CookBook/Package/Ind_Prelims.thy
changeset 189 069d525f8f1d
parent 188 8939b8fd8603
child 190 ca0ac2e75f6d
--- a/CookBook/Package/Ind_Prelims.thy	Wed Mar 18 23:52:51 2009 +0100
+++ /dev/null	Thu Jan 01 00:00:00 1970 +0000
@@ -1,352 +0,0 @@
-theory Ind_Prelims
-imports Main LaTeXsugar"../Base" Simple_Inductive_Package
-begin
-
-section{* Preliminaries *}
-  
-text {*
-  The user will just give a specification of an inductive predicate and
-  expects from the package to produce a convenient reasoning
-  infrastructure. This infrastructure needs to be derived from the definition
-  that correspond to the specified predicate. This will roughly mean that the
-  package has three main parts, namely:
-
-
-  \begin{itemize}
-  \item parsing the specification and typing the parsed input,
-  \item making the definitions and deriving the reasoning infrastructure, and
-  \item storing the results in the theory. 
-  \end{itemize}
-
-  Before we start with explaining all parts, let us first give three examples
-  showing how to define inductive predicates by hand and then also how to
-  prove by hand important properties about them. From these examples, we will
-  figure out a general method for defining inductive predicates.  The aim in
-  this section is \emph{not} to write proofs that are as beautiful as
-  possible, but as close as possible to the ML-code we will develop in later
-  sections.
-
-
-  We first consider the transitive closure of a relation @{text R}. It is
-  an inductive predicate characterised by the two introduction rules:
-
-  \begin{center}\small
-  @{prop[mode=Axiom] "trcl R x x"} \hspace{5mm}
-  @{prop[mode=Rule] "R x y \<Longrightarrow> trcl R y z \<Longrightarrow> trcl R x z"}
-  \end{center}
-
-  In Isabelle, the user will state for @{term trcl\<iota>} the specification:
-*}
-
-simple_inductive
-  trcl\<iota> :: "('a \<Rightarrow> 'a \<Rightarrow> bool) \<Rightarrow> 'a \<Rightarrow> 'a \<Rightarrow> bool"
-where
-  base: "trcl\<iota> R x x"
-| step: "trcl\<iota> R x y \<Longrightarrow> R y z \<Longrightarrow> trcl\<iota> R x z"
-
-text {*
-  As said above the package has to make an appropriate definition and provide
-  lemmas to reason about the predicate @{term trcl\<iota>}. Since an inductively
-  defined predicate is the least predicate closed under a collection of
-  introduction rules, the predicate @{text "trcl R x y"} can be defined so
-  that it holds if and only if @{text "P x y"} holds for every predicate
-  @{text P} closed under the rules above. This gives rise to the definition
-*}
-
-definition "trcl \<equiv> 
-     \<lambda>R x y. \<forall>P. (\<forall>x. P x x) 
-                  \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>x y z. R x y \<longrightarrow> P y z \<longrightarrow> P x z) \<longrightarrow> P x y"
-
-text {*
-  where we quantify over the predicate @{text P}. We have to use the
-  object implication @{text "\<longrightarrow>"} and object quantification @{text "\<forall>"} for
-  stating this definition (there is no other way for definitions in
-  HOL). However, the introduction rules and induction principles 
-  should use the meta-connectives since they simplify the
-  reasoning for the user.
-
-  With this definition, the proof of the induction principle for @{term trcl}
-  is almost immediate. It suffices to convert all the meta-level
-  connectives in the lemma to object-level connectives using the
-  proof method @{text atomize} (Line 4), expand the definition of @{term trcl}
-  (Line 5 and 6), eliminate the universal quantifier contained in it (Line~7),
-  and then solve the goal by assumption (Line 8).
-
-*}
-
-lemma %linenos trcl_induct:
-  assumes "trcl R x y"
-  shows "(\<And>x. P x x) \<Longrightarrow> (\<And>x y z. R x y \<Longrightarrow> P y z \<Longrightarrow> P x z) \<Longrightarrow> P x y"
-apply(atomize (full))
-apply(cut_tac prems)
-apply(unfold trcl_def)
-apply(drule spec[where x=P])
-apply(assumption)
-done
-
-text {*
-  The proofs for the introduction rules are slightly more complicated. 
-  For the first one, we need to prove the following lemma:
-*}
-
-lemma %linenos trcl_base: 
-  shows "trcl R x x"
-apply(unfold trcl_def)
-apply(rule allI impI)+
-apply(drule spec)
-apply(assumption)
-done
-
-text {*
-  We again unfold first the definition and apply introduction rules 
-  for @{text "\<forall>"} and @{text "\<longrightarrow>"} as often as possible (Lines 3 and 4).
-  We then end up in the goal state:
-*}
-
-(*<*)lemma "trcl R x x"
-apply (unfold trcl_def)
-apply (rule allI impI)+(*>*)
-txt {* @{subgoals [display]} *}
-(*<*)oops(*>*)
-
-text {*
-  The two assumptions correspond to the introduction rules. Thus, all we have
-  to do is to eliminate the universal quantifier in front of the first
-  assumption (Line 5), and then solve the goal by assumption (Line 6).
