* SUBPROOF sp_tac @{context} 1 *})?
txt {*
The tactic produces the following printout:
\begin{quote}\small
\begin{tabular}{ll}
params: & @{term x}, @{term y}\\
schematics: & @{term z}\\
assumptions: & @{term "A x y"}\\
conclusion: & @{term "B y x \<longrightarrow> C (z y) x"}\\
premises: & @{term "A x y"}
\end{tabular}
\end{quote}
Note in the actual output the brown colour of the variables @{term x} and
@{term y}. Although they are parameters in the original goal, they are fixed inside
the subproof. By convention these fixed variables are printed in brown colour.
Similarly the schematic variable @{term z}. The assumption, or premise,
@{prop "A x y"} is bound as @{ML_type cterm} to the record-variable
@{text asms}, but also as @{ML_type thm} to @{text prems}.
Notice also that we had to append @{text [quotes] "?"} to the
\isacommand{apply}-command. The reason is that @{ML SUBPROOF} normally
expects that the subgoal is solved completely. Since in the function @{ML
sp_tac} we returned the tactic @{ML no_tac}, the subproof obviously
fails. The question-mark allows us to recover from this failure in a
graceful manner so that the warning messages are not overwritten by an
``empty sequence'' error message.
If we continue the proof script by applying the @{text impI}-rule
*}
apply(rule impI)
apply(tactic {* SUBPROOF sp_tac @{context} 1 *})?
txt {*
then the tactic prints out:
\begin{quote}\small
\begin{tabular}{ll}
params: & @{term x}, @{term y}\\
schematics: & @{term z}\\
assumptions: & @{term "A x y"}, @{term "B y x"}\\
conclusion: & @{term "C (z y) x"}\\
premises: & @{term "A x y"}, @{term "B y x"}
\end{tabular}
\end{quote}
*}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
Now also @{term "B y x"} is an assumption bound to @{text asms} and @{text prems}.
One convenience of @{ML SUBPROOF} is that we can apply the assumptions
using the usual tactics, because the parameter @{text prems}
contains them as theorems. With this you can easily
implement a tactic that behaves almost like @{ML atac}:
*}
ML{*val atac' = SUBPROOF (fn {prems, ...} => resolve_tac prems 1)*}
text {*
If you apply @{ML atac'} to the next lemma
*}
lemma shows "\<lbrakk>B x y; A x y; C x y\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> A x y"
apply(tactic {* atac' @{context} 1 *})
txt{* it will produce
@{subgoals [display]} *}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
The restriction in this tactic which is not present in @{ML atac} is
that it cannot instantiate any
schematic variable. This might be seen as a defect, but it is actually
an advantage in the situations for which @{ML SUBPROOF} was designed:
the reason is that, as mentioned before, instantiation of schematic variables can affect
several goals and can render them unprovable. @{ML SUBPROOF} is meant
to avoid this.
Notice that @{ML atac'} inside @{ML SUBPROOF} calls @{ML resolve_tac} with
the subgoal number @{text "1"} and also the outer call to @{ML SUBPROOF} in
the \isacommand{apply}-step uses @{text "1"}. This is another advantage
of @{ML SUBPROOF}: the addressing inside it is completely
local to the tactic inside the subproof. It is therefore possible to also apply
@{ML atac'} to the second goal by just writing:
*}
lemma shows "True" and "\<lbrakk>B x y; A x y; C x y\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> A x y"
apply(tactic {* atac' @{context} 2 *})
apply(rule TrueI)
done
text {*
\begin{readmore}
The function @{ML SUBPROOF} is defined in @{ML_file "Pure/subgoal.ML"} and
also described in \isccite{sec:results}.
\end{readmore}
A similar but less powerful function than @{ML SUBPROOF} is @{ML SUBGOAL}.
