author | Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de> |
Wed, 17 Dec 2008 05:08:33 +0000 | |
changeset 59 | b5914f3c643c |
parent 38 | e21b2f888fa2 |
child 88 | ebbd0dd008c8 |
permissions | -rw-r--r-- |
32 | 1 |
theory Ind_Examples |
2 |
imports Main |
|
3 |
begin |
|
4 |
||
5 |
section{* Examples of inductive definitions *} |
|
6 |
||
7 |
text {* |
|
8 |
\label{sec:ind-examples} |
|
9 |
In this section, we will give three examples showing how to define inductive |
|
10 |
predicates by hand and prove characteristic properties such as introduction |
|
11 |
rules and an induction rule. From these examples, we will then figure out a |
|
12 |
general method for defining inductive predicates, which will be described in |
|
13 |
\S\ref{sec:ind-general-method}. This description will serve as a basis for the |
|
14 |
actual implementation to be developed in \S\ref{sec:ind-interface} -- \S\ref{sec:ind-proofs}. |
|
15 |
It should be noted that our aim in this section is not to write proofs that |
|
16 |
are as beautiful as possible, but as close as possible to the ML code producing |
|
17 |
the proofs that we will develop later. |
|
18 |
As a first example, we consider the \emph{transitive closure} @{text "trcl R"} |
|
19 |
of a relation @{text R}. It is characterized by the following |
|
20 |
two introduction rules |
|
21 |
\[ |
|
22 |
\begin{array}{l} |
|
23 |
@{term "trcl R x x"} \\ |
|
24 |
@{term [mode=no_brackets] "R x y \<Longrightarrow> trcl R y z \<Longrightarrow> trcl R x z"} |
|
25 |
\end{array} |
|
26 |
\] |
|
27 |
Note that the @{text trcl} predicate has two different kinds of parameters: the |
|
28 |
first parameter @{text R} stays \emph{fixed} throughout the definition, whereas |
|
29 |
the second and third parameter changes in the ``recursive call''. |
|
30 |
Since an inductively defined predicate is the \emph{least} predicate closed under |
|
31 |
a collection of introduction rules, we define the predicate @{text "trcl R x y"} in |
|
32 |
such a way that it holds if and only if @{text "P x y"} holds for every predicate |
|
33 |
@{text P} closed under the above rules. This gives rise to a definition containing |
|
34 |
a universal quantifier over the predicate @{text P}: |
|
35 |
*} |
|
36 |
||
37 |
definition "trcl \<equiv> \<lambda>R x y. |
|
38 |
\<forall>P. (\<forall>x. P x x) \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>x y z. R x y \<longrightarrow> P y z \<longrightarrow> P x z) \<longrightarrow> P x y" |
|
39 |
||
40 |
text {* |
|
41 |
\noindent |
|
42 |
Since the predicate @{term "trcl R x y"} yields an element of the type of object |
|
43 |
level truth values @{text bool}, the meta-level implications @{text "\<Longrightarrow>"} in the |
|
44 |
above introduction rules have to be converted to object-level implications |
|
45 |
@{text "\<longrightarrow>"}. Moreover, we use object-level universal quantifiers @{text "\<forall>"} |
|
46 |
rather than meta-level universal quantifiers @{text "\<And>"} for quantifying over |
|
47 |
the variable parameters of the introduction rules. Isabelle already offers some |
|
48 |
infrastructure for converting between meta-level and object-level connectives, |
|
49 |
which we will use later on. |
|
50 |
||
51 |
With this definition of the transitive closure, the proof of the (weak) induction |
|
52 |
theorem is almost immediate. It suffices to convert all the meta-level connectives |
|
53 |