-*}
-
-text {*
-  Next we have to show that the second introduction rule also follows from the
-  definition.  Since this rule has premises, the proof is a bit more
-  involved. After unfolding the definitions and applying the introduction
-  rules for @{text "\<forall>"} and @{text "\<longrightarrow>"}
-*}
-
-lemma trcl_step: 
-  shows "R x y \<Longrightarrow> trcl R y z \<Longrightarrow> trcl R x z"
-apply (unfold trcl_def)
-apply (rule allI impI)+
-
-txt {* 
-  we obtain the goal state
-
-  @{subgoals [display]} 
-
-  To see better where we are, let us explicitly name the assumptions 
-  by starting a subproof.
-*}
-
-proof -
-  case (goal1 P)
-  have p1: "R x y" by fact
-  have p2: "\<forall>P. (\<forall>x. P x x) 
-                  \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>x y z. R x y \<longrightarrow> P y z \<longrightarrow> P x z) \<longrightarrow> P y z" by fact
-  have r1: "\<forall>x. P x x" by fact
-  have r2: "\<forall>x y z. R x y \<longrightarrow> P y z \<longrightarrow> P x z" by fact
-  show "P x z"
-  
-txt {*
-  The assumptions @{text "p1"} and @{text "p2"} correspond to the premises of
-  the second introduction rule; the assumptions @{text "r1"} and @{text "r2"}
-  correspond to the introduction rules. We apply @{text "r2"} to the goal
-  @{term "P x z"}. In order for the assumption to be applicable as a rule, we
-  have to eliminate the universal quantifier and turn the object-level
-  implications into meta-level ones. This can be accomplished using the @{text
-  rule_format} attribute. So we continue the proof with:
-
-*}
-
-    apply (rule r2[rule_format])
-
-txt {*
-  This gives us two new subgoals
-
-  @{subgoals [display]} 
-
-  which can be solved using assumptions @{text p1} and @{text p2}. The latter
-  involves a quantifier and implications that have to be eliminated before it
-  can be applied. To avoid potential problems with higher-order unification,
-  we explicitly instantiate the quantifier to @{text "P"} and also match
-  explicitly the implications with @{text "r1"} and @{text "r2"}. This gives
-  the proof:
-*}
-
-    apply(rule p1)
-    apply(rule p2[THEN spec[where x=P], THEN mp, THEN mp, OF r1, OF r2])
-    done
-qed
-
-text {*
-  Now we are done. It might be surprising that we are not using the automatic
-  tactics available in Isabelle for proving this lemmas. After all @{text
-  "blast"} would easily dispense of it.
-*}
-
-lemma trcl_step_blast: 
-  shows "R x y \<Longrightarrow> trcl R y z \<Longrightarrow> trcl R x z"
-apply(unfold trcl_def)
-apply(blast)
-done
-
-text {*
-  Experience has shown that it is generally a bad idea to rely heavily on
-  @{text blast}, @{text auto} and the like in automated proofs. The reason is
-  that you do not have precise control over them (the user can, for example,
-  declare new intro- or simplification rules that can throw automatic tactics
-  off course) and also it is very hard to debug proofs involving automatic
-  tactics whenever something goes wrong. Therefore if possible, automatic 
-  tactics should be avoided or sufficiently constrained.
-
-  The method of defining inductive predicates by impredicative quantification
-  also generalises to mutually inductive predicates. The next example defines
-  the predicates @{text even} and @{text odd} characterised by the following
-  rules:
- 
-  \begin{center}\small
-  @{prop[mode=Axiom] "even (0::nat)"} \hspace{5mm}
-  @{prop[mode=Rule] "odd n \<Longrightarrow> even (Suc n)"} \hspace{5mm}
-  @{prop[mode=Rule] "even n \<Longrightarrow> odd (Suc n)"}
-  \end{center}
-  
-  The user will state for this inductive definition the specification:
-*}
-
-simple_inductive
-  even and odd
-where
-  even0: "even 0"
-| evenS: "odd n \<Longrightarrow> even (Suc n)"
-| oddS: "even n \<Longrightarrow> odd (Suc n)"
-
-text {*
-  Since the predicates @{term even} and @{term odd} are mutually inductive, each 
-  corresponding definition must quantify over both predicates (we name them 
-  below @{text "P"} and @{text "Q"}).