It allows you to inspect a given subgoal. With this you can implement
a tactic that applies a rule according to the topmost logic connective in the
subgoal (to illustrate this we only analyse a few connectives). The code
of the tactic is as follows.\label{tac:selecttac}
*}
ML %linenosgray{*fun select_tac (t,i) =
case t of
@{term "Trueprop"} $ t' => select_tac (t',i)
| @{term "op \<Longrightarrow>"} $ _ $ t' => select_tac (t',i)
| @{term "op \<and>"} $ _ $ _ => rtac @{thm conjI} i
| @{term "op \<longrightarrow>"} $ _ $ _ => rtac @{thm impI} i
| @{term "Not"} $ _ => rtac @{thm notI} i
| Const (@{const_name "All"}, _) $ _ => rtac @{thm allI} i
| _ => all_tac*}
text {*
The input of the function is a term representing the subgoal and a number
specifying the subgoal of interest. In line 3 you need to descend under the
outermost @{term "Trueprop"} in order to get to the connective you like to
analyse. Otherwise goals like @{prop "A \<and> B"} are not properly
analysed. Similarly with meta-implications in the next line. While for the
first five patterns we can use the @{text "@term"}-antiquotation to
construct the patterns, the pattern in Line 8 cannot be constructed in this
way. The reason is that an antiquotation would fix the type of the
quantified variable. So you really have to construct the pattern using the
basic term-constructors. This is not necessary in other cases, because their type
is always fixed to function types involving only the type @{typ bool}. For the
final pattern, we chose to just return @{ML all_tac}. Consequently,
@{ML select_tac} never fails.
Let us now see how to apply this tactic. Consider the four goals:
*}
lemma shows "A \<and> B" and "A \<longrightarrow> B \<longrightarrow>C" and "\<forall>x. D x" and "E \<Longrightarrow> F"
apply(tactic {* SUBGOAL select_tac 4 *})
apply(tactic {* SUBGOAL select_tac 3 *})
apply(tactic {* SUBGOAL select_tac 2 *})
apply(tactic {* SUBGOAL select_tac 1 *})
txt{* \begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage} *}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
where in all but the last the tactic applied an introduction rule.
Note that we applied the tactic to the goals in ``reverse'' order.
This is a trick in order to be independent from the subgoals that are
produced by the rule. If we had applied it in the other order
*}
lemma shows "A \<and> B" and "A \<longrightarrow> B \<longrightarrow>C" and "\<forall>x. D x" and "E \<Longrightarrow> F"
apply(tactic {* SUBGOAL select_tac 1 *})
apply(tactic {* SUBGOAL select_tac 3 *})
apply(tactic {* SUBGOAL select_tac 4 *})
apply(tactic {* SUBGOAL select_tac 5 *})
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
then we have to be careful to not apply the tactic to the two subgoals produced by
the first goal. To do this can result in quite messy code. In contrast,
the ``reverse application'' is easy to implement.
Of course, this example is contrived: there are much simpler methods available in
Isabelle for implementing a proof procedure analysing a goal according to its topmost
connective. These simpler methods use tactic combinators, which we will explain
in the next section.
*}
section {* Tactic Combinators *}
text {*
The purpose of tactic combinators is to build compound tactics out of
smaller tactics. In the previous section we already used @{ML THEN}, which
just strings together two tactics in a sequence. For example:
*}
lemma shows "(Foo \<and> Bar) \<and> False"
apply(tactic {* rtac @{thm conjI} 1 THEN rtac @{thm conjI} 1 *})
txt {* \begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage} *}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
If you want to avoid the hard-coded subgoal addressing, then you can use
the ``primed'' version of @{ML THEN}. For example:
*}
lemma shows "(Foo \<and> Bar) \<and> False"
apply(tactic {* (rtac @{thm conjI} THEN' rtac @{thm conjI}) 1 *})
txt {* \begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage} *}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
Here you only have to specify the subgoal of interest only once and
it is consistently applied to the component tactics.
For most tactic combinators such a ``primed'' version exists and
in what follows we will usually prefer it over the ``unprimed'' one.
If there is a list of tactics that should all be tried out in
sequence, you can use the combinator @{ML EVERY'}. For example
the function @{ML foo_tac'} from page~\pageref{tac:footacprime} can also
be written as:
*}
ML{*val foo_tac'' = EVERY' [etac @{thm disjE}, rtac @{thm disjI2},
atac, rtac @{thm disjI1}, atac]*}
text {*
There is even another way of implementing this tactic: in automatic proof
procedures (in contrast to tactics that might be called by the user) there
are often long lists of tactics that are applied to the first
subgoal. Instead of writing the code above and then calling @{ML "foo_tac'' 1"},
you can also just write
*}
ML{*val foo_tac1 = EVERY1 [etac @{thm disjE}, rtac @{thm disjI2},
atac, rtac @{thm disjI1}, atac]*}
text {*
and call @{ML foo_tac1}.