in the induction rule to object-level connectives using the @{text atomize} proof |
|
54 |
method, expand the definition of @{text trcl}, eliminate the universal quantifier |
|
55 |
contained in it, and then solve the goal by assumption. |
|
56 |
*} |
|
57 |
||
58 |
lemma trcl_induct: |
|
59 |
assumes trcl: "trcl R x y" |
|
60 |
shows "(\<And>x. P x x) \<Longrightarrow> (\<And>x y z. R x y \<Longrightarrow> P y z \<Longrightarrow> P x z) \<Longrightarrow> P x y" |
|
61 |
apply (atomize (full)) |
|
62 |
apply (cut_tac trcl) |
|
63 |
apply (unfold trcl_def) |
|
64 |
apply (drule spec [where x=P]) |
|
65 |
apply assumption |
|
66 |
done |
|
67 |
(*<*) |
|
68 |
lemma "trcl R x x" |
|
69 |
apply (unfold trcl_def) |
|
70 |
apply (rule allI impI)+ |
|
71 |
(*>*) |
|
72 |
txt {* |
|
73 |
\noindent |
|
74 |
The above induction rule is \emph{weak} in the sense that the induction step may |
|
75 |
only be proved using the assumptions @{term "R x y"} and @{term "P y z"}, but not |
|
76 |
using the additional assumption \mbox{@{term "trcl R y z"}}. A stronger induction rule |
|
77 |
containing this additional assumption can be derived from the weaker one with the |
|
78 |
help of the introduction rules for @{text trcl}. |
|
79 |
||
80 |
We now turn to the proofs of the introduction rules, which are slightly more complicated. |
|
81 |
In order to prove the first introduction rule, we again unfold the definition and |
|
82 |
then apply the introdution rules for @{text "\<forall>"} and @{text "\<longrightarrow>"} as often as possible. |
|
83 |
We then end up in a proof state of the following form: |
|
84 |
@{subgoals [display]} |
|
85 |
The two assumptions correspond to the introduction rules, where @{term "trcl R"} has been |
|
86 |
replaced by @{term "P"}. Thus, all we have to do is to eliminate the universal quantifier |
|
87 |
in front of the first assumption, and then solve the goal by assumption: |
|
88 |
*} |
|
89 |
(*<*)oops(*>*) |
|
90 |
lemma trcl_base: "trcl R x x" |
|
91 |
apply (unfold trcl_def) |
|
92 |
apply (rule allI impI)+ |
|
93 |
apply (drule spec) |
|
94 |
apply assumption |
|
95 |
done |
|
96 |
(*<*) |
|
97 |
lemma "R x y \<Longrightarrow> trcl R y z \<Longrightarrow> trcl R x z" |
|
98 |
apply (unfold trcl_def) |
|
99 |
apply (rule allI impI)+ |
|
100 |
(*>*) |
|
101 |
txt {* |
|
102 |
\noindent |
|
103 |
Since the second introduction rule has premises, its proof is not as easy as the previous |
|
104 |
one. After unfolding the definitions and applying the introduction rules for @{text "\<forall>"} |
|
105 |
and @{text "\<longrightarrow>"}, we get the proof state |
|
106 |
@{subgoals [display]} |
|
107 |
The third and fourth assumption corresponds to the first and second introduction rule, |
|
108 |
respectively, whereas the first and second assumption corresponds to the premises of |
|
109 |
the introduction rule. Since we want to prove the second introduction rule, we apply |
|
110 |
the fourth assumption to the goal @{term "P x z"}. In order for the assumption to |
|
111 |
be applicable, we have to eliminate the universal quantifiers and turn the object-level |
|
112 |
implications into meta-level ones. This can be accomplished using the @{text rule_format} |
|
113 |
attribute. Applying the assumption produces two new subgoals, which can be solved using |
|
114 |
the first and second assumption. The second assumption again involves a quantifier and |
|
115 |
implications that have to be eliminated before it can be applied. To avoid problems |