-*}
-
-definition "even\<iota> \<equiv> 
-  \<lambda>n. \<forall>P Q. P 0 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. Q m \<longrightarrow> P (Suc m)) 
-                 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. P m \<longrightarrow> Q (Suc m)) \<longrightarrow> P n"
-
-definition "odd\<iota> \<equiv>
-  \<lambda>n. \<forall>P Q. P 0 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. Q m \<longrightarrow> P (Suc m)) 
-                 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. P m \<longrightarrow> Q (Suc m)) \<longrightarrow> Q n"
-
-text {*
-  For proving the induction principles, we use exactly the same technique 
-  as in the transitive closure example, namely:
-*}
-
-lemma even_induct:
-  assumes "even n"
-  shows "P 0 \<Longrightarrow> 
-             (\<And>m. Q m \<Longrightarrow> P (Suc m)) \<Longrightarrow> (\<And>m. P m \<Longrightarrow> Q (Suc m)) \<Longrightarrow> P n"
-apply(atomize (full))
-apply(cut_tac prems)
-apply(unfold even_def)
-apply(drule spec[where x=P])
-apply(drule spec[where x=Q])
-apply(assumption)
-done
-
-text {*
-  The only difference with the proof @{text "trcl_induct"} is that we have to
-  instantiate here two universal quantifiers.  We omit the other induction
-  principle that has @{term "Q n"} as conclusion.  The proofs of the
-  introduction rules are also very similar to the ones in the @{text
-  "trcl"}-example. We only show the proof of the second introduction rule.
-
-*}
-
-lemma %linenos evenS: 
-  shows "odd m \<Longrightarrow> even (Suc m)"
-apply (unfold odd_def even_def)
-apply (rule allI impI)+
-proof -
-  case (goal1 P Q)
-  have p1: "\<forall>P Q. P 0 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. Q m \<longrightarrow> P (Suc m)) 
-                             \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. P m \<longrightarrow> Q (Suc m)) \<longrightarrow> Q m" by fact
-  have r1: "P 0" by fact
-  have r2: "\<forall>m. Q m \<longrightarrow> P (Suc m)" by fact
-  have r3: "\<forall>m. P m \<longrightarrow> Q (Suc m)" by fact
-  show "P (Suc m)"
-    apply(rule r2[rule_format])
-    apply(rule p1[THEN spec[where x=P], THEN spec[where x=Q],
-	           THEN mp, THEN mp, THEN mp, OF r1, OF r2, OF r3])
-    done
-qed
-
-text {*
-  In Line 13, we apply the assumption @{text "r2"} (since we prove the second
-  introduction rule). In Lines 14 and 15 we apply assumption @{text "p1"} (if
-  the second introduction rule had more premises we have to do that for all
-  of them). In order for this assumption to be applicable, the quantifiers
-  need to be instantiated and then also the implications need to be resolved
-  with the other rules.
-
-
-  As a final example, we define the accessible part of a relation @{text R} characterised 
-  by the introduction rule
-  
-  \begin{center}\small
-  \mbox{\inferrule{@{term "\<And>y. R y x \<Longrightarrow> accpart R y"}}{@{term "accpart R x"}}}
-  \end{center}
-
-  whose premise involves a universal quantifier and an implication. The
-  definition of @{text accpart} is:
-*}
-
-definition "accpart \<equiv> \<lambda>R x. \<forall>P. (\<forall>x. (\<forall>y. R y x \<longrightarrow> P y) \<longrightarrow> P x) \<longrightarrow> P x"
-
-text {*
-  The proof of the induction principle is again straightforward.
-*}
-
-lemma accpart_induct:
-  assumes "accpart R x"
-  shows "(\<And>x. (\<And>y. R y x \<Longrightarrow> P y) \<Longrightarrow> P x) \<Longrightarrow> P x"
-apply(atomize (full))
-apply(cut_tac prems)
-apply(unfold accpart_def)
-apply(drule spec[where x=P])
-apply(assumption)
-done
-
-text {*
-  Proving the introduction rule is a little more complicated, because the quantifier
-  and the implication in the premise. The proof is as follows.
-*}
-
-lemma %linenos accpartI: 
-  shows "(\<And>y. R y x \<Longrightarrow> accpart R y) \<Longrightarrow> accpart R x"
-apply (unfold accpart_def)
-apply (rule allI impI)+
-proof -
-  case (goal1 P)
-  have p1: "\<And>y. R y x \<Longrightarrow> 
-                   (\<forall>P. (\<forall>x. (\<forall>y. R y x \<longrightarrow> P y) \<longrightarrow> P x) \<longrightarrow> P y)" by fact
-  have r1: "\<forall>x. (\<forall>y. R y x \<longrightarrow> P y) \<longrightarrow> P x" by fact
-  show "P x"
-    apply(rule r1[rule_format])
-    proof -
-      case (goal1 y)
-      have r1_prem: "R y x" by fact
-      show "P y"
-	apply(rule p1[OF r1_prem, THEN spec[where x=P], THEN mp, OF r1])
-      done
-  qed
-qed
-
-text {*
-  In Line 11, applying the assumption @{text "r1"} generates a goal state with
-  the new local assumption @{term "R y x"}, named @{text "r1_prem"} in the 
-  proof above (Line 14). This local assumption is used to solve
-  the goal @{term "P y"} with the help of assumption @{text "p1"}.
-
-  The point of these examples is to get a feeling what the automatic proofs 
-  should do in order to solve all inductive definitions we throw at them.
-  This is usually the first step in writing a package. We next explain
-  the parsing and typing part of the package.
-
-*}
-(*<*)end(*>*)