With the combinators @{ML THEN'}, @{ML EVERY'} and @{ML EVERY1} it must be
guaranteed that all component tactics successfully apply; otherwise the
whole tactic will fail. If you rather want to try out a number of tactics,
then you can use the combinator @{ML ORELSE'} for two tactics, and @{ML
FIRST'} (or @{ML FIRST1}) for a list of tactics. For example, the tactic
*}
ML{*val orelse_xmp = rtac @{thm disjI1} ORELSE' rtac @{thm conjI}*}
text {*
will first try out whether rule @{text disjI} applies and after that
@{text conjI}. To see this consider the proof
*}
lemma shows "True \<and> False" and "Foo \<or> Bar"
apply(tactic {* orelse_xmp 2 *})
apply(tactic {* orelse_xmp 1 *})
txt {* which results in the goal state
\begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage}
*}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
Using @{ML FIRST'} we can simplify our @{ML select_tac} from Page~\pageref{tac:selecttac}
as follows:
*}
ML{*val select_tac' = FIRST' [rtac @{thm conjI}, rtac @{thm impI},
rtac @{thm notI}, rtac @{thm allI}, K all_tac]*}
text {*
Since we like to mimic the behaviour of @{ML select_tac} as closely as possible,
we must include @{ML all_tac} at the end of the list, otherwise the tactic will
fail if no rule applies (we also have to wrap @{ML all_tac} using the
@{ML K}-combinator, because it does not take a subgoal number as argument). You can
test the tactic on the same goals:
*}
lemma shows "A \<and> B" and "A \<longrightarrow> B \<longrightarrow>C" and "\<forall>x. D x" and "E \<Longrightarrow> F"
apply(tactic {* select_tac' 4 *})
apply(tactic {* select_tac' 3 *})
apply(tactic {* select_tac' 2 *})
apply(tactic {* select_tac' 1 *})
txt{* \begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage} *}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
Since such repeated applications of a tactic to the reverse order of
\emph{all} subgoals is quite common, there is the tactic combinator
@{ML ALLGOALS} that simplifies this. Using this combinator you can simply
write: *}
lemma shows "A \<and> B" and "A \<longrightarrow> B \<longrightarrow>C" and "\<forall>x. D x" and "E \<Longrightarrow> F"
apply(tactic {* ALLGOALS select_tac' *})
txt{* \begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage} *}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
Remember that we chose to implement @{ML select_tac'} so that it
always succeeds. This can be potentially very confusing for the user,
for example, in cases where the goal is the form
*}
lemma shows "E \<Longrightarrow> F"
apply(tactic {* select_tac' 1 *})
txt{* \begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage} *}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
In this case no rule applies. The problem for the user is that there is little
chance to see whether or not progress in the proof has been made. By convention
therefore, tactics visible to the user should either change something or fail.
To comply with this convention, we could simply delete the @{ML "K all_tac"}
from the end of the theorem list. As a result @{ML select_tac'} would only
succeed on goals where it can make progress. But for the sake of argument,
let us suppose that this deletion is \emph{not} an option. In such cases, you can
use the combinator @{ML CHANGED} to make sure the subgoal has been changed
by the tactic. Because now
*}
lemma shows "E \<Longrightarrow> F"
apply(tactic {* CHANGED (select_tac' 1) *})(*<*)?(*>*)
txt{* gives the error message:
\begin{isabelle}
@{text "*** empty result sequence -- proof command failed"}\\
@{text "*** At command \"apply\"."}
\end{isabelle}
*}(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
We can further extend @{ML select_tac'} so that it not just applies to the topmost
connective, but also to the ones immediately ``underneath'', i.e.~analyse the goal
completely. For this you can use the tactic combinator @{ML REPEAT}. As an example
suppose the following tactic
*}
ML{*val repeat_xmp = REPEAT (CHANGED (select_tac' 1)) *}
text {* which applied to the proof *}
lemma shows "((\<not>A) \<and> (\<forall>x. B x)) \<and> (C \<longrightarrow> D)"
apply(tactic {* repeat_xmp *})
txt{* produces
\begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage} *}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
Here it is crucial that @{ML select_tac'} is prefixed with @{ML CHANGED},
because otherwise @{ML REPEAT} runs into an infinite loop (it applies the
tactic as long as it succeeds). The function
@{ML REPEAT1} is similar, but runs the tactic at least once (failing if
this is not possible).