|
116 |
with higher order unification, it is advisable to provide an instantiation for the |
|
117 |
universally quantified predicate variable in the assumption. |
|
118 |
*} |
|
119 |
(*<*)oops(*>*) |
|
120 |
lemma trcl_step: "R x y \<Longrightarrow> trcl R y z \<Longrightarrow> trcl R x z" |
|
121 |
apply (unfold trcl_def) |
|
122 |
apply (rule allI impI)+ |
|
123 |
proof - |
|
124 |
case goal1 |
|
125 |
show ?case |
|
126 |
apply (rule goal1(4) [rule_format]) |
|
127 |
apply (rule goal1(1)) |
|
128 |
apply (rule goal1(2) [THEN spec [where x=P], THEN mp, THEN mp, |
|
129 |
OF goal1(3-4)]) |
|
130 |
done |
|
131 |
qed |
|
132 |
||
133 |
text {* |
|
134 |
\noindent |
|
135 |
This method of defining inductive predicates easily generalizes to mutually inductive |
|
136 |
predicates, like the predicates @{text even} and @{text odd} characterized by the |
|
137 |
following introduction rules: |
|
138 |
\[ |
|
139 |
\begin{array}{l} |
|
140 |
@{term "even (0::nat)"} \\ |
|
141 |
@{term "odd m \<Longrightarrow> even (Suc m)"} \\ |
|
142 |
@{term "even m \<Longrightarrow> odd (Suc m)"} |
|
143 |
\end{array} |
|
144 |
\] |
|
145 |
Since the predicates are mutually inductive, each of the definitions contain two |
|
146 |
quantifiers over the predicates @{text P} and @{text Q}. |
|
147 |
*} |
|
148 |
||
149 |
definition "even \<equiv> \<lambda>n. |
|
150 |
\<forall>P Q. P 0 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. Q m \<longrightarrow> P (Suc m)) \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. P m \<longrightarrow> Q (Suc m)) \<longrightarrow> P n" |
|
151 |
||
152 |
definition "odd \<equiv> \<lambda>n. |
|
153 |
\<forall>P Q. P 0 \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. Q m \<longrightarrow> P (Suc m)) \<longrightarrow> (\<forall>m. P m \<longrightarrow> Q (Suc m)) \<longrightarrow> Q n" |
|
154 |
||
155 |
text {* |
|
156 |
\noindent |
|
157 |
For proving the induction rule, we use exactly the same technique as in the transitive |
|
158 |
closure example: |
|
159 |
*} |
|
160 |
||
161 |
lemma even_induct: |
|
162 |
assumes even: "even n" |
|
38
e21b2f888fa2
added a preliminary section about parsing
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
32
diff
changeset
|
163 |
shows "P 0 \<Longrightarrow> |
e21b2f888fa2
added a preliminary section about parsing
Christian Urban <urbanc@in.tum.de>
parents:
32
diff
changeset
|
164 |
(\<And>m. Q m \<Longrightarrow> P (Suc m)) \<Longrightarrow> (\<And>m. P m \<Longrightarrow> Q (Suc m)) \<Longrightarrow> P n" |
32 | 165 |
apply (atomize (full)) |
166 |
apply (cut_tac even) |
|
167 |
apply (unfold even_def) |
|
168 |
apply (drule spec [where x=P]) |
|
169 |
apply (drule spec [where x=Q]) |
|
170 |
apply assumption |
|
171 |
done |
|
172 |
||
173 |
text {* |
|
174 |
\noindent |
|
175 |
A similar induction rule having @{term "Q n"} as a conclusion can be proved for |
|
176 |
the @{text odd} predicate. |
|
177 |
The proofs of the introduction rules are also very similar to the ones in the |
|
178 |
previous example. We only show the proof of the second introduction rule, |
|
179 |
since it is almost the same as the one for the third introduction rule, |
|
180 |
and the proof of the first rule is trivial. |
|
181 |
*} |
|
182 |
||
183 |
lemma evenS: "odd m \<Longrightarrow> even (Suc m)" |
|
184 |
apply (unfold odd_def even_def) |
|
185 |
apply (rule allI impI)+ |
|
186 |
proof - |
|
187 |
case goal1 |
|
188 |