If you are after the ``primed'' version of @{ML repeat_xmp} then you
need to implement it as
*}
ML{*val repeat_xmp' = REPEAT o CHANGED o select_tac'*}
text {*
since there are no ``primed'' versions of @{ML REPEAT} and @{ML CHANGED}.
If you look closely at the goal state above, the tactics @{ML repeat_xmp}
and @{ML repeat_xmp'} are not yet quite what we are after: the problem is
that goals 2 and 3 are not analysed. This is because the tactic
is applied repeatedly only to the first subgoal. To analyse also all
resulting subgoals, you can use the tactic combinator @{ML REPEAT_ALL_NEW}.
Suppose the tactic
*}
ML{*val repeat_all_new_xmp = REPEAT_ALL_NEW (CHANGED o select_tac')*}
text {*
you see that the following goal
*}
lemma shows "((\<not>A) \<and> (\<forall>x. B x)) \<and> (C \<longrightarrow> D)"
apply(tactic {* repeat_all_new_xmp 1 *})
txt{* \begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage} *}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
is completely analysed according to the theorems we chose to
include in @{ML select_tac'}.
Recall that tactics produce a lazy sequence of successor goal states. These
states can be explored using the command \isacommand{back}. For example
*}
lemma "\<lbrakk>P1 \<or> Q1; P2 \<or> Q2\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> R"
apply(tactic {* etac @{thm disjE} 1 *})
txt{* applies the rule to the first assumption yielding the goal state:\smallskip
\begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage}\smallskip
After typing
*}
(*<*)
oops
lemma "\<lbrakk>P1 \<or> Q1; P2 \<or> Q2\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> R"
apply(tactic {* etac @{thm disjE} 1 *})
(*>*)
back
txt{* the rule now applies to the second assumption.\smallskip
\begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage} *}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
Sometimes this leads to confusing behaviour of tactics and also has
the potential to explode the search space for tactics.
These problems can be avoided by prefixing the tactic with the tactic
combinator @{ML DETERM}.
*}
lemma "\<lbrakk>P1 \<or> Q1; P2 \<or> Q2\<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> R"
apply(tactic {* DETERM (etac @{thm disjE} 1) *})
txt {*\begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
@{subgoals [display]}
\end{minipage} *}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
This combinator will prune the search space to just the first successful application.
Attempting to apply \isacommand{back} in this goal states gives the
error message:
\begin{isabelle}
@{text "*** back: no alternatives"}\\
@{text "*** At command \"back\"."}
\end{isabelle}
\begin{readmore}
Most tactic combinators described in this section are defined in @{ML_file "Pure/tctical.ML"}.
\end{readmore}
*}
section {* Rewriting and Simplifier Tactics *}
text {*
@{ML rewrite_goals_tac}
@{ML ObjectLogic.full_atomize_tac}
@{ML ObjectLogic.rulify_tac}
*}
section {* Simprocs *}
text {*
In Isabelle you can also implement custom simplification procedures, called
\emph{simprocs}. Simprocs can be triggered on a specified term-pattern and
rewrite a term according to theorem. They are useful in cases where
a rewriting rule must be produced on ``demand'' or when rewriting by
simplification is too unpredictable and potentially loops.
To see how simprocs work, let us first write a simproc that just prints out
the pattern that triggers it and otherwise does nothing. For this
you can use the function:
*}
ML %linenosgray{*fun fail_sp_aux simpset redex =
let
val ctxt = Simplifier.the_context simpset
val _ = warning ("The redex: " ^ (str_of_cterm ctxt redex))
in
NONE
end*}
text {*
This function takes a simpset and a redex (a @{ML_type cterm}) as
argument. In Lines 3 and~4, we first extract the context from the given
simpset and then print out a message containing the redex. The function
returns @{ML NONE} (standing for an optional @{ML_type thm}) since at the
moment we are \emph{not} interested in actually rewriting anything. We want
that the simproc is triggered by the pattern @{term "Suc n"}. This can be
done by adding the simproc to the current simproc as follows
*}
simproc_setup fail_sp ("Suc n") = {* K fail_sp_aux *}
text {*
where the second argument specifies the pattern and the right-hand side
contains the code of the simproc (we have to use @{ML K} since we ignoring
an argument about morphisms\footnote{FIXME: what does the morphism do?}).