show ?case |
|
189 |
apply (rule goal1(3) [rule_format]) |
|
190 |
apply (rule goal1(1) [THEN spec [where x=P], THEN spec [where x=Q], |
|
191 |
THEN mp, THEN mp, THEN mp, OF goal1(2-4)]) |
|
192 |
done |
|
193 |
qed |
|
194 |
(*<*) |
|
195 |
lemma even0: "even 0" |
|
196 |
apply (unfold even_def) |
|
197 |
apply (rule allI impI)+ |
|
198 |
apply assumption |
|
199 |
done |
|
200 |
||
201 |
lemma oddS: "even m \<Longrightarrow> odd (Suc m)" |
|
202 |
apply (unfold odd_def even_def) |
|
203 |
apply (rule allI impI)+ |
|
204 |
proof - |
|
205 |
case goal1 |
|
206 |
show ?case |
|
207 |
apply (rule goal1(4) [rule_format]) |
|
208 |
apply (rule goal1(1) [THEN spec [where x=P], THEN spec [where x=Q], |
|
209 |
THEN mp, THEN mp, THEN mp, OF goal1(2-4)]) |
|
210 |
done |
|
211 |
qed |
|
212 |
(*>*) |
|
213 |
text {* |
|
214 |
\noindent |
|
215 |
As a final example, we will consider the definition of the accessible |
|
216 |
part of a relation @{text R} characterized by the introduction rule |
|
217 |
\[ |
|
218 |
@{term "(\<And>y. R y x \<Longrightarrow> accpart R y) \<Longrightarrow> accpart R x"} |
|
219 |
\] |
|
220 |
whose premise involves a universal quantifier and an implication. The |
|
221 |
definition of @{text accpart} is as follows: |
|
222 |
*} |
|
223 |
||
224 |
definition "accpart \<equiv> \<lambda>R x. \<forall>P. (\<forall>x. (\<forall>y. R y x \<longrightarrow> P y) \<longrightarrow> P x) \<longrightarrow> P x" |
|
225 |
||
226 |
text {* |
|
227 |
\noindent |
|
228 |
The proof of the induction theorem is again straightforward: |
|
229 |
*} |
|
230 |
||
231 |
lemma accpart_induct: |
|
232 |
assumes acc: "accpart R x" |
|
233 |
shows "(\<And>x. (\<And>y. R y x \<Longrightarrow> P y) \<Longrightarrow> P x) \<Longrightarrow> P x" |
|
234 |
apply (atomize (full)) |
|
235 |
apply (cut_tac acc) |
|
236 |
apply (unfold accpart_def) |
|
237 |
apply (drule spec [where x=P]) |
|
238 |
apply assumption |
|
239 |
done |
|
240 |
(*<*) |
|
241 |
lemma accpartI: "(\<And>y. R y x \<Longrightarrow> accpart R y) \<Longrightarrow> accpart R x" |
|
242 |
apply (unfold accpart_def) |
|
243 |
apply (rule allI impI)+ |
|
244 |
(*>*) |
|
245 |
txt {* |
|
246 |
\noindent |
|
247 |
Proving the introduction rule is a little more complicated, due to the quantifier |
|
248 |
and the implication in the premise. We first convert the meta-level universal quantifier |
|
249 |
and implication to their object-level counterparts. Unfolding the definition of |
|
250 |
@{text accpart} and applying the introduction rules for @{text "\<forall>"} and @{text "\<longrightarrow>"} |
|
251 |
yields the following proof state: |
|
252 |
@{subgoals [display]} |
|
253 |
Applying the second assumption produces a proof state with the new local assumption |
|
254 |
@{term "R y x"}, which will then be used to solve the goal @{term "P y"} using the |
|
255 |
first assumption. |
|
256 |
*} |
|
257 |
(*<*)oops(*>*) |
|
258 |
lemma accpartI: "(\<And>y. R y x \<Longrightarrow> accpart R y) \<Longrightarrow> accpart R x" |
|
259 |
apply (unfold accpart_def) |
|
260 |
apply (rule allI impI)+ |
|
261 |
proof - |
|
262 |
case goal1 |
|
263 |
note goal1' = this |
|
264 |
show ?case |
|
265 |
apply (rule goal1'(2) [rule_format]) |
|
266 |
proof - |
|
267 |
case goal1 |
|
268 |
show ?case |
|
269 |
apply (rule goal1'(1) [OF goal1, THEN spec [where x=P], |
|
270 |
THEN mp, OF goal1'(2)]) |
|
271 |
done |
|
272 |
qed |
|
273 |
qed |
|
274 |
||
275 |
end |