After this, the simplifier is aware of the simproc and you can test whether
it fires on the lemma:
*}
lemma shows "Suc 0 = 1"
apply(simp)
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
This will print out the message twice: once for the left-hand side and
once for the right-hand side. The reason is that during simplification the
simplifier will at some point reduce the term @{term "1::nat"} to @{term "Suc
0"}, and then the simproc ``fires'' also on that term.
We can add or delete the simproc from the current simpset by the usual
\isacommand{declare}-statement. For example the simproc will be deleted
if you type:
*}
declare [[simproc del: fail_sp]]
text {*
If you want to see what happens with just \emph{this} simproc, without any
interference from other rewrite rules, you can call @{text fail_sp}
as follows:
*}
lemma shows "Suc 0 = 1"
apply(tactic {* simp_tac (HOL_ss addsimprocs [@{simproc fail_sp}]) 1*})
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
(FIXME: should one use HOL-basic-ss or HOL-ss?)
Now the message shows up only once since the term @{term "1::nat"} is
left unchanged.
Setting up a simproc using the command \isacommand{setup\_simproc} will
always add automatically the simproc to the current simpset. If you do not
want this, then you have to use a slightly different method for setting
up the simproc. First the function @{ML fail_sp_aux} needs to be modified
to
*}
ML{*fun fail_sp_aux' simpset redex =
let
val ctxt = Simplifier.the_context simpset
val _ = warning ("The redex: " ^ (Syntax.string_of_term ctxt redex))
in
NONE
end*}
text {*
Here the redex is given as a @{ML_type term}, instead of a @{ML_type cterm}
(therefore we printing it out using the function @{ML string_of_term in Syntax}).
We can turn this function into a proper simproc using
*}
ML{*val fail_sp' =
let
val thy = @{theory}
val pat = [@{term "Suc n"}]
in
Simplifier.simproc_i thy "fail_sp'" pat (K fail_sp_aux')
end*}
text {*
Here the pattern is given as @{ML_type term} (instead of @{ML_type cterm}).
The function also takes a list of patterns that can trigger the simproc.
It might be interesting to notice that simprocs are applied from inside
to outside and from left to right. You can see this in the proof
*}
lemma shows "Suc (Suc 0) = (Suc 1)"
apply(tactic {* simp_tac (HOL_ss addsimprocs [fail_sp']) 1*})
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
since @{ML fail_sp'} prints out the sequence
@{text [display]
"> Suc 0
> Suc (Suc 0)
> Suc 1"}
To see how a simproc applies a theorem, let us implement a simproc that
rewrites terms according to the equation:
*}
lemma plus_one:
shows "Suc n \<equiv> n + 1" by simp
text {*
Simprocs expect that the given equation is a meta-equation, however the
equation can contain preconditions (the simproc then will only fire if the
preconditions can be solved). To see one has relatively precise control over
the rewriting with simprocs, let us further assume we want that the simproc
only rewrites terms ``greater'' than @{term "Suc 0"}. For this we can write
*}
ML{*fun plus_one_sp_aux ss redex =
case redex of
@{term "Suc 0"} => NONE
| _ => SOME @{thm plus_one}*}
text {*
and set up the simproc as follows.
*}
ML{*val plus_one_sp =
let
val thy = @{theory}
val pat = [@{term "Suc n"}]
in
Simplifier.simproc_i thy "sproc +1" pat (K plus_one_sp_aux)
end*}
text {*
Now the simproc is set up xso that it is triggered by terms
of the form @{term "Suc n"}, but inside the simproc we only produce
a theorem if the term is not @{term "Suc 0"}. The result you can see
in the following proof
*}
lemma shows "P (Suc (Suc (Suc 0))) (Suc 0)"
apply(tactic {* simp_tac (HOL_ss addsimprocs [plus_one_sp]) 1*})
txt{*
where the simproc produces the goal state
@{subgoals[display]}
*}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
As usual with simplification you have to be careful with looping: you already have
one @{ML plus_one_sp}, if you apply if with the default simpset (because
the default simpset contains a rule which just undoes the rewriting
@{ML plus_one_sp}).
Let us next implement a simproc that replaces terms of the form @{term "Suc n"}
with the number @{text n} increase by one. First we implement a function that
takes a term and produces the corresponding integer value, if it can.
*}
ML{*fun dest_suc_trm ((Const (@{const_name "Suc"}, _)) $ t) = 1 + dest_suc_trm t
| dest_suc_trm t = snd (HOLogic.dest_number t)*}
text {*
It uses the library function @{ML dest_number in HOLogic} that transforms
(Isabelle) terms, like @{term "0::nat"}, @{term "1::nat"}, @{term "2::nat"} and so
on, into integer values. This function raises the exception @{ML TERM}, if
the term is not a number. The next function expects a pair consisting of a term
@{text t} (containing @{term Suc}s) and the corresponding integer value @{text n}.
*}
ML %linenosgray{*fun get_thm ctxt (t, n) =
let
val num = HOLogic.mk_number @{typ "nat"} n
val goal = HOLogic.mk_Trueprop (HOLogic.mk_eq (t,num))
in
mk_meta_eq (Goal.prove ctxt [] [] goal (K (simp_tac @{simpset} 1)))
end*}
text {*
(FIXME: is @{text "@{simpset}"} kosher here? Otherwise the following will loop.)
From the integer value it generates the corresponding number term, called
@{text num} (Line 3), and then generates the equation @{text "t = num"} (Line 4),
which it proves by simplification in Line 6. The function @{ML mk_meta_eq}
at the outside of the proof just transforms the equality into a meta-equality.
Both functions can be stringed together in the function that produces the
actual theorem for the simproc.
*}
ML{*fun nat_number_sp_aux ss t =
let
val ctxt = Simplifier.the_context ss
in
SOME (get_thm ctxt (t, dest_suc_trm t))
handle TERM _ => NONE
end*}
text {*
This function uses the fact that @{ML dest_suc_trm} might throw an exception
@{ML TERM}. In this case there is nothing that can be rewritten and therefore no
theorem is produced (i.e.~the function returns @{ML NONE}). To try out the simproc
on an example, you can set it up as follows:
*}
ML{*val nat_number_sp =
let
val thy = @{theory}
val pat = [@{term "Suc n"}]
in
Simplifier.simproc_i thy "nat_number" pat (K nat_number_sp_aux)
end*}
text {*
Now in the lemma
*}
lemma "P (Suc (Suc 2)) (Suc 99) (0::nat) (Suc 4 + Suc 0) (Suc (0 + 0))"
apply(tactic {* simp_tac (HOL_ss addsimprocs [nat_number_sp]) 1*})
txt {*
you obtain the more legible goal state
@{subgoals [display]}
*}
(*<*)oops(*>*)
text {*
where the simproc rewrites all @{term "Suc"}s except in the last arguments. There it cannot
rewrite anything, because it does not know how to transform the term @{term "Suc (0 + 0)"}
into a number. To solve this problem have a look at the next exercise.
\begin{exercise}\label{ex:addsimproc}
Write a simproc that replaces terms of the form @{term "t\<^isub>1 + t\<^isub>2"} by their
result. You can assume the terms are ``proper'' numbers, that is of the form
@{term "0::nat"}, @{term "1::nat"}, @{term "2::nat"} and so on.
\end{exercise}
(FIXME: We did not do anything with morphisms. Anything interesting
one can say about them?)
*}
section {* Structured Proofs *}
text {* TBD *}
lemma True
proof
{
fix A B C
assume r: "A & B \<Longrightarrow> C"
assume A B
then have "A & B" ..
then have C by (rule r)
}
{
fix A B C
assume r: "A & B \<Longrightarrow> C"
assume A B
note conjI [OF this]
note r [OF this]
}
oops
ML {* fun prop ctxt s =
Thm.cterm_of (ProofContext.theory_of ctxt) (Syntax.read_prop ctxt s) *}
ML {*
val ctxt0 = @{context};
val ctxt = ctxt0;
val (_, ctxt) = Variable.add_fixes ["A", "B", "C"] ctxt;
val ([r], ctxt) = Assumption.add_assumes [prop ctxt "A & B \<Longrightarrow> C"] ctxt;
val (this, ctxt) = Assumption.add_assumes [prop ctxt "A", prop ctxt "B"] ctxt;
val this = [@{thm conjI} OF this];
val this = r OF this;
val this = Assumption.export false ctxt ctxt0 this
val this = Variable.export ctxt ctxt0 [this]
*}
end